RELIABILISM COSMIC OPTIMISM Naoki Kitta

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

RELIABILISM COSMIC OPTIMISM Naoki Kitta RELIABILISM AND COSMIC OPTIMISM Situating John Hick in The History of Philosophy of Religion Naoki Kitta, M.A. (The University of Nottingham) M.A. (Hitotsubashi University) Thesis submitted to the University of Nottingham for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy July 2016 Abstract This dissertation aims to rehabilitate the reasonableness of Hick’s religious pluralism by disclosing the deep structure of his philosophical system. To realize this aim, this dissertation will introduce a new philosophical method of reliabilism, which is proposed by Ernest Sosa and emphasizes total balance and historical maturation. As a result of the introduction of reliabilism, Hick’s philosophical system is disclosed to be composed of Hick’s own philosophy of personhood, combined with the philosophies of Wittgenstein, Kant, and Hume. Instead of emphasizing one of them, this dissertation will propose to read these different components of Hick’s philosophical system as forming a total worldview, which are complementary with each other. Also, this dissertation will situate Hick’s philosophy in the history of philosophy of religion (e.g. pre-analytical paradigms of British Idealism and Critical Realism, and analytical paradigms of Logical Positivism, neo-Wittgensteinian philosophy, and Reformed Epistemology). Hick’s project will be discussed as a recovery of a pre- analytical worldview from within analytical contexts. As Hick’s central philosophical works, this dissertation will focus on Faith and Knowledge and An Interpretation of Religion. Faith and Knowledge has not been examined in detail in past literature. But Hick’s arguments about personhood, Wittgenstein, Kant, and Hume in An Interpretation of Religion originates in Faith and Knowledge (both the first edition and the second edition). A correct understanding of Hick’s religious pluralism in An Interpretation of Religion is impossible without a detailed examination of Faith and Knowledge. For Reiichi Miura Contents Abstract ii Acknowledgements ix Introduction 1 1. Related Fields of Research 14 I. THREE PARADIGMS IN THE PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION 14 II. FROM THE PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE TO THE PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE 17 III. PARADIGM SHIFTS IN CHRISTIAN THEOLOGY 20 2. A Framework for the Reading of Hick 32 3. An Outline of the Argument 53 Chapter 1. A METHODOLOGICAL PREPARATION: Hermeneutics and Reliabilism 57 1. Two Conflicting Hermeneutics 59 I. AN INTERPRETATION OF JOHN HICK’S HERMENEUTICS 59 II. AN ALTERNATIVE HERMENEUTICS OF GEORGE LINDBECK 63 III. PHILOSOPHICAL PRESUPPOSITIONS OF THE CONFLICT 67 iv 2. Foundationalism, Coherentism, and Reliabilism 70 I. FOUNDATIONALISM AND ITS IMPLICATIONS FOR RELIGION 70 II. COHERENTISM AND ITS IMPLICATIONS FOR RELIGION 73 III. A METHOD OF RELIABILISM 77 3. Reliabilist Theories of Knowledge 80 I. ALVIN I. GOLDMAN 80 II. ALVIN PLANTINGA 83 III. ERNEST SOSA AND THE RELIGIOUS IMPLICATION 87 Chapter 2. CRITICS OF HICK: A Proposal of Reliabilist Ethics 91 1. Reformed Epistemology 94 I. WILLIAM P. ALSTON 94 II. ALVIN PLANTINGA 99 III. A PHILOSOPHICAL PRESUPPOSITION OF WEAK FOUNDATIONALISM 113 2. Theologians of Religions 119 I. GAVIN D’COSTA 119 II. S. MARK HEIM 123 III. A PHILOSOPHICAL PRESUPPOSITION OF COHERENTISM 129 v 3. Reliabilist Ethics of Normality 134 I. A COMPARATIVE EXAMINATION OF CRITICISMS OF HICK 134 II. AN ETHICS OF RELIABILISM 141 III. A RELIABILIST READING OF HICK 151 Chapter 3. PHILLIPS AND SELLARS: Contradiction between Language and Reality 153 1. Faith and Knowledge 156 2. An Interpretation of Religion 163 I. NON-REALISM OF D. Z. PHILLIPS 163 II. CRITICAL REALISM OF ROY WOOD SELLARS 174 3. Hick’s Defence of Critical Realism 184 Chapter 4. COSMIC OPTIMISM: Contradiction between the Particular and the Universal 189 1. Faith and Knowledge 194 I. WILLIAM JAMES 194 II. JOHN HENRY NEWMAN 203 III. THE ORIGIN OF COSMIC OPTIMISM 208 vi 2. An Interpretation of Religion 218 3. An Intermediate Summary of the Argument 225 Chapter 5. HICK’S INHERITANCE FROM KANT: The System of An Interpretation of Religion 234 1. Incompatible Readings of Kant 239 I. WILLIAM FORGIE 239 II. JOHN MILBANK 240 III. PHILOSOPHICAL PRESUPPOSITIONS OF THE CONFLICT 241 2. An Alternative Reading of Kant 243 I. NORMAN KEMP SMITH 243 II. JOHN OMAN 251 III. JOHN HICK 258 3. Hick’s Religious Pluralism 265 I. IMCOMPATIBLE READINGS OF HICK’S RELIGIOUS PLURALISM 265 II. CRITICAL REALISM AND COSMIC OPTIMISM 268 III. AN ALTERNATIVE READING OF HICK’S RELIGIOUS PLURALISM 274 vii Chapter 6. COMMON SENSE AND HISTORY: Two Complementary Aspects of Hick’s Philosophy 277 1. Philosophy of Common Sense: Hume 282 I. JOHN HICK 282 II. NORMAN KEMP SMITH 290 III. JOHN MILBANK 295 2. Philosophy of History: Theodicy, Eschatology, and Soteriology 301 I. THEODICY 301 II. ESCHATOLOGY 317 III. SOTERIOLOGY 311 3. The Reception of Idealism in Britain, and the Relation between Philosophy and Practice 318 Conclusion 329 Bibliography 347 viii Acknowledgements My gratitude goes first of all to my supervisor, Prof. Philip Goodchild. He has been an encouragement throughout my study in Nottingham. The theology department at Nottingham provided me a stimulating environment to study and live. I am deeply thankful to Conor Cunningham, Simon Oliver, Karen Kilby, John Milbank, Alison Milbank, and Agata Bielik-Robson. I am also grateful to other individuals for their support. I would like to thank Alan Darley, Lukas Theo Paul, Mark Warrener, Andy Hall, Derek Chandler, Mike Coep, Sam Townsend, Rachael Pain, Satoshi Ukai, Tomoko Takemura, Masami Narita, Hidetaka Fukazawa, Takaya Suto, Ikuo Tsuboko, Eijiro Hazama, Daisuke Arie, Ryuichi Yamaoka, Yoshiyuki Kato, Keisuke Sato, and Saori Makino. Above all, I am deeply grateful to my parents for their unflinching support and encouragement. My academic education and formation would have been impossible without their help. ix Introduction The philosophy of John Hick has been accepted as a typical position in the field of philosophy of religion in the English-speaking world, especially with regard to the problem of religious diversity. However, Hick’s position has generated considerable critical response.1 This study will aim to clarify hidden philosophical methods that these critiques of Hick have been presupposing and propose an alternative philosophical method of reliabilism that is more appropriate to understand the contribution Hick makes to the philosophy of religion. Therefore, the aim of this study is twofold. The first is a rehabilitation of Hick’s philosophy against key criticisms. To realize this aim, this study will introduce a new philosophical method of reliabilism, which emphasizes total balance and historical maturation. As a result of the introduction of reliabilism, Hick’s philosophical system is 1 See, for example, Gavin D’Costa, The Meeting of Religions and the Trinity, Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 2000, pp. 24-29 and 45-52. S. Mark Heim, Salvations: Truth and Difference in Religion, Maryknoll, N.Y.: Orbis, 1995, pp. 13-43. William P. Alston, Perceiving God: The Epistemology of Religious Experience, Ithaca and London; Cornell University Press, 1991, pp. 27-28, and 264-66. Alvin Plantinga, ‘Pluralism: A Defense of Religious Exclusivism,’ in The Philosophical Challenge of Religious Diversity, ed. Kevin Meeker & Philip Quinn, New York: Oxford University Press, 1999, pp. 172-92. John Milbank, ‘The End of Dialogue,’ in The Future of Love: Essays in Political Theology, Eugene, Oregon: CACADE Books, 2009, pp. 279-300. David Cheetham, Ways of Meeting and the Theology of Religions, Farnham: Ashgate, pp. 39-60. 1 disclosed to be composed of Hick’s own philosophy of personhood, combined with philosophies of Wittgenstein, Kant, and Hume. Instead of emphasizing one of them, this dissertation will propose to read these different components of Hick’s philosophical system as forming a total worldview, which are complementary with each other. Second, this study will situate Hick’s philosophy in the history of philosophy of religion. Various phases of Hick’s philosophy can be understood as responses to his contemporary situations (e.g. the ‘theology and falsification’ debate, neo-Wittgensteinian philosophy, and Reformed Epistemology). However, the central insight of Hick’s philosophy can be understood to be inherited from a pre-analytical paradigm, which had been almost wholly neglected in the latter half of twentieth century philosophical thinking. For example, in Faith and Knowledge2, one can find an influence from British Idealism 2 John Hick, Faith and Knowledge: A Modern Introduction to the Problem of Religious Knowledge, First Edition, Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press, 1957. 2 (through Norman Kemp Smith3 and John Oman, etc.4). In An Interpretation of Religion5, 3 ‘The philosophical reader can see in Faith and Knowledge the influence of Kant, received through Kemp Smith at Edinburgh.’ See John Hick, An Autobiography, Oxford: Oneworld Publications, 2002, p. 115. Under the influence from Edward Caird and John Watson, Norman Kemp Smith defines Kant’s position as ‘objective idealism’ and situates Kant in the traditions of ‘Lotze, Sigwart, Green, Bradley, Bosanquet, Jones and Dewey.’ See Norman Kemp Smith, Commentary to Kant’s ‘Critique of Pure Reason’, London: Macmillan and Co., 1923, pp. l, 36, and 274. See also Edward Caird, The Critical Philosophy of Immanuel Kant, Glasgow: James Maclehose, 1889. John Watson, The Philosophy of Kant Explained, Glasgow: James Maclehose, 1908. Norman Kemp Smith, Prolegomena to an Idealist Theory of Knowledge, London: Macmillan and Co., Limited, 1924. In various phases of his philosophy, Hick is also influenced by Kemp Smith’s interpretation of Hume: ‘we thus come to rest in something like the ‘natural belief’ that Hume – according to Norman Kemp Smith’s interpretation … – adumbrated.’ See John Hick, An Interpretation of Religion: Human Responses to the Transcendent, Basingstoke, Macmillan Press, 1989, p. 213. See also Hick, Faith and Knowledge, First Edition, pp. 124-25. John Hick, Arguments for the Existence of God, London: Macmillan, 1970, p. 110. Hick, An Autobiography, p. 314. John Hick, The New Frontier of Religion and Science, New York: Palgrave, 2006, pp.
Recommended publications
  • Is It Rational to Have Faith? Looking for New Evidence, Good’S Theorem, and Risk Aversion
    Lara Buchak, November 2009 DRAFT DO NOT CITE Is it rational to have faith? Looking for new evidence, Good’s Theorem, and Risk Aversion 0. Introduction Although statements involving ascriptions of faith are quite common, faith and rationality are often thought to conflict; at best, they are thought to have nothing to say to each other. In this paper, I analyze the concept of faith: in particular, I give an account that unifies statements of faith in mundane matters and statements of religious faith. My account focuses on spelling out the sense in which faith requires going beyond the evidence, and I argue that faith requires stopping ones search for further evidence. I then turn to the question of whether it is rational to have faith, taking into account both epistemic rationality and practical rationality. I argue that faith need not conflict with epistemic rationality at all; however, whether faith can be practically rational hinges on which attitudes towards risk it is rationally permissible to adopt when making decisions: more specifically, it hinges on how one should respond to the risk of misleading evidence. I have argued elsewhere that practical rationality permits a wider range of attitudes towards risk than is commonly supposed, and if this is right, then it is also rationally permissible to have faith; indeed, depending on the attitude towards risk that one decides to adopt, it is sometimes rationally required.1 1. Faith Statements I begin by sketching some characteristics that faith statements have in common. By faith statements, I simply mean statements involving the term faith.
    [Show full text]
  • Literature Review
    New Insights and Directions for Religious Epistemology http://www.newinsights.ox.ac.uk Literature Review Analytic epistemology experienced a monumental resurgence in the latter part of the twentieth century. A short paper by Edmund Gettier launched a frenzied era of original research into the nature of some of our central epistemic concepts, e.g., knowledge, justification, rationality, belief, defeat, and evidence. The excitement of Gettier’s challenge to the view that knowledge is justified true belief drew interest from a wide range of very talented philosophers. Formidable figures such as Fred Dretske, John Pollack, Robert Nozick, Roderick Chisholm, Alvin Goldman, Marshall Swain, David Armstrong, Alvin Plantinga, William Alston, Richard Swinburne, and Gilbert Harman, to name just a few, published widely on the foregoing epistemic concepts. This outpouring of original research meant that new theoretical tools and insights became available for application in philosophy of religion. Religious epistemology, taking advantage of this resurgence in mainstream epistemology, experienced a new era of original research. William Alston, Nicholas Wolterstorff, Alvin Plantinga, and Richard Swinburne all played a particularly central role in this resurgence. Alston, in his popular book Perceiving God, argued that religious beliefs held by way of religious experience are just as justified as our regular or quotidian perceptual beliefs. In his masterpiece Warranted Christian Belief, Plantinga, inspired by (i) the notion of a basic belief in the epistemic theory of foundationalism, (ii) his proper functioning account of warrant, and (iii) John Calvin’s theology, defended the position that Christian beliefs are warranted if true. The broad outlines of his position came to be labeled “Reformed Epistemology.” Wolterstorff, in his Reason within the Bounds of Religion, provided an elegant and sophisticated account of the role religious belief play in an agent’s overall epistemic “web” of beliefs.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae of Alvin Plantinga
    CURRICULUM VITAE OF ALVIN PLANTINGA A. Education Calvin College A.B. 1954 University of Michigan M.A. 1955 Yale University Ph.D. 1958 B. Academic Honors and Awards Fellowships Fellow, Center for Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences, 1968-69 Guggenheim Fellow, June 1 - December 31, 1971, April 4 - August 31, 1972 Fellow, American Academy of Arts & Sciences, 1975 - Fellow, Calvin Center for Christian Scholarship, 1979-1980 Visiting Fellow, Balliol College, Oxford 1975-76 National Endowment for the Humanities Fellowships, 1975-76, 1987, 1995-6 Fellowship, American Council of Learned Societies, 1980-81 Fellow, Frisian Academy, 1999 Gifford Lecturer, 1987, 2005 Honorary Degrees Glasgow University, l982 Calvin College (Distinguished Alumni Award), 1986 North Park College, 1994 Free University of Amsterdam, 1995 Brigham Young University, 1996 University of the West in Timisoara (Timisoara, Romania), 1998 Valparaiso University, 1999 2 Offices Vice-President, American Philosophical Association, Central Division, 1980-81 President, American Philosophical Association, Central Division, 1981-82 President, Society of Christian Philosophers, l983-86 Summer Institutes and Seminars Staff Member, Council for Philosophical Studies Summer Institute in Metaphysics, 1968 Staff member and director, Council for Philosophical Studies Summer Institute in Philosophy of Religion, 1973 Director, National Endowment for the Humanities Summer Seminar, 1974, 1975, 1978 Staff member and co-director (with William P. Alston) NEH Summer Institute in Philosophy of Religion (Bellingham, Washington) 1986 Instructor, Pew Younger Scholars Seminar, 1995, 1999 Co-director summer seminar on nature in belief, Calvin College, July, 2004 Other E. Harris Harbison Award for Distinguished Teaching (Danforth Foundation), 1968 Member, Council for Philosophical Studies, 1968-74 William Evans Visiting Fellow University of Otago (New Zealand) 1991 Mentor, Collegium, Fairfield University 1993 The James A.
    [Show full text]
  • 'Solved by Sacrifice' : Austin Farrer, Fideism, and The
    ‘SOLVED BY SACRIFICE’ : AUSTIN FARRER, FIDEISM, AND THE EVIDENCE OF FAITH Robert Carroll MacSwain A Thesis Submitted for the Degree of PhD at the University of St. Andrews 2010 Full metadata for this item is available in the St Andrews Digital Research Repository at: https://research-repository.st-andrews.ac.uk/ Please use this identifier to cite or link to this item: http://hdl.handle.net/10023/920 This item is protected by original copyright ‘SOLVED BY SACRIFICE’: Austin Farrer, Fideism, and the Evidence of Faith Robert Carroll MacSwain A thesis submitted to the School of Divinity of the University of St Andrews in candidacy for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy The saints confute the logicians, but they do not confute them by logic but by sanctity. They do not prove the real connection between the religious symbols and the everyday realities by logical demonstration, but by life. Solvitur ambulando, said someone about Zeno’s paradox, which proves the impossibility of physical motion. It is solved by walking. Solvitur immolando, says the saint, about the paradox of the logicians. It is solved by sacrifice. —Austin Farrer v ABSTRACT 1. A perennial (if controversial) concern in both theology and philosophy of religion is whether religious belief is ‘reasonable’. Austin Farrer (1904-1968) is widely thought to affirm a positive answer to this concern. Chapter One surveys three interpretations of Farrer on ‘the believer’s reasons’ and thus sets the stage for our investigation into the development of his religious epistemology. 2. The disputed question of whether Farrer became ‘a sort of fideist’ is complicated by the many definitions of fideism.
    [Show full text]
  • Natural Theology and the Christian Contribution to Metaphysics: on Thomas Joseph White’S Wisdom in the Face of Modernity
    Nova et Vetera, English Edition, Vol. 10, No. 2 (2012): 539 –62 539 Natural Theology and the Christian Contribution to Metaphysics: On Thomas Joseph White’s Wisdom in the Face of Modernity NICHOLAS J. H EALY , J R. John Paul II Institute Washington, DC From the very heart of Christian faith and, at the same time, the heart of Greek thought now joined to faith, Manuel II was able to say: Not to act “with logos” is contrary to God’s nature. [T]he faith of the Church has always insisted that between God and us, between his eternal Creator Spirit and our created reason there exists a real analogy, in which unlike - ness remains infinitely greater than likeness, yet not to the point of abol - ishing analogy and its language (cf. Lateran IV). God does not become more divine when we push him away from us in a sheer, impenetrable voluntarism; rather, the truly divine God is the God who has revealed himself as logos and, as logos, has acted and continues to act lovingly on our behalf. This inner rapprochement between biblical faith and Greek philosophical inquiry was an event of decisive importance not only from the standpoint of the history of religions, but also from that of world history—it is an event which concerns us even today. 1 It is my view that the neoscholastic rationalism that was trying to reconstruct the praeambula fidei, the approach to faith, with pure rational certainty, by means of rational argument that was strictly inde - pendent of any faith, has failed; and it cannot be otherwise for any such attempts to do that kind of thing.
    [Show full text]
  • CYRUS P. OLSEN III May 2020
    Cyrus Olsen / 1 CYRUS P. OLSEN III May 2020 414 Loyola Science Center, The University of Scranton Scranton, PA 18510-4699 Telephone: (570) 941-7729 Fax: (570) 941-4386 [email protected]; [email protected] University Webpage ACADEMIC AND ADMINISTRATIVE POSITIONS Faculty Fellow, Slattery Center for the Humanities, University of Scranton, Spring 2021 Co-Director, Health Humanities Concentration, University of Scranton, 2020-Present Associate Prof. Theology/Religious Studies, University of Scranton, 2013-Present Tenure: Spring, 2014 Promotion: Spring, 2013 Director, General Education Assessment, University of Scranton, 2015-18 Assistant Prof. Theology/Religious Studies, University of Scranton, 2007-2013 Director (Interim), M.A. Program, Theology/Religious Studies, University of Scranton, 2009-10 Lecturer, Theology/Religious Studies, University of Scranton, 2006-2007 EDUCATION D.Phil. University of Oxford, Modern Theology (2008) M.Phil. University of Oxford, Modern Theology (2003) B.A. University of Washington, Comparative History of Ideas (2000) Exch. University of Aberdeen, Philosophy, Theology, English, Latin (1998-1999) SELECT GRANT APPLICATIONS AND FUNDED PROJECTS (since 2008) Hope and Healing for Ugandan Youth: Educating Amidst Environmental Degradation, Food Insecurity, and Poverty, Emmanuel Katongole (Notre Dame): $2,500.00 (Spring, 2021) Humanities Connection Grant Co-Signatory and Participant, National Endowment for the Humanities (NEH), Health Humanities Concentration and Community-Based Learning at The University of
    [Show full text]
  • The Triumph of the Irrational in Postenlightenment Theology
    Andrews University Seminaly Studies, Spring 1999, Vol. 37, No. 1, 5-22 Copyright 1999 by Andrews University Press. THE TRIUMPH OF THE IRRATIONAL IN POSTENLIGHTENMENT THEOLOGY PAULFISHER Tunkhannock, PA 18657 This essay advances the idea that a dualism between faith and reason has come to characterize the postenlightenment theological enterprise.' This severance of faith and rationality is rooted in philosophical and not biblical modes of thought.2The result of this dualism is the triumph of the irrational in the interpretation of religious symbols. It would appear that the rigid confinement of faith and reason to autonomous spheres of operation leads to the ascendance of nonhistorical, non~once~tual, nonpsychological, and nonrational interpretations of biblical concepts.) Historical Development of Dualism in Knowledge The interplay of rationality and irrationality in the realm of religion has been analyzed by the conservative Christian apologist Francis Schaeffer. In his Escapefrom Reason, Schaeffer traced the development of a dualism between faith and rationality beginning with Saint Thomas 'The term postenlightenment is used to include both modern and postmodern theological developments. Schleiermacher, Bultmann, Barth, and Tillich are representative of the modern viewpoint; Lindbeck is representative of the postmodern camp. Gerhard Hasel, in a summary of the objections to historical criticism raised by E. Krentz, says, "Faith and the historical-critical method have ddfering means of determining reality. Thus, acceptance of historical criticism leads the Christian into intellectualdualism and forces him to live in two worlds that clash" (Biblicallntqretation Today [Washington,DC: Review and Herald, 1985],82); see also Wolfhart Pannenberg, "Faith and Reason," in Basic Questions in lleology (Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1971), 47.
    [Show full text]
  • The Medieval Social Epistemologies of Augustine and Aquinas
    Knowing and Trusting: The Medieval Social Epistemologies of Augustine and Aquinas by Matthew Kent Siebert A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of Toronto 2014 © Copyright by Matthew Kent Siebert, 2014 Knowing and Trusting The Medieval Social Epistemologies of Augustine and Aquinas Matthew Kent Siebert Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of Toronto 2014 Abstract This dissertation is an introductory exploration of two influential medieval thinkers, Augustine and Aquinas, on the topic of testimony. I explain how Augustine’s view that testimony is a source of knowledge (notitia) developed through four stages, and argue that on Augustine’s view testimonial belief is justified inferentially. I argue that Aquinas thinks some testimonial belief is justified inferentially, and some is justified by adhering to the speaker as the formal object of one’s belief, on the grounds that the speaker is truthful. I argue that these provide knowledge when they provide cognitio. And I argue that Aquinas’s view can be developed into a plausible account of testimonial trust and trustworthiness. ii Acknowledgments I am extremely grateful for the guidance and support of Peter King, Martin Pickavé, and Jennifer Nagel in the writing of this dissertation. I am also grateful to Deborah Black, Michael Siebert, Simona Vucu, and Ian Drummond, for their very helpful comments on earlier drafts of some of these chapters. And I am grateful to the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada, the Government of Ontario, and the University of Toronto for financial support.
    [Show full text]
  • Modernity, Science, and the Making of Religion
    Modernity, Science, and the Making of Religion: A Critical Analysis of a Modern Dichotomy by Rodney W. Tussing A Thesis Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts Approved November 2014 by the Graduate Supervisory Committee: Linell Cady, Chair Joel Gereboff Owen Anderson ARIZONA STATE UNIVERSITY December 2014 ABSTRACT This project examines and challenges the West’s generally accepted two category approach to the world’s belief systems. That is, it will deconstruct the religion / science ‘paradigm’ that has developed over the past two centuries. It will argue that the dichotomy between the two categories was created by modernity for the purpose of establishing an exclusive view believed to be based on knowledge. This exclusive view, philosophical naturalism (science), was set in opposition to all alternative views identified as religion. As the exclusive view, though constructed on a defective foundation of knowledge, philosophical naturalism, nonetheless, became the privileged interpreter and explainer of reality in the academy of the Western world. As a work in the area of epistemology and the philosophy of religion, this project will challenge philosophical naturalism’s claim to knowledge. The approach will be philosophical and historical critically assessing both modernity’s and postmodernity’s basis for knowledge. Without a rational basis for exclusive knowledge the popular dichotomy dissolves. The implications of this dissolution for ‘religious studies’ will be addressed by offering an alternative
    [Show full text]
  • © 2013 University of Notre Dame © 2013 University of Notre Dame CATHOLIC PROGRESSIVES I N E N G L a N D
    CATHOLIC PROGRESSIVES IN ENGLAND AFTER VATICAN II © 2013 University of Notre Dame © 2013 University of Notre Dame C AT H O L I C PROGRESSIVES I N E N G L A N D AFTER VATICAN II JAY P. CORRIN University of Notre Dame Press Notre Dame, Indiana © 2013 University of Notre Dame Copyright © 2013 University of Notre Dame Notre Dame, Indiana 46556 undpress.nd.edu All Rights Reserved Manufactured in the United States of America Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Corrin, Jay P., 1943– Catholic progressives in England after Vatican II / Jay P. Corrin. pages cm Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-0-268-02310-2 (pbk. : alk. paper) — ISBN 0-268-02310-7 (pbk. : alk. paper) 1. Catholic Church—England—History—20th century. 2. England—Church history—20th century. 3. Liberalism (Religion)—Catholic Church—History—20th century. 4. New Left—England. I. Title. BX1493.2.C67 2013 282'.420904—dc23 2013029849 ∞ The paper in this book meets the guidelines for permanence and durability of the Committee on Production Guidelines for Book Longevity of the Council on Library Resources. © 2013 University of Notre Dame To my sister and good friend JANIS HEANEY © 2013 University of Notre Dame © 2013 University of Notre Dame CONTENTS Acknowledgments ix Introduction 1 PA R T O N E The English Cultural Setting ONE The Church in England 9 TWO The Sources of English Catholic Radicalism 21 THREE English Catholics and the Establishment 42 PA R T T W O The Reformers FOUR Reinforcing the Citadel 63 FIVE The Role of John XXIII 88 SIX The Council
    [Show full text]
  • This Thesis Has Been Submitted in Fulfilment of the Requirements for a Postgraduate Degree (E.G
    This thesis has been submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for a postgraduate degree (e.g. PhD, MPhil, DClinPsychol) at the University of Edinburgh. Please note the following terms and conditions of use: This work is protected by copyright and other intellectual property rights, which are retained by the thesis author, unless otherwise stated. A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge. This thesis cannot be reproduced or quoted extensively from without first obtaining permission in writing from the author. The content must not be changed in any way or sold commercially in any format or medium without the formal permission of the author. When referring to this work, full bibliographic details including the author, title, awarding institution and date of the thesis must be given. Not Beyond Language: Wittgenstein and Lindbeck on the Problem of Speaking about God Khay Tham Nehemiah Lim Doctor of Philosophy The University of Edinburgh 2019 Declaration I, Khay Tham Nehemiah Lim, declare that this thesis has been composed solely by myself and that it has not been submitted, in whole or in part, in any previous application for a degree. Except where stated otherwise by reference or acknowledgment, the work presented is entirely my own. Signature: ________________________ Date: ___________________ iii To Jenise whose faith in me has been unswerving and whose encouragement has helped me stay the course. My debt of gratitude to her is beyond language. iv Abstract The problem of speaking about God arises from the claim that God is utterly transcendent and is ‘wholly other’ from human or this-worldly existence.
    [Show full text]
  • An Apophatic View of God and Creation
    Archive of SID An Apophatic View of God and Creation Franco Manni 1 Department of Theology and Religious Studies, King’s College London, UK. E-mail: [email protected]. Abstract The English Dominican Herbert McCabe highlighted some ideas of Thomas Aquinas on the knowability of God and on creation, which can usefully challenge some widespread commonplaces. The purposes of this article are two: to present McCabe’s sophisticated doctrine on the knowability of God and on creation in a systematic way, and to put this doctrine into its historical context. In the scattered and meagre scholarship on McCabe, both points are missing. In fact, despite being highly praised by leading intellectuals such as Stanley Hauerwas, Alasdair McIntyre, Terry Eagleton, David Burrell, Rowan Williams, Denys Turner, and Eamon Duffy, McCabe has remained widely unknown. According to McCabe, both the American creationists and some atheist scientists believe that God—given that he exists—is a powerful entity within the universe, and thus both the atheist and the creationist expect exactly the same elements in the universe. However, according to McCabe, God does not act like natural causes; he is not an element within the universe and not even the most powerful of all the elements, because he created the universe from nothing and is not part of it. Keywords: Herbert McCabe, apophaticism, Aquinas, creatio ex nihilo, Richard Dawkins, creationism. Introduction: Representing God Herbert McCabe (1926-2001) follows Aquinas's model in dealing with the cause that brought everything else into existence, and particularly Religious Inquiries, Volume 8, Number 15, June 2019, pp.
    [Show full text]