The Idealism of Life: Hegel and Kant on the Ontology of Living Individuals

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Idealism of Life: Hegel and Kant on the Ontology of Living Individuals The Idealism of Life: Hegel and Kant on the Ontology of Living Individuals by Franklin Charles Owen Cooper-Simpson A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of PhD Graduate Department of Philosophy University of Toronto © Copyright by Franklin Charles Owen Cooper-Simpson 2017 The Idealism of Life: Hegel and Kant on the Ontology of Living Individuals Franklin Charles Owen Cooper-Simpson PhD Graduate Department of Philosophy University of Toronto 2017 Abstract My dissertation, The Idealism of Life: Hegel and Kant on the Ontology of Living Individuals, investigates the significance of the concept of life for Kant’s and Hegel’s respective forms of idealism. In Chapter 1, I argue that Kant’s account of the subjective origin of the a priori forms of cognition requires that when we judge something to be a living individual, we only suppose it to be so (or, in other words, that these judgments do not determine anything in the object being judged). In the remaining chapters, I argue that Hegel’s account of life as objectively real (i.e. rather than a supposition we make) depends on his development of the concept of the individual as self-determining self. I trace this development in the Science of Logic through three stages. In Chapter 2, I argue that any minimal notion of self depends on Hegel’s logic of the Infinite as described in the Doctrine of Being. In Chapter 3, I argue that this minimal account of selfhood is possible only if that self is immanently, rather than externally, determined—that is, that a self cannot be defined from without—by tracing Hegel’s account of ‘Determining Reflection’. In Chapter 4, I show how, for Hegel, the logic of self- determination gives us the resources to describe the concept of individuality, which Hegel develops as the ‘Concept’. In Chapter 5, I conclude that Hegel’s account of life depends on the ii claim that the ideal relations immanent to it (relations between, e.g., self and other, or organism and organ) both constitute and are constituted by the material determinations of the living thing. This, in turn, suggests that any idealism that attributes ideal forms and material determinations to distinct sources will be unable to describe life as objectively real. iii Acknowledgments My experience writing this dissertation has been both taxing and rewarding (in roughly equal parts), and I would not have been able to meet the challenges it posed, nor to appreciate the rewards it offered, without the guidance and support of many. I would like to thank, first, Rebecca Comay, whose supervision and guidance first made this project possible. I have been incredibly fortunate to have a supervisor in Rebecca who was willing to challenge me to see new possibilities, both in Hegel’s writing and in my own, all while expressing staunch support for the idea I meant to develop. I would also like to express my deep gratitude for the mentorship and support of John Russon, without whom this project could not have been completed. From each of our many conversations about Hegel, I have come away with both a richer understanding of Hegel’s thinking and of what it means to do philosophy in the first place. I would like to thank Margaret Morrison, whose advice and support first encouraged me to pursue a graduate degree in philosophy, and who helped me develop, over the course of two years, the argument that would become the first chapter of this dissertation. I would like to thank, too, Nicholas Stang, whose careful reading and invaluable comments helped me develop a much more nuanced argument. I am also extremely grateful for all those who helped my nascent sense of what is true while at the University of Toronto. In particular, I would like to thank Arthur Ripstein, whose undergraduate course on Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason convinced me that I would need to spend the rest of my life thinking about Kant’s philosophy; Evan Thompson, who introduced me to both the phenomenology of life of Hans Jonas and his own work in Mind in Life, which inaugurated my thinking about the concept of life as self-determining; and to Ulrich Schlösser, whose attentive reading of Kant’s first and third Critique shaped my understanding of those texts to this day. My intellectual development also owes a great deal to the many instructive (and deeply enjoyable) conversations I have had with G. Anthony Bruno, Sean Michael Smith, Michael Blezy, and Dave Suarez. I would like to express my heartfelt gratitude to my parents, Anne and Peter, whose unconditional support, guidance and teaching has, in many different ways, made me the person— and scholar—that I am. Finally, I would like to thank my partner, Lucy, who has lived with me in the trenches for the past three years, and whose continual encouragement, inspiration and love made this whole thing seem possible. iv To Lucy v Table of Contents Acknowledgements iv Introduction: The Idealism of Life 1 Chapter 1: Kant’s Conception of Life and the Limits of a Discursive Intellect 24 1.1 The Life of Transcendental Philosophy 24 1.2 Two Kind of Chaos 27 1.3 Empirical Chaos and the notion of Purposiveness 33 1.4 From Purposiveness to Life 40 1.5 The Limits of the Discursive Intellect 57 Chapter 2: Hegel’s Concept of the Infinite 64 2.1 From Finite to Infinite Idealism 64 2.2 The Infinity of Being 68 2.3 The Idealism of the Finite 82 Chapter 3: Reflection and the Self-Determination of Being 101 3.1 Introduction: From Being to Essence 101 3.2 The Logic of Reflection 104 3.3 Positing Reflection 107 3.4 From External Reflection to Determining Reflection 124 3.5 The Origin of Difference 135 vi Chapter 4: The Self-Determination of the Concept 145 4.1 The Concept in General 145 4.2 The Moments of the Concept 148 4.3 The Universality of the Now 165 4.4 The Concept as Logic of the Self 170 4.5 The Concept as Subject-Object: The Idea 176 Chapter 5: The Logic of Life 187 5.1 What Is ‘Logical’ Life? 187 5.2 The Idea of Life 194 5.3 The Idea of Life and the Judgment of Natural Ends 209 5.4 The Idealism of Life 217 Conclusion 223 References and Abbreviations 226 Bibliography 227 vii Introduction The Idealism of Life Hegel’s Early Reception of Kant’s Theory of the Organic In Hegel’s first published philosophical work, the Difference essay of 1801, he makes a brief and curious remark about Kant’s theoretical treatment of nature: Kant…views nature as Subject-Object in that he treats the product of nature as an end of nature, as purposeful without a concept of purpose, as necessary without being mechanistic, as identity of concept and being. But at the same time this view of nature is supposed to be merely teleological, that is to say, it only serves validly as a maxim for our limited human understanding whose thinking is discursive and whose universal concepts do not contain the particular phenomena of nature. This human perspective is not supposed to affirm anything concerning the reality of nature.1 Hegel is here clearly making reference to Kant’s “Critique of Teleological Judgment,” the latter half of the Critique of Judgment famous, especially among the German Idealists, for Kant’s characterization of the “intuitive understanding”. It is clear, too, that here Hegel celebrates Kant for regarding in nature’s ‘purposefulness’ the “identity of concept and being,” while lamenting the fact that, for Kant, to regard nature in this light is merely to adopt a “maxim for our limited human understanding,” one that does not allow us to know “anything concerning the reality of nature”. In other words, for Hegel, Kant has arrived at some important expression of the ‘Subject-Object’ in nature, but he nevertheless fails to regard it as actually true of nature, or as actually describing 1 DS 163. 1 2 nature’s reality apart from how we, as discursive thinkers, merely subjectively understand it. Though the terms of his analysis change somewhat, Hegel makes a similar point in his next major philosophical work, Faith and Knowledge: In his reflection upon [organic nature] in the “Critique of Teleological Judgment,” Kant expresses the Idea of Reason more definitely than in the preceding concept of a harmonious play of cognitive powers. He expresses it now in the Idea of an intuitive intellect, for which possibility and actuality are one… An intuitive intellect would “not proceed from the universal to the particular and so to the singular (through concepts); and the concordance of the particular laws in nature’s products with the intellect will not be contingent for it.”2 It is an “archetypal (urbildich) intellect” for which “the possibility of the parts, etc., as to their character and integration is dependent on the whole.”3 […] The Idea occurs [to Kant] here only as a thought. Notwithstanding its admitted necessity, reality must not be predicated of it. On the contrary, we must once for all accept the fact that universal and particular are inevitably and necessarily distinct.4 Here, as before, Hegel identifies a significant idea in Kant’s theorizing on purposive or teleological nature which, he feels, has been unduly relegated to a subjective status, or which has been denied reality. Here, the reference to Kant’s notion of an intuitive intellect5 is explicit. We are 2 CPJ, 5: 405-408. 3 Ibid., 5: 405-408.
Recommended publications
  • The Meaning and Significance of Dispute on Objectless Presentations
    NeuroQuantology | December 2018 | Volume 16 | Issue 12 | Page 87-91| doi: 10.14704/nq.2018.16.12.1344 Seliverstov S., The Meaning and Significance of Dispute on Objectless Presentations The Meaning and Significance of Dispute on Objectless Presentations Vladimir Seliverstov* ABSTRACT This paper considers the evolution of understanding and the status of objectless presentations in the works of the three main authors of this tradition: “The Theory of Science” by B. Bolzano, “On Content and Object of Presentations” by K. Twardowski and “Intentional Objects” by E. Husserl. A critical analysis of these positions on objectless presentations is interesting, because here in one point, in one discussion, we have several very important philosophical theories that have had an impact on the philosophical debates in the twentieth century, particularly on the discussion Alexius Meinong and Bertrand Russell at the beginning of XX century. We want to show, how this Meinong’s conception has contemporary philosophy. Here author aims to show how theory of objects as such came into being and how its main ideasmade weresignificant discussed contribution and criticized into the in problemsubsequent of nonexistent philosophical objects thought. that Thisstill remainsdispute pushesone of theus tomost think debated that we in deal here with fundamental ideological differences between these conceptions. Therefore, it allowed to consider another important philosophical and methodological problem - the problem of incommunicability between logical and psychological conceptions. Key Words: Bolzano, Twardowski, Theory of Objects, Phenomenology, Objectless Presentations, Intentionality 87 DOI Number: 10.14704/nq.2018.16.12.1344 NeuroQuantology 2018; 16(12):87-91 The Problem he is often called a precursor of analytic philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Either in Plain Text Format As Am Attached PDF) at the End of the Term
    History of Analytic Philosophy410 — Syllabus Lecturer: SidneyFelder,e-mail: [email protected] Rutgers The State University of NewJersey, Spring 2021 “Office Hours” (i.e., individual discussions): By Appointment Formanyreasons, there is no uncontroversial general characterization of the range of work that tends to be classified under the heading “Analytic Philosophy”. For our purposes, an analytic philosopher is anyone whose work is conducted in awareness of the fundamental importance, for every variety of foundational and philosophical inquiry,ofobtaining a proper understanding of what properties of thought, perception, language, and the world, and what properties of their relationship, makepossible the meaningful ascription of truth, fal- sity,and referential significance of anykind to such things as thoughts, beliefs, sentences, propositions, and judgments. This course covers the early history of analytic philosophy, concentrating largely on writings of Gottlob Frege, Bertrand Russell, G.E. Moore, and Ludwig Wittgenstein, whose work secured recognition of the necessity as well as the great difficulty of this kind of inquiry. Weeks 1, 2, 3, 4 Transition from idealism, naturalism, and Kantianism Russell Our Knowledgeofthe External World (1914) Chapter I, Current Tendencies; Chapter II, Logic As the Essence of Philosophy Frege The Foundations of Arithmetic (1884) , Introduction and sections 1-28. Moore Principia Ethica (1903) , Chapters I, II, III (36-44) ,VI(110-121) Russell The Principles of Mathematics (1903) , Chapters I, III (Sections 37-38, 43-45) ,IV, V(56-60, 63-65) ,VI(66-74) , VIII (86-87, 93) ,IX, X, XVI, XXVI, XXVII (217-219) ,XLII, XLIII (337-341) ,LI Weeks 5, 6, 7, 8, 9, 10 Construction of a Language for Mathematics.
    [Show full text]
  • Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus</Em>
    University of South Florida Scholar Commons Graduate Theses and Dissertations Graduate School 8-6-2008 Three Wittgensteins: Interpreting the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus Thomas J. Brommage Jr. University of South Florida Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd Part of the American Studies Commons Scholar Commons Citation Brommage, Thomas J. Jr., "Three Wittgensteins: Interpreting the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus" (2008). Graduate Theses and Dissertations. https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/149 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Three Wittgensteins: Interpreting the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus by Thomas J. Brommage, Jr. A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy College of Arts and Sciences University of South Florida Co-Major Professor: Kwasi Wiredu, B.Phil. Co-Major Professor: Stephen P. Turner, Ph.D. Charles B. Guignon, Ph.D. Richard N. Manning, J. D., Ph.D. Joanne B. Waugh, Ph.D. Date of Approval: August 6, 2008 Keywords: Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, logical empiricism, resolute reading, metaphysics © Copyright 2008 , Thomas J. Brommage, Jr. Acknowledgments There are many people whom have helped me along the way. My most prominent debts include Ray Langely, Billy Joe Lucas, and Mary T. Clark, who trained me in philosophy at Manhattanville College; and also to Joanne Waugh, Stephen Turner, Kwasi Wiredu and Cahrles Guignon, all of whom have nurtured my love for the philosophy of language.
    [Show full text]
  • Frege's Influence on Wittgenstein: Reversing Metaphysics Via the Context Principle*
    Frege's Influence on Wittgenstein: Reversing Metaphysics via the Context Principle* Erich H. Reck Gottlob Frege and Ludwig Wittgenstein (the later Wittgenstein) are often seen as polar opposites with respect to their fundamental philosophical outlooks: Frege as a paradig- matic "realist", Wittgenstein as a paradigmatic "anti-realist". This opposition is supposed to find its clearest expression with respect to mathematics: Frege is seen as the "arch-pla- tonist", Wittgenstein as some sort of "radical anti-platonist". Furthermore, seeing them as such fits nicely with a widely shared view about their relation: the later Wittgenstein is supposed to have developed his ideas in direct opposition to Frege. The purpose of this paper is to challenge these standard assumptions. I will argue that Frege's and Wittgen- stein's basic outlooks have something crucial in common; and I will argue that this is the result of the positive influence Frege had on Wittgenstein. It would be absurd to claim that there are no important differences between Frege and Wittgenstein. Likewise, it would be absurd to claim that the later Wittgenstein was not critical of some of Frege's ideas. What, then, is the common element I see? My sugges- tion is that the two thinkers agree on what I call a reversal of metaphysics (relative to a standard kind of metaphysics attacked by both). This is not an agreement on one particu- lar thesis or on one argument. Rather, it has to do with what is prior and what is posterior when it comes to certain fundamental explanations in metaphysics (also, relatedly, in semantics and epistemology).
    [Show full text]
  • The Theatre of Death: the Uncanny in Mimesis Tadeusz Kantor, Aby Warburg, and an Iconography of the Actor; Or, Must One Die to Be Dead
    The Theatre of Death: The Uncanny in Mimesis Tadeusz Kantor, Aby Warburg, and an Iconography of the Actor; Or, must one die to be dead. Twitchin, Mischa The copyright of this thesis rests with the author and no quotation from it or information derived from it may be published without the prior written consent of the author For additional information about this publication click this link. http://qmro.qmul.ac.uk/jspui/handle/123456789/8626 Information about this research object was correct at the time of download; we occasionally make corrections to records, please therefore check the published record when citing. For more information contact [email protected] The Theatre of Death: The Uncanny in Mimesis Tadeusz Kantor, Aby Warburg, and an Iconography of the Actor; Or, must one die to be dead? Mischa Twitchin Submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements of the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy. 1 The Theatre of Death: the Uncanny in Mimesis (Abstract) The aim of this thesis is to explore an heuristic analogy as proposed in its very title: how does a concept of the “uncanny in mimesis” and of the “theatre of death” give content to each other – historically and theoretically – as distinct from the one providing either a description of, or even a metaphor for, the other? Thus, while the title for this concept of theatre derives from an eponymous manifesto of Tadeusz Kantor’s, the thesis does not aim to explain what the concept might mean in this historically specific instance only. Rather, it aims to develop a comparative analysis, through the question of mimesis, allowing for different theatre artists to be related within what will be proposed as a “minor” tradition of modernist art theatre (that “of death”).
    [Show full text]
  • Concepts and Objects
    5 Concepts and Objects Ray Brassier 1. The question ‘What is real?’ stands at the crossroads of metaphysics and epistemol- ogy. More exactly, it marks the juncture of metaphysics and epistemology with the seal of conceptual representation. 2. Metaphysics understood as the investigation into what there is intersects with epistemology understood as the enquiry into how we know what there is. This intersec- tion of knowing and being is articulated through a theory of conception that explains how thought gains traction on being. 3. That the articulation of thought and being is necessarily conceptual follows from the Critical injunction which rules out any recourse to the doctrine of a pre-es- tablished harmony between reality and ideality. Thought is not guaranteed access to being; being is not inherently thinkable. There is no cognitive ingress to the real save through the concept. Yet the real itself is not to be confused with the concepts through which we know it. The fundamental problem of philosophy is to understand how to reconcile these two claims. 4. We gain access to the structure of reality via a machinery of conception which extracts intelligible indices from a world that is not designed to be intelligible and is not originarily infused with meaning. Meaning is a function of conception and con- ception involves representation—though this is not to say that conceptual representa- tion can be construed in terms of word-world mappings. It falls to conceptual ratio- nality to forge the explanatory bridge from thought to being. 5. Thus the metaphysical exploration of the structure of being can only be carried out in tandem with an epistemological investigation into the nature of conception.
    [Show full text]
  • The Theatre of Death: the Uncanny in Mimesis Tadeusz Kantor, Aby Warburg, and an Iconography of the Actor; Or, Must One Die to Be Dead?
    The Theatre of Death: The Uncanny in Mimesis Tadeusz Kantor, Aby Warburg, and an Iconography of the Actor; Or, must one die to be dead? Mischa Twitchin Submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements of the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy. 1 The Theatre of Death: the Uncanny in Mimesis (Abstract) The aim of this thesis is to explore an heuristic analogy as proposed in its very title: how does a concept of the “uncanny in mimesis” and of the “theatre of death” give content to each other – historically and theoretically – as distinct from the one providing either a description of, or even a metaphor for, the other? Thus, while the title for this concept of theatre derives from an eponymous manifesto of Tadeusz Kantor’s, the thesis does not aim to explain what the concept might mean in this historically specific instance only. Rather, it aims to develop a comparative analysis, through the question of mimesis, allowing for different theatre artists to be related within what will be proposed as a “minor” tradition of modernist art theatre (that “of death”). This comparative enquiry – into theatre practices conceived of in terms of the relation between abstraction and empathy, in which the “model” for the actor is seen in mannequins, puppets, or effigies – is developed through such questions as the following: What difference does it make to the concept of “theatre” when thought of in terms “of death”? What thought of mimesis do the dead admit of? How has this been figured, historically, in aesthetics? How does an art of theatre participate
    [Show full text]
  • I HEGEL's LOGIC of ABSOLUTE IDEALISM and HIS POLITICAL
    HEGEL’S LOGIC OF ABSOLUTE IDEALISM AND HIS POLITICAL ARGUMENT: THE CONCEPTUALITY OF ACTUALITY A Dissertation Submitted to the Temple University Graduate Board in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY by Matthew J. Smetona May, 2010 Examining Committee Members: Aryeh Botwinick, Advisory Chair, Political Science Joseph M. Schwartz, Political Science Carol C. Gould, Philosophy and Political Science Joseph Margolis, External Member, Philosophy i © by Matthew J. Smetona 2010 All Rights Reserved ii ABSTRACT Title: Hegel’s Logic of Absolute Idealism and his Political Argument: The Conceptuality of Actuality Candidate’s Name: Matthew J. Smetona Degree: Doctor of Philosophy Temple University, 2010 Doctoral Advisory Committee Chair: Aryeh Botwinick This dissertation is about the theoretical foundation of Hegel’s political argument. Its goal is to comprehend the basic structure of that argument by articulating the conceptual framework Hegel employs when he asserts that the particular set of political institutions he is arguing for is rational. Its argument is that the criterion Hegel employs in his conception of rationality is that an object is rational if and only if it is comprehended by thought in and through the holistic inferential system of concepts he refers to as the Concept ( der Begriff ). Hegel’s final argument in the Science of Logic is that there can be no actual object that is not “rational,” i.e., that is not constituted, in all of its determinations, by the unified activity of thinking that is the Concept. Consequently, it is argued that the rationality, and therewith the actuality, of Hegel’s rational state depicted in the Philosophy of Right derives from the fact that it is comprehended by thought in and through the totality as thought that is the Concept.
    [Show full text]
  • Epistemology and Ontology in Frege and Peirce: on Thoughts and Generals* Epistemologia E Ontologia Em Frege E Peirce: Sobre Pensamentos E Gerais
    Epistemology and Ontology in Frege and Peirce: On Thoughts and Generals* Epistemologia e Ontologia em Frege e Peirce: Sobre Pensamentos e Gerais Maria Uxía Rivas Monroy Departamento de Lóxica e Filosofía Moral Faculdade de Filosofía Universidade de Santiago de Compostela – USC, España [email protected] Abstract: The main aim of this paper is to compare the refl ections by Frege and Peirce with respect to the ontology and epistemology of some abstract entities or abstract elements, namely, Fregean thoughts and Peircean generals. The reason for this comparison is that they have given distinct answers to similar epistemological and ontological problems. Therefore, the paper will concentrate basically on the importance given by them to abstract entities or abstract features, and on the ontological position they have taken in regards to them, and which were motivated by their interests in science and in the justifi cation of scientifi c knowledge. The paper will also analyse the different roles that language and representation systems play in Frege’s and Peirce’s refl ections with respect to these abstract elements or entities, favouring Peirce’s position, which did not separate ontology from epistemology, and, therefore, it is not committed to the Platonism Frege was led to. Keywords: Abstract entities. Epistemology. Frege. Fregean thoughts. Generals. Ontology. Peirce. Resumo: O objetivo principal deste trabalho é comparar as refl exões de Frege e Peirce em relação à ontologia e à epistemologia de algumas entidades abstratas ou elementos abstratos, a saber, os pensamentos fregianos e os gerais Peircianos. A razão para essa comparação é que eles deram respostas distintas para problemas epistemológicos e ontológicos similares.
    [Show full text]
  • Rafael Ferber Key Concepts in Philosophy
    Rafael Ferber Key Concepts in Philosophy Rafael Ferber Key Concepts in Philosophy An Introduction Translated from German by Ladislaus Löb Academia Verlag Sankt Augustin Originaltitel: Philosophische Grundbegriffe (82008), © Verlag C. H. Beck oHG, München Bibliografische Information der Deutschen Bibliothek Die Deutsche Bibliothek verzeichnet diese Publikation in der Deutschen Nationalbibliografie; detaillierte bibliografische Daten sind im Internet über http://dnb.ddb.de abrufbar. ISBN 978-3-89665-648-3 © Academia Verlag 2015 Bahnstraße 7, D-53757 Sankt Augustin Internet: www.academia-verlag.de E-Mail: [email protected] Printed in Germany Alle Rechte vorbehalten Ohne schriftliche Genehmigung des Verlages ist es nicht gestattet, das Werk unter Verwendung mechanischer, elektronischer und anderer Systeme in irgendeiner Weise zu verarbeiten und zu verbreiten. Insbesondere vorbehalten sind die Rechte der Vervielfältigung – auch von Teilen des Werkes – auf fotomechanischem oder ähnlichem Wege, der tontechnischen Wiedergabe, des Vortrags, der Funk- und Fernsehsendung, der Speicherung in Datenverarbeitungsanlagen, der Übersetzung und der literarischen und anderweitigen Bearbeitung. Table of Contents 5 Contents Preface ................................................................................ 11 Preface to the English Translation .................................. 12 I. Philosophy 1. The Beginning in the Cave ........................................ 15 2. Word and Concept ..................................................... 17 3.
    [Show full text]
  • The Search Jor Logically Alien Thought: Descartes, Kant, Frege, and the Tractatus1
    PHILOSOPHICAL TOPICS VOL. 20 NO. 1, FALL 1991 The Search Jor Logically Alien Thought: Descartes, Kant, Frege, and the Tractatus1 James Conant University ofPittsburgh [I]n order to draw a limit to thought we should have to be able to think both sides ofthis limit (we should there­ fore have to be able to think what cannot be thought). The limit can, therefore, only be drawn in language and what lies on the other side ofthe limit will be sim­ ply nonsense. -Ludwig Wittgenstein2 The only proper way to break an egg is from the inside. -Parva Gallina Rubra3 This essay is about three things: Wittgenstein's ideas conceming the question of the possibility of illogical thought, the sources of those ideas (especially in Kant and Frege), and Putnam's recent interest in both of these matters. Along the way, this paper briefly sketches the broad outlines of two almost parallel traditions ofthought about the laws oflogic: one rather long and complicated tradition called the History of Modem Philosophy, and one rather short and complicated one called Hilary Putnam. Here is a thumb­ nail version ofhow these two traditions align: Descartes thought the laws of logic were only contingently necessary; not so recent Putnam agreed. 8t. Thomas Aquinas believed that they were necessarily necessary; relatively recent Putnam agreed (this is only confusing ifyou think Aquinas should not 115 be a step ahead of Descartes). Kant thought they were simply necessary. Frege wanted to agree-but his manner of doing so raised the worry that there was no way in which to express his agreement that made sense.
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz™ Metaphysics of Intentionality
    LEIBNIZ’ METAPHYSICS OF INTENTIONALITY JONATHAN CHARLES REYNOLD HILL (BA (HONS), M PHIL (OXON)) A THESIS SUBMITTED FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY NATIONAL UNIVERSITY OF SINGAPORE 2008 i Contents Summary iii 1 Introduction 1 2 The medieval philosophers 15 The “package” 15 Thomas Aquinas 19 Henry of Ghent 49 John Duns Scotus 62 Conclusion 87 3 Leibniz and relations 89 Reducibility, reality, and the nature of rewriting projects 90 The rewriting project 108 Inter-substantial relations and relational properties 125 Extrinsic denominations 138 Incompossibility 145 Inter-relatedness and isolationism 152 Conclusion 161 4 Leibniz’ theory of ideas 163 Ideas – realism or nominalism? 166 Ideas as dispositions 170 Ideas as objects 178 God and human ideas 182 Ideas in the mind of God 187 Possible creatures and sin 195 God and creatures: analogy and disanalogy 209 Logical and causal dependence 211 Conclusion 214 5 Concepts and definitions in Leibniz 216 Concepts, ideas, and possibilities 216 Concepts and the predicate-in-notion principle 223 Concepts and definitions 228 Concepts and essences 238 Essences and individuals 247 Actual and possible existence 249 Concepts and relations 273 ii 6 Perception, cognition, and intentionality in Leibniz 281 Direct and indirect objects 281 Representation 292 Causation 309 Sensation and cognition 317 The objects of sensation and cognition 335 Conclusion 343 Bibliography 348 iii Summary In this thesis, I consider Leibniz’ views on intentionality, and their relation to his metaphysics and particularly his views on relations. I focus in particular on how Leibniz’ theory can be understood in the light of his scholastic influences.
    [Show full text]