Legal Values: Freedom

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Legal Values: Freedom View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Jagiellonian Univeristy Repository L Legal Values: Freedom the type of freedom which is or can be an object of human aspirations and, consequently, is or can be Katarzyna Eliasz and Wojciech Załuski pursued by means of law (by contrast, freedom as Jagiellonian University, Krakow, Poland a fact cannot be aspired to; either human beings are endowed with free will or can be free only in the sense of freedom from compulsion). One can Introduction distinguish four types of freedom as value, viz., negative freedom (i.e., freedom as non- The concept of freedom is strongly ambiguous: it interference), freedom as non-domination, politi- has many different meanings which come into cal freedom, and positive freedom. The article will complex relationships. It seems that a good point aim at presenting them and analyzing their mutual of departure for disentangling these meanings is relationships. making a distinction between freedom as a fact and freedom as a value. The former type of free- dom has a purely descriptive sense: it describes, “ ” Freedom as Noninterference (Negative so to speak, a metaphysical condition of man. Freedom) and Freedom as The basic controversy in this context is whether Non-domination human beings have free will (which is the capacity to make choices undetermined by past events) or The basis for the distinction between freedom as whether the only type of freedom inscribed in noninterference (negative freedom) and freedom their “metaphysical condition” is freedom from as non-domination – two types of freedom which compulsion (which consists in acting in accor- are usually opposed to each other – is the question dance with one’s desires and beliefs and is about the conditions under which one can plausi- compromised either when an agent is coerced bly say that freedom is violated. The adherents of into doing an act by some other agent or if she freedom as noninterference claim that freedom is suffers from some mental disease, deficiency, or undermined in the case of the actual interference disturbance that makes her incapable of recogniz- into a subject’s sphere of choices, whereas the ing the significance of her act and/or controlling adherents of freedom as non-domination claim her conduct). This controversy, essential for the that the very possibility of interference, i.e., poten- philosophy of criminal law (and more specifically, tial interference with an agent’s sphere of choices, for the question about the conditions of moral and constitutes a diminution of her freedom (Pettit legal responsibility), will not be a focus of this 1996, 1997). article. Its focus will be freedom as a value, i.e., # Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2017 M. Sellers, S. Kirste (eds.), Encyclopedia of the Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy, DOI 10.1007/978-94-007-6730-0_234-1 2 Legal Values: Freedom The famous formulation of freedom as non- distinction with a master-slave scenario: the interference (negative freedom) comes from Isa- slave may have a benignant master who does not iah Berlin who claimed that being free is interfere with his activities. For the proponents of equivalent to enjoying a state of lack of coercion, freedom as noninterference, this alone would be i.e., “the deliberate interference of other human sufficient to claim that slave’s freedom is not beings within the area in which I could otherwise compromised. However, the master could alter act” (Berlin 2000: 194). Interference, if thus his conduct and interfere with slave’s affairs on understood, is a deliberate encroachment aimed an arbitrary basis and with impunity. This state of at worsening a subject’s situation of choice. This being at the mercy of the other person is tanta- manner of thinking about freedom can be, in gen- mount to unfreedom according to the adherents of eral, attributed to the representatives of the liberal freedom as non-domination (Pettit 1997:22–23). tradition (e.g., Hobbes, Locke, Mill, or von In this point, freedom as non-domination proves Hayek). For instance, in Thomas Hobbes’s formu- to be a wider or stronger ideal than freedom as lation, a free man is the one who can act in accor- noninterference, as it implies that liberty is dance with his wit or strength without compromised not only by actual but also by impediments (Hobbes 1996: 146). In a likewise potential interference. However, saying that free- manner, Friedrich August von Hayek defines free- dom as non-domination is an extension or dom as the absence of coercion, where coercion is strengthening of freedom as noninterference understood as a state “when one man’s actions are would not be fully apt, since, as is emphasized made to serve another man’s will, not for his own by Pettit, acts of interference are not regarded by but for other’s purpose” (Hayek 2011: 199). the adherents of freedom of non-domination as Needless to say, the acceptance of the conception infringements thereof unless they have a dominat- of freedom as noninterference does not entail the ing character. It should be noted that if, as the support for the unlimited sphere of this freedom. republicans claim, unfreedom of an agent is cor- Maximal negative freedom, i.e., unrestrained by related with the other agent’s (who may be an any external (e.g., legal) regulations, would turn individual but also institutions) capacity to exer- into its opposite – a state of minimal negative cise arbitrary power over her sphere of choices, freedom in which all could interfere with one the question arises as to the means by which another’s choices without impediment. Thus, freedom as non-domination can be secured. The although the supporters of negative freedom con- republicans assert that freedom as non- sider legal and political institutions as a limitation domination can be most effectively secured by of liberty, they acknowledge its necessity. properly designed legal and political institutions, The supporters of freedom as non-domination i.e., based on such measures as the separation of draw attention to the insufficiency of freedom as powers, checks and balances, or the rule of law. noninterference. Although the idea of non- These measures minimize political domination, domination has been thoroughly examined and i.e., domination in the sphere of relations between developed in Philip Pettit’s works, it is not a the citizens and the state. However, as is empha- contemporary conception (Pettit 1997). sized in the more contemporary works in the According to Pettit, equating freedom with non- republican tradition, for freedom as non- domination is a trademark of republican political domination to be fully realized, also social domi- thinkers, such as Machiavelli, Harrington, or nation, i.e., domination in the social relations, Montesquieu. The republicans oppose freedom must be diminished. Social domination results to domination, i.e., a state of arbitrary interfer- from the glaring inequalities in social and eco- ence of one party into the affairs of another under- nomic status. Thus, contemporary supporters of taken at will and with impunity, where non-domination acknowledge that fulfilling this arbitrariness is understood as the lack of “refer- ideal requires certain means of promoting per- ence to the interests, or the opinions, of those sonal independence and economic prosperity affected” (Pettit 1997: 55). Pettit illustrates the (Pettit 1997: 158–165). For instance, according Legal Values: Freedom 3 to Frank Lovett, non-domination demands some foreign governments; in voting laws; in pronounc- form of distributive justice, e.g., guaranteeing for ing judgments; in examining the accounts, the each citizen unconditional basic income (Lovett acts, the stewardship of the magistrates; in calling 2009). them to appear in front of the assembled people, in It is worth noting at the end of this section that, accusing, condemning or absolving them” at the general level, there exists no fundamental (Constant 1988: 311). Thus, ancient political free- disparity between the approaches to law by the dom encompassed an extensive bundle of political supporters of freedom as noninterference and the rights. However, such conception could not be supporters of freedom of non-domination. Both sustained in the modern and contemporary era would agree in the crucial point, namely, that law due to the transformations in the sociopolitical is effective in realizing the type of freedom they conditions, e.g., to the emergence of mass socie- adhere to. However, some subtle differences exist ties. For this reason, the idea of direct participation between them. Firstly, while the former claim that of all citizens in governance has been replaced by law, although effective in securing a possibly the support for representation (among contempo- large amount of negative freedom, constitutes rary philosophers, it was Hannah Arendt (1958) nonetheless its infringement, the latter do not who – despite certain reservations – supported the definitionally oppose law and freedom and ideal of wide political participation in the public thereby do not depict being under the protective realm). Moreover, the support for the ideal of legal and political institutions as a form of a lim- representation stemmed from disbelief that the itation of freedom as non-domination. Secondly, majority could make reasonable decisions and while the former assume that law is an effective from the fear of what Alexis de Tocqueville but not necessary way of generating a possibly labeled as “the tyranny of the majority,” taking large sphere of negative freedom, the latter (given place when the majority of citizens forces its their claim about the definitional connection demands upon minority without taking into con- between law and freedom) assert that law is a sideration (or even at the expense of) its needs and necessary means for realizing freedom as interests (Tocqueville 2000: 239–241).
Recommended publications
  • Freedom, Democracy and Economic Welfare
    copyright The Fraser Institute copyright The Fraser Institute LORD BAUER RAMON DIAZ MILTON FRIEDMAN RAYMOND D GASTIL TIBOR R MACHAN DOUGLASS NORTH SVETOZAR PEJOVICH ALVIN RABUSHKA INGEMAR STAHL LINDSAY M WRIGHT PROCEEDINGS OF AN INTERNATIONAL EDITED BY MICHAEL A WALKER SYMPOSIUM copyright The Fraser Institute Proceedings of an International Symposium on Economic, Political, and Civil Freedom, held October 5-8, 1986 in Napa Valley, California. This event is part of the programme of Liberty Fund Inc., under the direction of its President, Dr W. W. Hill. This Symposium was managed by The Fraser Institute and organized by its Director, Dr. Michael A. Walker. Canadian Cataloguing in Publication Data Main entry under title: Freedom, democracy and economic welfare Symposium held Oct 5-8, 1986 in Napa Valley, Calif. Includes bibliographical references. ISBN 0-88975-116-1 1.Capitalism – Congresses. 2. Liberty – Congresses. 3. Economics – Political aspects – Congresses. 4. Economics – Philosophy – Congresses. I. Walker, Michael 1945 – II.Fraser Institute (Vancouver, BC.) HB501.F74 1988 330.12’2 C88-091102-6 Copyright 1988 by the Fraser Institute. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced in any manner whatsoever without written permission except in the case of brief quotations embodied in critical arti- cles and reviews. Printed in Canada copyright The Fraser Institute CONTENTS Participants / vii Preface, Michael A. Walker / ix PART ONE POLITICAL, ECONOMIC AND CIVIL FREEDOMS: A CONCEPTUAL, HISTORICAL AND STATISTICAL OVERVIEW 1 INSTITUTIONS, ECONOMIC GROWTH AND FREEDOM: AN HISTORICAL INTRODUCTION, Douglass C. North / 3 Discussion / 26 2 CAPITALISM AND FREEDOM, Milton Friedman / 47 Discussion / 59 3 THE STATE OF THE WORLD POLITICAL AND ECONOMIC FREEDOM, Raymond D.
    [Show full text]
  • Unit 24 Individualism and Communitarianism
    Gandhism (Dharma, UNIT 24 INDIVIDUALISM AND Swaraj, Sarvodaya and COMMUNITARIANISM Satyagraha) Structure 24.0 Objectives 24.1 Introduction 24.1.1 Individualist Versus Communitarian Position 24.1.2 Relevance in the Indian Context 24.2 Meaning and Development of Individualism 24.2.1 Atomism and Methodological Individualism 24.2.2 Views of Contractualists Including John Rawls 24.2.3 Views of Utilitarians 24.3 The Individualist Conception of the Self 24.4 The Individualist Theory of the Nature and Functions of the State 24.4.1 Functions of State and Government 24.5 Communitarianism: An Introduction 24.6 The Communitarian Critique of the Individualist Conception of the Self 24.6.1 Two Main Limitations of Individualism 24.7 The Communitarian Critique of the Idea of State Neutrality 24.8 Let Us Sum Up 24.9 Some Useful References 24.10 Answers to Check Your Progress Exercises 24.0 OBJECTIVES Our objective in this unit is to understand and assess one of the major ongoing debates in contemporary political theory; namely, the debate between liberal individualism and communitarianism. After studying this unit, you should be able to: • Understand the individualistic theory of the nature and functions of state; • Describe and assess the communitarian critique of liberal individualism; • Compare the major theoretical positions of individualism and communitarianism; and • Understand the relevance of this debate to contemporary political theory and practice. 24.1 INTRODUCTION In this unit, you will be introduced to one of the central debates in contemporary political theory, namely, the debate between liberal individualism and communitarianism. The debate between individualism and communitarianism developed and became central to political theory during the 1980s with the publication of Michael Sandel’s Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (1982).
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 4 Freedom and Progress
    Chapter 4 Freedom and Progress The best road to progress is freedom’s road. John F. Kennedy The only freedom which deserves the name, is that of pursuing our own good in our own way, so long as we do not attempt to deprive others of theirs, or impeded their efforts to obtain it. John Stuart Mill To cull the inestimable benefits assured by freedom of the press, it is necessary to put up with the inevitable evils springing therefrom. Alexis de Tocqueville Freedom is necessary to generate progress; people also value freedom as an important component of progress. This chapter will contend that both propositions are correct. Without liberty, there will be little or no progress; most people will consider an expansion in freedom as progress. Neither proposition would win universal acceptance. Some would argue that a totalitarian state can marshal the resources to generate economic growth. Many will contend that too much liberty induces libertine behavior and is destructive of society, peace, and the family. For better or worse, the record shows that freedom has increased throughout the world over the last few centuries and especially over the last few decades. There are of course many examples of non-free, totalitarian, ruthless government on the globe, but their number has decreased and now represents a smaller proportion of the world’s population. Perhaps this growth of freedom is partially responsible for the breakdown of the family and the rise in crime, described in the previous chapter. Dictators do tolerate less crime and are often very repressive of deviant sexual behavior, but, as the previous chapter reported, divorce and illegitimacy are more connected with improved income of women than with a permissive society.
    [Show full text]
  • Durham Research Online
    Durham Research Online Deposited in DRO: 24 April 2017 Version of attached le: Accepted Version Peer-review status of attached le: Peer-reviewed Citation for published item: Dimova-Cookson, Maria (2013) 'Defending Isaiah Berlin's distinctions between negative and positive freedoms.', in Isaiah Berlin and the politics of freedom : 'Two concepts of liberty' 50 years later. New York: Routledge, pp. 73-86. Routledge innovations in political theory. (48). Further information on publisher's website: https://www.routledge.com/9780415656795/ Publisher's copyright statement: This is an Accepted Manuscript of a book chapter published by Routledge in Isaiah Berlin and the politics of freedom: 'Two concepts of liberty' 50 years later on 20/12/2012, available online: https://www.routledge.com/9780415656795/ Additional information: Use policy The full-text may be used and/or reproduced, and given to third parties in any format or medium, without prior permission or charge, for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-prot purposes provided that: • a full bibliographic reference is made to the original source • a link is made to the metadata record in DRO • the full-text is not changed in any way The full-text must not be sold in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holders. Please consult the full DRO policy for further details. Durham University Library, Stockton Road, Durham DH1 3LY, United Kingdom Tel : +44 (0)191 334 3042 | Fax : +44 (0)191 334 2971 https://dro.dur.ac.uk Defending Isaiah Berlin’s Distinctions between Negative and Positive Freedoms1 Maria Dimova-Cookson Published in Bruce Baum and Robert Nichols, eds.
    [Show full text]
  • WPSA 2017 Unstable Equilibrium
    Unstable Equilibrium: Positive and Negative Liberty for Isaiah Berlin Kathleen Cole, Ph.D. Metropolitan State University Paper for Presentation at the Annual Meeting of the Western Political Science Association April 15, 2017 This paper is a working draft. Please do not circulate. In his landmark essay, “Two Concepts of Liberty,” Isaiah Berlin identifies two distinct conceptions of liberty that have emerged from various philosophical traditions: negative and positive liberty. For Berlin, theorists of negative and positive liberty differ with respect to the divergent questions they ask when determining conditions of freedom or unfreedom. Negative liberty theorists are centrally concerned with the question, “[What is the] minimum area of personal freedom which must on no account be violated”?1 From this perspective, “I am normally said to be free to the degree to which no man or body of men interferes with my activity. Political liberty in this sense if simply the area within which a man can act unobstructed by others.”2 In contrast, positive liberty theorists determine conditions of freedom or unfreedom by asking, “By whom am I ruled?”3 From this perspective, to be free is to be one’s own master, to make autonomous choices about the purpose and practices of one’s life, and to bear the responsibility for those choices.4 Berlin’s essay has been widely praised for clarifying important distinctions between conflicting meanings of the term liberty.5 The essay has become one of Berlin’s most widely read and influential publications. Often, the essay is interpreted as an endorsement of negative liberty and a rejection of positive conceptions of liberty.
    [Show full text]
  • AFTER BERLIN the Literature 2002–2020 George Crowder
    AFTER BERLIN The Literature 2002–2020 George Crowder The Isaiah Berlin Virtual Library aims to post, in the fullness of time, PDFs of all Berlin’s uncollected and unpublished work, including lectures, interviews and broadcasts, so that it is conveniently readable and searchable online. Occasional articles by other authors about Berlin, such as this one, will also be included. All enquiries, including those concerning rights, should be directed to the Isaiah Berlin Legacy Fellow at Wolfson College, [email protected] AFTER BERLIN The Literature 2002–2020 George Crowder This essay was first posted (in the Isaiah Berlin Virtual Library) in March 2016. It is intended to complement and update Ian Harris’s ‘Berlin and His Critics’, in Isaiah Berlin, Liberty, ed. Henry Hardy (Oxford, 2002: Oxford University Press), 349–64. Later impressions of that volume include a postscript, most recently updated as ‘Postscript September 2016’ (365–74), which may be read in conjunction with George Crowder’s treatment of recent developments below. Some corrections, updatings and additions were made in 2020. ‘AMONG ALL FORMS OF MISTAKE,’ wrote George Eliot, ‘prophecy is the most gratuitous’ (Eliot 1871–2: 84). About fifteen years ago an eminent political theorist told me that the work of Isaiah Berlin would attract little attention in twenty years’ time. That prophecy has another few years to run, but at this stage it shows no sign of being vindicated. As a rough measure one might look at The Isaiah Berlin Virtual Library (IBVL: Hardy 2000– ), the primary online site for Berlin studies. The section entitled ‘Articles on Berlin, and other publications that discuss him’, lists approximately 320 items for the 1990s, but over 600 for the period 2000–20.
    [Show full text]
  • Liberty, Property and Rationality
    Liberty, Property and Rationality Concept of Freedom in Murray Rothbard’s Anarcho-capitalism Master’s Thesis Hannu Hästbacka 13.11.2018 University of Helsinki Faculty of Arts General History Tiedekunta/Osasto – Fakultet/Sektion – Faculty Laitos – Institution – Department Humanistinen tiedekunta Filosofian, historian, kulttuurin ja taiteiden tutkimuksen laitos Tekijä – Författare – Author Hannu Hästbacka Työn nimi – Arbetets titel – Title Liberty, Property and Rationality. Concept of Freedom in Murray Rothbard’s Anarcho-capitalism Oppiaine – Läroämne – Subject Yleinen historia Työn laji – Arbetets art – Level Aika – Datum – Month and Sivumäärä– Sidoantal – Number of pages Pro gradu -tutkielma year 100 13.11.2018 Tiivistelmä – Referat – Abstract Murray Rothbard (1926–1995) on yksi keskeisimmistä modernin libertarismin taustalla olevista ajattelijoista. Rothbard pitää yksilöllistä vapautta keskeisimpänä periaatteenaan, ja yhdistää filosofiassaan klassisen liberalismin perinnettä itävaltalaiseen taloustieteeseen, teleologiseen luonnonoikeusajatteluun sekä individualistiseen anarkismiin. Hänen tavoitteenaan on kehittää puhtaaseen järkeen pohjautuva oikeusoppi, jonka pohjalta voidaan perustaa vapaiden markkinoiden ihanneyhteiskunta. Valtiota ei täten Rothbardin ihanneyhteiskunnassa ole, vaan vastuu yksilöllisten luonnonoikeuksien toteutumisesta on kokonaan yksilöllä itsellään. Tutkin työssäni vapauden käsitettä Rothbardin anarko-kapitalistisessa filosofiassa. Selvitän ja analysoin Rothbardin ajattelun keskeisimpiä elementtejä niiden filosofisissa,
    [Show full text]
  • Social Power and Political Freedom 21
    Social Power and Political Freedom 21 2 Social Power and Political Freedom SEEKING CONTROLS OVER GOVERNMENTS One of the most urgent general problems in politics today is how to control the actions of modern governments. Their uncontrolled power threatens us in various ways -- most blatantly in the forms of modern tyranny and war. The traditional means of controlling rulers - - constitutional limitations, elections, self-restraint in the rulers themselves, and violent revolution -- have been demonstrated to have significant limitations and disadvantages, regardless of their other 22 SOCIAL POWER and POLITICAL FREEDOM Social Power and Political Freedom 23 contributions. In extreme situations in which control is most needed, one might threaten or implement a direct explosive attack of great we can no longer rely upon those traditional means as our only magnitude (as a violent revolution or an international war) intended options. If we are not to become helpless political automatons, or to to destroy at least part of the mighty structure. It has been widely be annihilated, we must find and implement effective means of assumed that against a ruler unwilling to accept limits or to abdicate control over the power of rulers. voluntarily only such destructive means are capable of weakening or If we are to discover, develop, and implement such means of abolishing the power of the regime. control we must think about this problem. To do this, we need to go back to a much more basic level of discussion of political power than is usual these days in discussions of the problems of war, tyranny, THE SOURCES OF THE POWER OF RULERS and oppression.
    [Show full text]
  • Two Concepts of Liberty
    “No chains around my feet, but I’m not free.” – Bob Marley (Concrete Jungle) Two Concepts of Liberty 1. Positive vs Negative Liberty: Isaiah Berlin’s highly influential article brought to light the nature of the disagreement about political freedom. Largely until his time, the default assumption was that ‘liberty’ referred to what Berlin calls ‘negative liberty’. Negative Liberty: Roughly, freedom FROM. One is free in this sense to the extent that their actions are not hindered or prevented by outside interferers. Jefferson & Madison: This is, for instance, how the founding fathers understood liberty. Consider our constitutionally recognized rights of freedom of speech, freedom of religion (in James Madison’s Bill of Rights), and rights to life, liberty, and pursuit of happiness (in Thomas Jefferson’s Declaration of Independence). Example: Freedom of Speech: Having this right means that the government will not interfere with your speech (e.g., they will not pass laws forbidding you from saying whatever you want, and they will pass laws forbidding others from coercively preventing you from saying whatever you want, etc.). The same can be said for all of the others I listed. (For instance, as one more example, the government will allow you to pursue happiness, and they will not interfere with you or try to prevent you from doing so.) But, negative liberty of, say freedom of speech, doesn’t do me any good if I lack the ability to speak. For instance, imagine that I was raised by wolves and I don’t know how to speak any human languages, or read, or write, etc.
    [Show full text]
  • The Relation Between Economic Freedom and Political Freedom
    Page 1 of 7 Milton Friedman, Capitalism and Freedom, 1962. Chapter I The Relation between Economic Freedom and Political Freedom It is widely believed that politics and economics are separate and largely unconnected; that individual freedom is a political problem and material welfare an economic problem; and that any kind of political arrangements can be combined with any kind of economic arrangements. The chief contemporary manifestation of this idea is the advocacy of "democratic socialism" by many who condemn out of hand the restrictions on individual freedom imposed by "totalitarian socialism" in Russia, and who are persuaded that it is possible for a country to adopt the essential features of Russian economic arrangements and yet to ensure individual freedom through political arrangements. The thesis of this chapter is that such a view is a delusion, that there is an intimate connection between economics and politics, that only certain combinations of political and economic arrangements are possible, and that in particular, a society which is socialist cannot also be democratic, in the sense of guaranteeing individual freedom Economic arrangements play a dual role in the promotion of a free society. On the one hand, freedom in economic arrangements is itself a component of freedom broadly understood, so economic freedom is an end in itself. In the second place, economic freedom is also an indispensable means toward the achievement of political freedom. The first of these roles of economic freedom needs special emphasis because intellectuals in particular have a strong bias against regarding this aspect of freedom as important. They tend to express contempt for what they regard as material aspects of life, and to regard their own pursuit of allegedly higher values as on a different plane of significance and as deserving of special attention.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is Jewish (If Anything) About Isaiah Berlin’S Philosophy?
    Religions 2012, 3, 289–319; doi:10.3390/rel3020289 OPEN ACCESS religions ISSN 2077-1444 www.mdpi.com/journal/religions Article What is Jewish (If Anything) about Isaiah Berlin’s Philosophy? Arie M. Dubnov Department of History, Stanford University, 450 Serra Mall, Building 200, Stanford CA 94305, USA; E-Mail: [email protected] Received: 23 March 2012; in revised form: 28 March 2012 / Accepted: 31 March 2012 / Published: 13 April 2012 Abstract: This paper has two central aims: First, to reappraise Isaiah Berlin‘s political thought in a historically contextualized way, and in particular: to pay attention to a central conceptual tensions which animates it between, on the one hand, his famous definition of liberalism as resting on a negative concept of liberty and, on the other, his defense of cultural nationalism in general and Zionism in particular. Second, to see what do we gain and what do we lose by dubbing his philosophy Jewish. The discussion will proceed as follows: after describing the conceptual tension (Section 1), I will examine Berlin‘s discussion of nationalism and explain why comparisons between him and Hans Kohn as well as communitarian interpretations of him are incomplete and have limited merit. I will continue with a brief discussion of Berlin‘s Jewishness and Zionism (Section 3) and explain why I define this position ―Diaspora Zionism‖. The two concluding sections will discuss Berlin‘s place within a larger Cold War liberal discourse (Section 5) and why I find it problematic to see his political writings as part of a Jewish political tradition (Section 6).
    [Show full text]
  • Farewell to Freedom:A Western Genealogy of Liberty
    RICCARDO BALDISSONE FAREWELL to FREEDOM A Western Genealogy of Liberty Farewell to Freedom: A Western Genealogy of Liberty Riccardo Baldissone University of Westminster Press www.uwestminsterpress.co.uk Published by University of Westminster Press 115 New Cavendish Street London W1W 6UW www.uwestminsterpress.co.uk Text © Riccardo Baldissone 2018 First published 2018 Cover: Diana Jarvis Image: ‘Perseus Freeing Andromeda’, courtesy of Warburg Institute Printed in the UK by Lightning Source Ltd. Print and digital versions typeset by Siliconchips Services Ltd. ISBN (Paperback): 978-1-911534-60-0 ISBN (PDF) 978-1-911534-61-7 ISBN (ePUB): 978-1-911534-62-4 ISBN (Kindle): 978-1-911534-63-1 DOI: https://doi.org/10.16997/book15 This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution- NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International Licence. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by- nc-nd/4.0/ or send a letter to Creative Commons, 444 Castro Street, Suite 900, Mountain View, California, 94041, USA. This licence allows for copying and distributing the work, providing author attribution is clearly stated, that you are not using the material for commercial pur- poses, and that modified versions are not distributed. The full text of this book has been peer-reviewed to ensure high academic standards. For full review policies, see: http://www.uwestminsterpress.co.uk/site/publish/ Suggested citation: Baldissone, R 2018 Farewell to Freedom: A Western Genealogy of Liberty. London: University of Westminster Press. DOI: https://doi. org/10.16997/book15. License: CC-BY-NC-ND 4.0 To read the free, open access version of this book online, visit https://doi.org/10.16997/book15 or scan this QR code with your mobile device: to my mother, my lover, and my daughter contaminari decere fabulasα Il n’y a point de mot qui aît reçû plus de différentes significations, & qui aît frappé les esprits de tant de manières, que celui de Libertéβ α [I]t is proper to contaminate stories.
    [Show full text]