2019 Winter Meeting of the Association for Symbolic Logic
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Load more
Recommended publications
-
Russell's 1903 – 1905 Anticipation of the Lambda Calculus
HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC, 24 (2003), 15–37 Russell’s 1903 – 1905 Anticipation of the Lambda Calculus KEVIN C. KLEMENT Philosophy Dept, Univ. of Massachusetts, 352 Bartlett Hall, 130 Hicks Way, Amherst, MA 01003, USA Received 22 July 2002 It is well known that the circumflex notation used by Russell and Whitehead to form complex function names in Principia Mathematica played a role in inspiring Alonzo Church’s ‘Lambda Calculus’ for functional logic developed in the 1920s and 1930s. Interestingly, earlier unpublished manuscripts written by Russell between 1903 and 1905—surely unknown to Church—contain a more extensive anticipation of the essential details of the Lambda Calculus. Russell also anticipated Scho¨ nfinkel’s Combinatory Logic approach of treating multi- argument functions as functions having other functions as value. Russell’s work in this regard seems to have been largely inspired by Frege’s theory of functions and ‘value-ranges’. This system was discarded by Russell due to his abandonment of propositional functions as genuine entities as part of a new tack for solving Rus- sell’s paradox. In this article, I explore the genesis and demise of Russell’s early anticipation of the Lambda Calculus. 1. Introduction The Lambda Calculus, as we know it today, was initially developed by Alonzo Church in the late 1920s and 1930s (see, e.g. Church 1932, 1940, 1941, Church and Rosser 1936), although it built heavily on work done by others, perhaps most notably, the early works on Combinatory Logic by Moses Scho¨ nfinkel (see, e.g. his 1924) and Haskell Curry (see, e.g. -
Recent Work in Relevant Logic
Recent Work in Relevant Logic Mark Jago Forthcoming in Analysis. Draft of April 2013. 1 Introduction Relevant logics are a group of logics which attempt to block irrelevant conclusions being drawn from a set of premises. The following inferences are all valid in classical logic, where A and B are any sentences whatsoever: • from A, one may infer B → A, B → B and B ∨ ¬B; • from ¬A, one may infer A → B; and • from A ∧ ¬A, one may infer B. But if A and B are utterly irrelevant to one another, many feel reluctant to call these inferences acceptable. Similarly for the validity of the corresponding material implications, often called ‘paradoxes’ of material implication. Relevant logic can be seen as the attempt to avoid these ‘paradoxes’. Relevant logic has a long history. Key early works include Anderson and Belnap 1962; 1963; 1975, and many important results appear in Routley et al. 1982. Those looking for a short introduction to relevant logics might look at Mares 2012 or Priest 2008. For a more detailed but still accessible introduction, there’s Dunn and Restall 2002; Mares 2004b; Priest 2008 and Read 1988. The aim of this article is to survey some of the most important work in the eld in the past ten years, in a way that I hope will be of interest to a philosophical audience. Much of this recent work has been of a formal nature. I will try to outline these technical developments, and convey something of their importance, with the minimum of technical jargon. A good deal of this recent technical work concerns how quantiers should work in relevant logic. -
Haskell Before Haskell. an Alternative Lesson in Practical Logics of the ENIAC.∗
Haskell before Haskell. An alternative lesson in practical logics of the ENIAC.∗ Liesbeth De Mol† Martin Carl´e‡ Maarten Bullynck§ January 21, 2011 Abstract This article expands on Curry’s work on how to implement the prob- lem of inverse interpolation on the ENIAC (1946) and his subsequent work on developing a theory of program composition (1948-1950). It is shown that Curry’s hands-on experience with the ENIAC on the one side and his acquaintance with systems of formal logic on the other, were conduc- tive to conceive a compact “notation for program construction” which in turn would be instrumental to a mechanical synthesis of programs. Since Curry’s systematic programming technique pronounces a critique of the Goldstine-von Neumann style of coding, his “calculus of program com- position”not only anticipates automatic programming but also proposes explicit hardware optimisations largely unperceived by computer history until Backus famous ACM Turing Award lecture (1977). This article frames Haskell B. Curry’s development of a general approach to programming. Curry’s work grew out of his experience with the ENIAC in 1946, took shape by his background as a logician and finally materialised into two lengthy reports (1948 and 1949) that describe what Curry called the ‘composition of programs’. Following up to the concise exposition of Curry’s approach that we gave in [28], we now elaborate on technical details, such as diagrams, tables and compiler-like procedures described in Curry’s reports. We also give a more in-depth discussion of the transition from Curry’s concrete, ‘hands-on’ experience with the ENIAC to a general theory of combining pro- grams in contrast to the Goldstine-von Neumann method of tackling the “coding and planning of problems” [18] for computers with the help of ‘flow-charts’. -
Relevant and Substructural Logics
Relevant and Substructural Logics GREG RESTALL∗ PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT, MACQUARIE UNIVERSITY [email protected] June 23, 2001 http://www.phil.mq.edu.au/staff/grestall/ Abstract: This is a history of relevant and substructural logics, written for the Hand- book of the History and Philosophy of Logic, edited by Dov Gabbay and John Woods.1 1 Introduction Logics tend to be viewed of in one of two ways — with an eye to proofs, or with an eye to models.2 Relevant and substructural logics are no different: you can focus on notions of proof, inference rules and structural features of deduction in these logics, or you can focus on interpretations of the language in other structures. This essay is structured around the bifurcation between proofs and mod- els: The first section discusses Proof Theory of relevant and substructural log- ics, and the second covers the Model Theory of these logics. This order is a natural one for a history of relevant and substructural logics, because much of the initial work — especially in the Anderson–Belnap tradition of relevant logics — started by developing proof theory. The model theory of relevant logic came some time later. As we will see, Dunn's algebraic models [76, 77] Urquhart's operational semantics [267, 268] and Routley and Meyer's rela- tional semantics [239, 240, 241] arrived decades after the initial burst of ac- tivity from Alan Anderson and Nuel Belnap. The same goes for work on the Lambek calculus: although inspired by a very particular application in lin- guistic typing, it was developed first proof-theoretically, and only later did model theory come to the fore. -
Consequence and Degrees of Truth in Many-Valued Logic
Consequence and degrees of truth in many-valued logic Josep Maria Font Published as Chapter 6 (pp. 117–142) of: Peter Hájek on Mathematical Fuzzy Logic (F. Montagna, ed.) vol. 6 of Outstanding Contributions to Logic, Springer-Verlag, 2015 Abstract I argue that the definition of a logic by preservation of all degrees of truth is a better rendering of Bolzano’s idea of consequence as truth- preserving when “truth comes in degrees”, as is often said in many-valued contexts, than the usual scheme that preserves only one truth value. I review some results recently obtained in the investigation of this proposal by applying techniques of abstract algebraic logic in the framework of Łukasiewicz logics and in the broader framework of substructural logics, that is, logics defined by varieties of (commutative and integral) residuated lattices. I also review some scattered, early results, which have appeared since the 1970’s, and make some proposals for further research. Keywords: many-valued logic, mathematical fuzzy logic, truth val- ues, truth degrees, logics preserving degrees of truth, residuated lattices, substructural logics, abstract algebraic logic, Leibniz hierarchy, Frege hierarchy. Contents 6.1 Introduction .............................2 6.2 Some motivation and some history ...............3 6.3 The Łukasiewicz case ........................8 6.4 Widening the scope: fuzzy and substructural logics ....9 6.5 Abstract algebraic logic classification ............. 12 6.6 The Deduction Theorem ..................... 16 6.7 Axiomatizations ........................... 18 6.7.1 In the Gentzen style . 18 6.7.2 In the Hilbert style . 19 6.8 Conclusions .............................. 21 References .................................. 23 1 6.1 Introduction Let me begin by calling your attention to one of the main points made by Petr Hájek in the introductory, vindicating section of his influential book [34] (the italics are his): «Logic studies the notion(s) of consequence. -
Applications of Non-Classical Logic Andrew Tedder University of Connecticut - Storrs, [email protected]
University of Connecticut OpenCommons@UConn Doctoral Dissertations University of Connecticut Graduate School 8-8-2018 Applications of Non-Classical Logic Andrew Tedder University of Connecticut - Storrs, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://opencommons.uconn.edu/dissertations Recommended Citation Tedder, Andrew, "Applications of Non-Classical Logic" (2018). Doctoral Dissertations. 1930. https://opencommons.uconn.edu/dissertations/1930 Applications of Non-Classical Logic Andrew Tedder University of Connecticut, 2018 ABSTRACT This dissertation is composed of three projects applying non-classical logic to problems in history of philosophy and philosophy of logic. The main component concerns Descartes’ Creation Doctrine (CD) – the doctrine that while truths concerning the essences of objects (eternal truths) are necessary, God had vol- untary control over their creation, and thus could have made them false. First, I show a flaw in a standard argument for two interpretations of CD. This argument, stated in terms of non-normal modal logics, involves a set of premises which lead to a conclusion which Descartes explicitly rejects. Following this, I develop a multimodal account of CD, ac- cording to which Descartes is committed to two kinds of modality, and that the apparent contradiction resulting from CD is the result of an ambiguity. Finally, I begin to develop two modal logics capturing the key ideas in the multi-modal interpretation, and provide some metatheoretic results concerning these logics which shore up some of my interpretive claims. The second component is a project concerning the Channel Theoretic interpretation of the ternary relation semantics of relevant and substructural logics. Following Barwise, I de- velop a representation of Channel Composition, and prove that extending the implication- conjunction fragment of B by composite channels is conservative. -
Strategic Maneuvering in Mathematical Proofs
CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by Springer - Publisher Connector Argumentation (2008) 22:453–468 DOI 10.1007/s10503-008-9098-7 Strategic Maneuvering in Mathematical Proofs Erik C. W. Krabbe Published online: 6 May 2008 Ó The Author(s) 2008 Abstract This paper explores applications of concepts from argumentation theory to mathematical proofs. Note is taken of the various contexts in which proofs occur and of the various objectives they may serve. Examples of strategic maneuvering are discussed when surveying, in proofs, the four stages of argumentation distin- guished by pragma-dialectics. Derailments of strategies (fallacies) are seen to encompass more than logical fallacies and to occur both in alleged proofs that are completely out of bounds and in alleged proofs that are at least mathematical arguments. These considerations lead to a dialectical and rhetorical view of proofs. Keywords Argumentation Á Blunder Á Fallacy Á False proof Á Mathematics Á Meno Á Pragma-dialectics Á Proof Á Saccheri Á Strategic maneuvering Á Tarski 1 Introduction The purport of this paper1 is to show that concepts from argumentation theory can be fruitfully applied to contexts of mathematical proof. As a source for concepts to be tested I turn to pragma-dialectics: both to the Standard Theory and to the Integrated Theory. The Standard Theory has been around for a long time and achieved its final formulation in 2004 (Van Eemeren and Grootendorst 1984, 1992, 2004). According to the Standard Theory argumentation is a communication process aiming at 1 The paper was first presented at the NWO-conference on ‘‘Strategic Manoeuvring in Institutionalised Contexts’’, University of Amsterdam, 26 October 2007. -
Lecture 3 Relevant Logics
Lecture 3 Relevant logics Michael De [email protected] Heinrich Heine Universit¨atD¨usseldorf 22.07.2015 [1/17] Relevant logic [2/17] Relevance Witness some paradoxes of material implication: A ⊃ (B ⊃ A); A ⊃ (:A ! B); (A ^ :A) ⊃ B; A ⊃ (B _:B): Some instances seem absurd because for of lack of relevance between antecedent and consequent, as in If Peter likes pretzels, then Barcelona's in Spain or it isn't. Relevance logics originated from a desire to make right what is wrong with material implication: to formalize a conditional that does not endorse fallacies of relevance. [3/17] A brief history of relevance logic The magnum opus of relevance logic is Entailment Volumes 1 (1975) and 2 (1992) of Anderson and Belnap (and numerous coauthors). They expand on the work of Wilhelm Ackermann who, in 1956, published work on a theory of strengen Implikation. Relevance logic has grown into a rich and fascinating discipline. It has been mainly worked on by Australians and Americans, each working in their own style (Americans preferring many-valued world semantics, Australians two-valued world semantics). An introduction can be found on SEP (click here). But the introduction of Entailment Vol. 1 is an excellent|even entertaining!|read. [4/17] Anderson & Belnap on relevance We argue below that one of the principal merits of his system of strengen Implikation is that it, and its neighbors, give us for the first time a mathematically satisfactory way of grasping the elusive notion of relevance of antecedent to consequent in \if ... then|" propositions; such is the topic of this book. -
Hunting the Story of Moses Schönfinkel
Where Did Combinators Come From? Hunting the Story of Moses Schönfinkel Stephen Wolfram* Combinators were a key idea in the development of mathematical logic and the emergence of the concept of universal computation. They were introduced on December 7, 1920, by Moses Schönfinkel. This is an exploration of the personal story and intellectual context of Moses Schönfinkel, including extensive new research based on primary sources. December 7, 1920 On Tuesday, December 7, 1920, the Göttingen Mathematics Society held its regular weekly meeting—at which a 32-year-old local mathematician named Moses Schönfinkel with no known previous mathematical publications gave a talk entitled “Elemente der Logik” (“Elements of Logic”). This piece is included in S. Wolfram (2021), Combinators: A Centennial View, Wolfram Media. (wolframmedia.com/products/combinators-a-centennial-view.html) and accompanies arXiv:2103.12811 and arXiv:2102.09658. Originally published December 7, 2020 *Email: [email protected] 2 | Stephen Wolfram A hundred years later what was presented in that talk still seems in many ways alien and futuristic—and for most people almost irreducibly abstract. But we now realize that that talk gave the first complete formalism for what is probably the single most important idea of this past century: the idea of universal computation. Sixteen years later would come Turing machines (and lambda calculus). But in 1920 Moses Schönfinkel presented what he called “building blocks of logic”—or what we now call “combinators”—and then proceeded to show that by appropriately combining them one could effectively define any function, or, in modern terms, that they could be used to do universal computation. -
Common Sense for Concurrency and Strong Paraconsistency Using Unstratified Inference and Reflection
Published in ArXiv http://arxiv.org/abs/0812.4852 http://commonsense.carlhewitt.info Common sense for concurrency and strong paraconsistency using unstratified inference and reflection Carl Hewitt http://carlhewitt.info This paper is dedicated to John McCarthy. Abstract Unstratified Reflection is the Norm....................................... 11 Abstraction and Reification .............................................. 11 This paper develops a strongly paraconsistent formalism (called Direct Logic™) that incorporates the mathematics of Diagonal Argument .......................................................... 12 Computer Science and allows unstratified inference and Logical Fixed Point Theorem ........................................... 12 reflection using mathematical induction for almost all of Disadvantages of stratified metatheories ........................... 12 classical logic to be used. Direct Logic allows mutual Reification Reflection ....................................................... 13 reflection among the mutually chock full of inconsistencies Incompleteness Theorem for Theories of Direct Logic ..... 14 code, documentation, and use cases of large software systems Inconsistency Theorem for Theories of Direct Logic ........ 15 thereby overcoming the limitations of the traditional Tarskian Consequences of Logically Necessary Inconsistency ........ 16 framework of stratified metatheories. Concurrency is the Norm ...................................................... 16 Gödel first formalized and proved that it is not possible -
CURRY, Haskell Brooks (1900–1982) Haskell Brooks Curry Was Born On
CURRY, Haskell Brooks (1900–1982) Haskell Brooks Curry was born on 12 September 1900 at Millis, Massachusetts and died on 1 September 1982 at State College, Pennsylvania. His parents were Samuel Silas Curry and Anna Baright Curry, founders of the School for Expression in Boston, now known as Curry College. He graduated from high school in 1916 and entered Harvard College with the intention of going into medicine. When the USA entered World War I in 1917, he changed his major to mathematics because he thought it might be useful for military purposes in the artillery. He also joined the Student Army Training Corps on 18 October 1918, but the war ended before he saw action. He received his B.A. in mathematics from Harvard University in 1920. From 1920 until 1922, he studied electrical engineering at MIT in a program that involved working half-time at the General Electric Company. From 1922 until 1924, he studied physics at Harvard; during the first of those two years he was a half-time research assistant to P. W. Bridgman, and in 1924 he received an A. M. in physics. He then studied mathematics, still at Harvard, until 1927; during the first semester of 1926–27 he was a half-time instructor. During 1927–28 he was an instructor at Princeton University. During 1928–29, he studied at the University of Göttingen, where he wrote his doctoral dissertation; his oral defense under David Hilbert was on 24 July 1929, although the published version carries the date of 1930. In the fall of 1929, Haskell Curry joined the faculty of The Pennsylvania State College (now The Pennsylvania State University), where he spent most of the rest of his career. -
The Systems of Relevance Logic
ARGUMENT Vol. 1 1/2011 pp. 87–102 The Systems of Relevance Logic Ryszard MIREK Kraków ABSTRACT The system R, or more precisely the pure implicational fragment R →, is considered by the relevance logicians as the most important. The another central system of relevance logic has been the logic E of entailment that was supposed to capture strict relevant implication. The next system of relevance logic is RM or R-mingle. The question is whether adding mingle axiom to R → yields the pure implicational fragment RM → of the system? As concerns the weak systems there are at least two approaches to the problem. First of all, it is possible to restrict a validity of some theorems. In another approach we can investigate even weaker log- ics which have no theorems and are characterized only by rules of deducibility. 1. ThE SySTEM oF NATURAl DEDUCTIoN The central point of relevant logicians has been to avoid the paradoxes of material and strict implication. In other words, according to them, the heart of logic lies in the notion “if […] then [...]”. Among the material paradoxes the following are known: M1. α → (β → α) (positive paradox); M2. ~ α → (α → β); M3. (α → β) ∨ (β → α); M4. (α → β) ∨ (β → γ). In turn, among the strict paradoxes there are known the following: S1. α → (β → β); S2. α → (β ∨ ~ β); S3. (α ∧ ¬ α) → β (ex falso quodlibet). www.argument-journal.eu 88 Ryszard MIREK Relevance logicians have claimed that these theses are counterintui- tive. According to them, in each of them the antecedent seems irrelevant to the consequent.