Origins of Generic Point in Algebraic Geometry and Mathematical Practice

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Origins of Generic Point in Algebraic Geometry and Mathematical Practice UNIVERSIDADE ESTADUAL DE CAMPINAS Instituto de Filosofia e Ciências Humanas Renato Reis Leme Origens do ponto genérico em geometria algébrica e na prática matemática Origins of generic point in algebraic geometry and mathematical practice CAMPINAS 2020 Renato Reis Leme Origins of generic point in algebraic geometry and mathematical practice Origens do ponto genérico em geometria algébrica e na prática matemática Dissertação apresentada ao Instituto de Filosofia e Ciências Humanas da Universidade Estadual de Campinas como parte dos req- uisitos exigidos para a obtenção do título de Mestre em Filosofia. Dissertation presented to the Institute of Philosophy and Human Sciences of the Uni- versity of Campinas in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Philosophy. Supervisor/Orientador: Giorgio Venturi ESTE TRABALHO CORRESPONDE À VER- SÃO FINAL DA DISSERTAÇÃO DEFENDIDA PELO ALUNO RENATO REIS LEME, E ORI- ENTADA PELO PROF. DR. GIORGIO VEN- TURI. Campinas 2020 Ficha catalográfica Universidade Estadual de Campinas Biblioteca do Instituto de Filosofia e Ciências Humanas Cecília Maria Jorge Nicolau - CRB 8/3387 Leme, Renato Reis, 1993- L542o LemOrigins of generic point in algebraic geometry and mathematical practice / Renato Reis Leme. – Campinas, SP : [s.n.], 2020. LemOrientador: Giorgio Venturi. LemDissertação (mestrado) – Universidade Estadual de Campinas, Instituto de Filosofia e Ciências Humanas. Lem1. Lógica simbólica e matemática. 2. Geometria algébrica. 3. Matemática - História. 4. Matemática - Filosofia. I. Venturi, Giorgio, 1983-. II. Universidade Estadual de Campinas. Instituto de Filosofia e Ciências Humanas. III. Título. Informações para Biblioteca Digital Título em outro idioma: Origens do ponto genérico em geometria algébrica e na prática matemática Palavras-chave em inglês: Logic, symbolic and mathematical Algebraic geometry Mathematics - History Mathematics - Philosophy Área de concentração: Filosofia Titulação: Mestre em Filosofia Banca examinadora: Giorgio Venturi [Orientador] Rodrigo de Alvarenga Freire Bruno Ramos Mendonça Data de defesa: 18-12-2020 Programa de Pós-Graduação: Filosofia Identificação e informações acadêmicas do(a) aluno(a) - ORCID do autor: https://orcid.org/0000-0001-8199-1261 - Currículo Lattes do autor: http://buscatextual.cnpq.br/buscatextual/visu Powered by TCPDF (www.tcpdf.org) Universidade Estadual de Campinas Instituto de Filosofia e Ciências Humanas A Comissão Julgadora dos trabalhos de Defesa de Dissertação de Mes- trado, composta pelos Professores Doutores a seguir descritos, em sessão pública realizada em 18/12/2020, considerou o candidato Renato Reis Leme aprovado. Prof Dr Giorgio Venturi Prof Dr Rodrigo de Alvarenga Freire Prof Dr Bruno Ramos Mendonça A Ata de Defesa com as respectivas assinaturas dos membros encontra-se no SIGA/Sistema de Fluxo de Dissertações/Teses e na Secretaria do Pro- grama de Pós-Graduação em Filosofia do Instituto de Filosofia e Ciências Humanas. To The Timeless Agradecimentos Agradeço ao meu orientador Giorgio Venturi pelas aulas, reuniões de orientação e, acima de tudo, pelo exemplo de pesquisador. Agradeço aos colegas do grupo de pesquisa Edson Bezerra, João Vitor Schmidt, Pedro Yago e Santiago Jockwich, e aos colegas do IMECC Fábio Meneghetti e Vinícius Vasconcelos pelas discussões que ajudaram a dissipar dúvidas e desbravar o caminho, por vezes tortuoso, das ideias. Agradeço aos membros da banca pela cuidadosa leitura e valiosas sugestões, sem as quais este trabalho não estaria completo. Agradeço a Jessica Andrade por me fazer acreditar que sempre posso mais, e a minha família pelo apoio incondicional que, nos piores momentos, fez saber que não estou sozinho. Agradeço a todos os funcionários do IFCH pelo profissionalismo e prestatividade tão importantes para o dia a dia do Instituto. Agradeço a todos os professores e funcionários do CLE por preservarem e manterem vivo e atuante este centro de excelência de pesquisa em Lógica. Por fim, agradeço a Fundação de Amparo à Pesquisa do Estado de São Paulo (FAPESP, processo nº 19/01580-7) pelo fundamental apoio financeiro ao longo da condução desta pesquisa. Resumo O presente trabalho explora o fenômeno da genericidade e suas conexões em três eixos centrais: histórico, filosófico e lógico. No capítulo histórico deste trabalho, é apresentado o desenvolvimento da noção de genericidade desde suas origens no pensamento ocidental até a emergência do conceito de ponto genérico em geometria algébrica. No capítulo filosófico, partindo da crítica fregeana aos objetos variáveis na matemática, é avaliada a relação entre genericidade e arbitrariedade. Por fim, no capítulo lógico, mostramos a conexão entre gene- ricidade e possibilidade a partir da semântica topológica de McKinsey-Tarski para o cálculo modal 푆4. Palavras-chave: Lógica simbólica e matemática, Geometria algébrica, Matemática - História, Matemática - Filosofia. Abstract The present work explores genericity phenomena and its connections over three central axis: historical, philosophical and logical. In the historical chapter of this work, the devel- opment of the notion of genericity is presented from its origins in Western thought to the emergence of the concept of generic point in algebraic geometry. In the philosophical chapter, based on the Fregean critique of variable objects in mathematics, the relation between gener- icity and arbitrariness is evaluated. Finally, in the logical chapter, we show the connection between genericity and possibility based on McKinsey-Tarski’s topological semantics for the modal calculus 푆4. Keywords: Logic symbolic and mathematical, Algebraic geometry, Mathematics - His- tory, Mathematics - Philosophy. List of Figures 1.1 Our metaphysical target. 14 1.2 Our six-sided die. 15 2.1 Plato’s square. 20 2.2 An artist drawing with his perspective machinery. “Man drawing a Lute” – By Albrecht Dürer (1530)............................. 22 2.3 A circle of radius equal to 1 illustrating Descartes concept of coordinated system. 23 2.4 Vanishing point at the horizon. 25 2.5 Photo taken in July 1935, during the first official conference of Bourbaki, in Besse-et-Saint-Anastaise. Standing, from left to right: Henri Cartan, René de Possel, Jean Dieudonné, André Weil and Luc Olivier. Sitting, from left to right: a “guinea pig” called Mirles, Claude Chevalley and Szolem Mandelbrojt. 28 2.6 푆푝푒푐(Z). See Mumford [7]. 33 2.7 Mumford’s arithmetic surface........................... 34 3.1 A topological space with generic point. 40 3.2 Begriffsschrift language. 46 3.3 (((퐴 → 퐵) → 퐴) → 퐴) [Peirce’s law] . 47 3.4 A topological representation of 휔휔........................ 51 4.1 Topological spaces. Examples from Mumkres [17]. 57 4.2 Graph representation of generic classes. 61 4.3 Plots of the subspaces generated by the power-set of arbitrary sets with cardi- nality equals to 2, 3, 4, 5 and 6, respectively, all filtered generic sets and they ideal counterpart. 62 Contents 1 Introduction 12 1.0.1 Generic property . 13 2 From Plato to Weil and beyond: Genericity through the history of math- ematics 16 2.1 Introduction . 17 2.2 An ancient dual . 18 2.3 The renaissance of geometry . 22 2.4 Italian school of algebraic geometry . 24 2.5 Foundations reframed . 27 2.5.1 Bourbaki and the struggle for formal refinements . 28 2.5.2 The generic point find its definition . 30 2.6 Beyond foundations . 31 2.6.1 On how generic points looks like . 33 2.7 Conclusion . 35 3 Genericity and arbitrariness 36 3.1 Genericity . 37 3.2 Arbitrariness . 40 3.2.1 Frege’s target . 43 3.3 Structuralist theories of arbitrariness . 48 3.3.1 Arbitrary as function . 49 3.3.2 Aribtrary as generic . 52 4 A logic for genericity 55 4.1 Genericity in mathematics . 55 4.1.1 Generic points . 56 4.1.2 Generic points in (푋, 풫(푋)) ....................... 58 4.1.3 Combinatorial properties . 61 4.2 Generic propositions . 63 4.2.1 Boolean model for generic proposition . 63 4.2.2 S4 logic . 63 4.3 Tying things up . 66 5 Conclusion 68 References 69 A Isabelle Proof of Inf Theorem 71 B Isabelle Proof of Sup Theorem 72 C A PC-Begriffsschrift translator 73 12 Chapter 1 Introduction The limits of my language mean the limits of my world. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, 5.6 Since the dawn of human language, genericity has been employed by those who wants to communicate a plethora of things by sign only a single one. In an attempt to differentiate this from mere ambiguity, this linguistical phenomenon has been analyzed by several theories. Because it is useful, we cannot set that apart from our expressivity apparatus. Now, we try to understand how it works. In natural language, genericity often comes with a certain puzzlement. Consider the following generic sentences, taken from [18]: (i) Ravens are black. (ii) Frenchmen eat horsemeat. (iii) Prime numbers are odd. As Nickel observes, if we take generic to be true “just in case at least one member of the kind conforms to it”, then we would take it right in (푖) and (푖푖), but would make a mistake in the case of (푖푖푖), which we would say that is true. On the other hand, if we say that generic is true if, and only if, most members of the kind conform to it, then we would predict rightly in the case of (푖) and (푖푖푖), but wrongly in the case of (푖푖). Both ways entails problems, which is a clue that generic sentences should not be saw as a proposition that hiddes a fixed form. In the Introduction of [16], the authors traces a difference between three types of research on genericity: 13 Linguistic research on generics has developed in three primary directions. Some authors have focused on the generic interpretation of the subject DP. This research has mostly concentrated on the notion of kind and its pos- sible expression in natural languages. Other authors locate the sources of genericity in the VP. And a third group, starting from the assumption that genericity is a feature of the sentence rather than one of its components, have focused on the variety of generic readings of generic sentences.
Recommended publications
  • Arxiv:1708.06494V1 [Math.AG] 22 Aug 2017 Proof
    CLOSED POINTS ON SCHEMES JUSTIN CHEN Abstract. This brief note gives a survey on results relating to existence of closed points on schemes, including an elementary topological characterization of the schemes with (at least one) closed point. X Let X be a topological space. For a subset S ⊆ X, let S = S denote the closure of S in X. Recall that a topological space is sober if every irreducible closed subset has a unique generic point. The following is well-known: Proposition 1. Let X be a Noetherian sober topological space, and x ∈ X. Then {x} contains a closed point of X. Proof. If {x} = {x} then x is a closed point. Otherwise there exists x1 ∈ {x}\{x}, so {x} ⊇ {x1}. If x1 is not a closed point, then continuing in this way gives a descending chain of closed subsets {x} ⊇ {x1} ⊇ {x2} ⊇ ... which stabilizes to a closed subset Y since X is Noetherian. Then Y is the closure of any of its points, i.e. every point of Y is generic, so Y is irreducible. Since X is sober, Y is a singleton consisting of a closed point. Since schemes are sober, this shows in particular that any scheme whose under- lying topological space is Noetherian (e.g. any Noetherian scheme) has a closed point. In general, it is of basic importance to know that a scheme has closed points (or not). For instance, recall that every affine scheme has a closed point (indeed, this is equivalent to the axiom of choice). In this direction, one can give a simple topological characterization of the schemes with closed points.
    [Show full text]
  • 3 Lecture 3: Spectral Spaces and Constructible Sets
    3 Lecture 3: Spectral spaces and constructible sets 3.1 Introduction We want to analyze quasi-compactness properties of the valuation spectrum of a commutative ring, and to do so a digression on constructible sets is needed, especially to define the notion of constructibility in the absence of noetherian hypotheses. (This is crucial, since perfectoid spaces will not satisfy any kind of noetherian condition in general.) The reason that this generality is introduced in [EGA] is for the purpose of proving openness and closedness results on the locus of fibers satisfying reasonable properties, without imposing noetherian assumptions on the base. One first proves constructibility results on the base, often by deducing it from constructibility on the source and applying Chevalley’s theorem on images of constructible sets (which is valid for finitely presented morphisms), and then uses specialization criteria for constructible sets to be open. For our purposes, the role of constructibility will be quite different, resting on the interesting “constructible topology” that is introduced in [EGA, IV1, 1.9.11, 1.9.12] but not actually used later in [EGA]. This lecture is organized as follows. We first deal with the constructible topology on topological spaces. We discuss useful characterizations of constructibility in the case of spectral spaces, aiming for a criterion of Hochster (see Theorem 3.3.9) which will be our tool to show that Spv(A) is spectral, our ultimate goal. Notational convention. From now on, we shall write everywhere (except in some definitions) “qc” for “quasi-compact”, “qs” for “quasi-separated”, and “qcqs” for “quasi-compact and quasi-separated”.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is a Generic Point?
    Generic Point. Eric Brussel, Emory University We define and prove the existence of generic points of schemes, and prove that the irreducible components of any scheme correspond bijectively to the scheme's generic points, and every open subset of an irreducible scheme contains that scheme's unique generic point. All of this material is standard, and [Liu] is a great reference. Let X be a scheme. Recall X is irreducible if its underlying topological space is irre- ducible. A (nonempty) topological space is irreducible if it is not the union of two proper distinct closed subsets. Equivalently, if the intersection of any two nonempty open subsets is nonempty. Equivalently, if every nonempty open subset is dense. Since X is a scheme, there can exist points that are not closed. If x 2 X, we write fxg for the closure of x in X. This scheme is irreducible, since an open subset of fxg that doesn't contain x also doesn't contain any point of the closure of x, since the compliment of an open set is closed. Therefore every open subset of fxg contains x, and is (therefore) dense in fxg. Definition. ([Liu, 2.4.10]) A point x of X specializes to a point y of X if y 2 fxg. A point ξ 2 X is a generic point of X if ξ is the only point of X that specializes to ξ. Ring theoretic interpretation. If X = Spec A is an affine scheme for a ring A, so that every point x corresponds to a unique prime ideal px ⊂ A, then x specializes to y if and only if px ⊂ py, and a point ξ is generic if and only if pξ is minimal among prime ideals of A.
    [Show full text]
  • Generic Global Rigidity in Complex and Pseudo-Euclidean Spaces 3
    GENERIC GLOBAL RIGIDITY IN COMPLEX AND PSEUDO-EUCLIDEAN SPACES STEVEN J. GORTLER AND DYLAN P. THURSTON Abstract. In this paper we study the property of generic global rigidity for frameworks of graphs embedded in d-dimensional complex space and in a d-dimensional pseudo- Euclidean space (Rd with a metric of indefinite signature). We show that a graph is generically globally rigid in Euclidean space iff it is generically globally rigid in a complex or pseudo-Euclidean space. We also establish that global rigidity is always a generic property of a graph in complex space, and give a sufficient condition for it to be a generic property in a pseudo-Euclidean space. Extensions to hyperbolic space are also discussed. 1. Introduction The property of generic global rigidity of a graph in d-dimensional Euclidean space has recently been fully characterized [4, 7]. It is quite natural to study this property in other spaces as well. For example, recent work of Owen and Jackson [8] has studied the number of equivalent realizations of frameworks in C2. In this paper we study the property of generic global rigidity of graphs embedded in Cd as well as graphs embedded in a pseudo Euclidean space (Rd equipped with an indefinite metric signature). We show that a graph Γ is generically globally rigid (GGR) in d-dimensional Euclidean space iff Γ is GGR in d-dimensional complex space. Moreover, for any metric signature, s, We show that a graph Γ is GGR in d-dimensional Euclidean space iff Γ is GGR in d- dimensional real space under the signature s.
    [Show full text]
  • A Generic Property of the Bounded Syzygy Solutions Author(S): Florin N
    A Generic Property of the Bounded Syzygy Solutions Author(s): Florin N. Diacu Source: Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society, Vol. 116, No. 3 (Nov., 1992), pp. 809-812 Published by: American Mathematical Society Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2159450 Accessed: 16/11/2009 21:52 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ams. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. American Mathematical Society is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society. http://www.jstor.org PROCEEDINGS OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 116, Number 3, November 1992 A GENERIC PROPERTY OF THE BOUNDED SYZYGY SOLUTIONS FLORIN N.
    [Show full text]
  • DENINGER COHOMOLOGY THEORIES Readers Who Know What the Standard Conjectures Are Should Skip to Section 0.6. 0.1. Schemes. We
    DENINGER COHOMOLOGY THEORIES TAYLOR DUPUY Abstract. A brief explanation of Denninger's cohomological formalism which gives a conditional proof Riemann Hypothesis. These notes are based on a talk given in the University of New Mexico Geometry Seminar in Spring 2012. The notes are in the same spirit of Osserman and Ile's surveys of the Weil conjectures [Oss08] [Ile04]. Readers who know what the standard conjectures are should skip to section 0.6. 0.1. Schemes. We will use the following notation: CRing = Category of Commutative Rings with Unit; SchZ = Category of Schemes over Z; 2 Recall that there is a contravariant functor which assigns to every ring a space (scheme) CRing Sch A Spec A 2 Where Spec(A) = f primes ideals of A not including A where the closed sets are generated by the sets of the form V (f) = fP 2 Spec(A) : f(P) = 0g; f 2 A: By \f(P ) = 000 we means f ≡ 0 mod P . If X = Spec(A) we let jXj := closed points of X = maximal ideals of A i.e. x 2 jXj if and only if fxg = fxg. The overline here denote the closure of the set in the topology and a singleton in Spec(A) being closed is equivalent to x being a maximal ideal. 1 Another word for a closed point is a geometric point. If a point is not closed it is called generic, and the set of generic points are in one-to-one correspondence with closed subspaces where the associated closed subspace associated to a generic point x is fxg.
    [Show full text]
  • Lids-R-904 Robust Stability of Linear Systems
    LIDS-R-904 ROBUST STABILITY OF LINEAR SYSTEMS - SOME COMPUTATIONAL CONSIDERATIONS* by Alan J. Laub** 1. INTRODUCTION In this paper we shall concentrate on some of the computational issues which arise in studying the robust stability of linear systems. Insofar as possible, we shall use notation consistent with Stein's paper [11 and we shall make frequent reference to that work. As we saw in [1] a basic stability question for a linear time-invariant system with transfer matrix G(s) is the following: given that a nominal closed-loop feedbadk system is stable, does the feedback system remain stable when subjected to perturbations and how large can those perturba- tions be? It turned out, through invocation of the Nyquist Criterion, that the size of the allowable perturbations was related to the "nearness to singularity" of the return difference matrix I + G(jW). Closed-loop stability was said to be "robust" if G could tolerate considerable perturbation before I + G became singular. Invited Paper presented at the Second Annual Workshop on the Informa- tion Linkage between Applied Mathematics and Industry held at Naval Postgraduate School, Monterey, California, Feb. 20-24, 1979; this research was partially supported by NASA under grant NGL-22-009-124 and the Department of Energy under grant ET-78-(01-3395). ** Laboratory for Information and Decision Systems, Pm. 35-331, M.I.T., Cambridge, MA 02139. -2- We shall now indulge in a modicum of abstraction and attempt to formalize the notion of robustness. The definition will employ some jargon from algebraic geometry and will be applicable to a variety of situations.
    [Show full text]
  • Generic Flatness for Strongly Noetherian Algebras
    Journal of Algebra 221, 579–610 (1999) Article ID jabr.1999.7997, available online at http://www.idealibrary.com on Generic Flatness for Strongly Noetherian Algebras M. Artin* Department of Mathematics, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Cambridge, Massachusetts 02139 View metadata, citation and similar papersE-mail: at core.ac.uk [email protected] brought to you by CORE provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector L. W. Small Department of Mathematics, University of California at San Diego, La Jolla, California 92093 E-mail: [email protected] and J. J. Zhang Department of Mathematics, Box 354350, University of Washington, Seattle, Washington 98195 E-mail: [email protected] Communicated by J. T. Stafford Received November 18, 1999 Key Words: closed set; critically dense; generically flat; graded ring; Nullstellen- satz; strongly noetherian; universally noetherian. © 1999 Academic Press CONTENTS 0. Introduction. 1. Blowing up a critically dense sequence. 2. A characterization of closed sets. 3. Generic flatness. 4. Strongly noetherian and universally noetherian algebras. 5. A partial converse. *All three authors were supported in part by the NSF and the third author was also supported by a Sloan Research Fellowship. 579 0021-8693/99 $30.00 Copyright © 1999 by Academic Press All rights of reproduction in any form reserved. 580 artin, small, and zhang 0. INTRODUCTION In general, A will denote a right noetherian associative algebra over a commutative noetherian ring R.LetR0 be a commutative R-algebra. If R0 is finitely generated over R, then a version of the Hilbert basis theorem 0 asserts that A ⊗R R is right noetherian. We call an algebra A strongly right 0 0 noetherian if A ⊗R R is right noetherian whenever R is noetherian.
    [Show full text]
  • Generic Continuous Functions and Other Strange Functions in Classical Real Analysis
    Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Mathematics Theses Department of Mathematics and Statistics 4-17-2008 Generic Continuous Functions and other Strange Functions in Classical Real Analysis Douglas Albert Woolley Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/math_theses Part of the Mathematics Commons Recommended Citation Woolley, Douglas Albert, "Generic Continuous Functions and other Strange Functions in Classical Real Analysis." Thesis, Georgia State University, 2008. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/math_theses/44 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Mathematics and Statistics at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Mathematics Theses by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. GENERIC CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS AND OTHER STRANGE FUNCTIONS IN CLASSICAL REAL ANALYSIS by Douglas A. Woolley Under the direction of Mihaly Bakonyi ABSTRACT In this paper we examine continuous functions which on the surface seem to defy well-known mathematical principles. Before describing these functions, we introduce the Baire Cate- gory theorem and the Cantor set, which are critical in describing some of the functions and counterexamples. We then describe generic continuous functions, which are nowhere differ- entiable and monotone on no interval, and we include an example of such a function. We then construct a more conceptually challenging function, one which is everywhere differen- tiable but monotone on no interval. We also examine the Cantor function, a nonconstant continuous function with a zero derivative almost everywhere. The final section deals with products of derivatives. INDEX WORDS: Baire, Cantor, Generic Functions, Nowhere Differentiable GENERIC CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS AND OTHER STRANGE FUNCTIONS IN CLASSICAL REAL ANALYSIS by Douglas A.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 1: Lecture 11
    Chapter 1: Lecture 11 1. The Spectrum of a Ring & the Zariski Topology Definition 1.1. Let A be a ring. For I an ideal of A, define V (I)={P ∈ Spec(A) | I ⊆ P }. Proposition 1.2. Let A be a ring. Let Λ be a set of indices and let Il denote ideals of A. Then (1) V (0) = Spec(R),V(R)=∅; (2) ∩l∈ΛV (Il)=V (Pl∈Λ Il); k k (3) ∪l=1V (Il)=V (∩l=1Il); Then the family of all sets of the form V (I) with I ideal in A defines a topology on Spec(A) where, by definition, each V (I) is a closed set. We will call this topology the Zariski topology on Spec(A). Let Max(A) be the set of maximal ideals in A. Since Max(A) ⊆ Spec(A) we see that Max(A) inherits the Zariski topology. n Now, let k denote an algebraically closed fied. Let Y be an algebraic set in Ak .Ifwe n consider the Zariski topology on Y ⊆ Ak , then points of Y correspond to maximal ideals in A that contain I(Y ). That is, there is a natural homeomorphism between Y and Max(k[Y ]). Example 1.3. Let Y = {(x, y) | x2 = y3}⊂k2 with k algebraically closed. Then points in Y k[x, y] k[x, y] correspond to Max( ) ⊆ Spec( ). The latter set has a Zariski topology, and (x2 − y3) (x2 − y3) the restriction of the Zariski topology to the set of maximal ideals gives a topological space homeomorphic to Y (with the Zariski topology).
    [Show full text]
  • 18.726 Algebraic Geometry Spring 2009
    MIT OpenCourseWare http://ocw.mit.edu 18.726 Algebraic Geometry Spring 2009 For information about citing these materials or our Terms of Use, visit: http://ocw.mit.edu/terms. 18.726: Algebraic Geometry (K.S. Kedlaya, MIT, Spring 2009) More properties of schemes (updated 9 Mar 09) I’ve now spent a fair bit of time discussing properties of morphisms of schemes. How­ ever, there are a few properties of individual schemes themselves that merit some discussion (especially for those of you interested in arithmetic applications); here are some of them. 1 Reduced schemes I already mentioned the notion of a reduced scheme. An affine scheme X = Spec(A) is reduced if A is a reduced ring (i.e., A has no nonzero nilpotent elements). This occurs if and only if each stalk Ap is reduced. We say X is reduced if it is covered by reduced affine schemes. Lemma. Let X be a scheme. The following are equivalent. (a) X is reduced. (b) For every open affine subsheme U = Spec(R) of X, R is reduced. (c) For each x 2 X, OX;x is reduced. Proof. A previous exercise. Recall that any closed subset Z of a scheme X supports a unique reduced closed sub- scheme, defined by the ideal sheaf I which on an open affine U = Spec(A) is defined by the intersection of the prime ideals p 2 Z \ U. See Hartshorne, Example 3.2.6. 2 Connected schemes A nonempty scheme is connected if its underlying topological space is connected, i.e., cannot be written as a disjoint union of two open sets.
    [Show full text]
  • Non-Commutative Cryptography and Complexity of Group-Theoretic Problems
    Mathematical Surveys and Monographs Volume 177 Non-commutative Cryptography and Complexity of Group-theoretic Problems Alexei Myasnikov Vladimir Shpilrain Alexander Ushakov With an appendix by Natalia Mosina American Mathematical Society http://dx.doi.org/10.1090/surv/177 Mathematical Surveys and Monographs Volume 177 Non-commutative Cryptography and Complexity of Group-theoretic Problems Alexei Myasnikov Vladimir Shpilrain Alexander Ushakov With an appendix by Natalia Mosina American Mathematical Society Providence, Rhode Island EDITORIAL COMMITTEE Ralph L. Cohen, Chair MichaelA.Singer Jordan S. Ellenberg Benjamin Sudakov MichaelI.Weinstein 2010 Mathematics Subject Classification. Primary 94A60, 20F10, 68Q25, 94A62, 11T71. For additional information and updates on this book, visit www.ams.org/bookpages/surv-177 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Myasnikov, Alexei G., 1955– Non-commutative cryptography and complexity of group-theoretic problems / Alexei Myas- nikov, Vladimir Shpilrain, Alexander Ushakov ; with an appendix by Natalia Mosina. p. cm. – (Mathematical surveys and monographs ; v. 177) Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-0-8218-5360-3 (alk. paper) 1. Combinatorial group theory. 2. Cryptography. 3. Computer algorithms. 4. Number theory. I. Shpilrain, Vladimir, 1960– II. Ushakov, Alexander. III. Title. QA182.5.M934 2011 005.82–dc23 2011020554 Copying and reprinting. Individual readers of this publication, and nonprofit libraries acting for them, are permitted to make fair use of the material, such as to copy a chapter for use in teaching or research. Permission is granted to quote brief passages from this publication in reviews, provided the customary acknowledgment of the source is given. Republication, systematic copying, or multiple reproduction of any material in this publication is permitted only under license from the American Mathematical Society.
    [Show full text]