Exploring the Nature of Anti-Federalist Thought: Republicanism and Liberalism in the Political Thought of Cato Christopher Hallenbrook

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Exploring the Nature of Anti-Federalist Thought: Republicanism and Liberalism in the Political Thought of Cato Christopher Hallenbrook Undergraduate Review Volume 5 Article 11 2009 Exploring the Nature of Anti-Federalist Thought: Republicanism and Liberalism in the Political Thought of Cato Christopher Hallenbrook Follow this and additional works at: http://vc.bridgew.edu/undergrad_rev Part of the Political Theory Commons Recommended Citation Hallenbrook, Christopher (2009). Exploring the Nature of Anti-Federalist Thought: Republicanism and Liberalism in the Political Thought of Cato. Undergraduate Review, 5, 46-52. Available at: http://vc.bridgew.edu/undergrad_rev/vol5/iss1/11 This item is available as part of Virtual Commons, the open-access institutional repository of Bridgewater State University, Bridgewater, Massachusetts. Copyright © 2009 Christopher Hallenbrook Exploring the Nature of Anti-Federalist Thought: Republicanism and Liberalism in the Political Thought of Cato CHRISTOPHER HALLENBROOK Christopher is currently pursuing cholarship of the American founding remains divided as to the nature a double major in political science of Anti-Federalist political philosophy. One school of thought contends that the Anti-Federalists were the heirs of the republican tradition, while and history. After graduation, he the other maintains that the Anti-Federalists operated from a liberal intends to undertake graduate study Sworldview. Thus in what manner and to what extent Anti-Federalists draw upon in political theory beginning in the the republican and/or liberal political traditions remains unclear. In answering fall of 2009. He developed this paper this question I examine the writings of the Anti-Federalist Cato, analyzing what conceptualizations characterize Anti-Federalist thought and from what traditions during the summer of 2008 under the of political philosophy these ideas arose. I also analyzie texts of the major traditions supervision of Dr. Jordon Barkalow as that my have had a formative influence on Anti-Federalist thought in order to a part of his Interdisciplinary Honors provide a basis of comparison with the Anti-Federalists. As the Anti-Federalists played a crucial role in creating the Bill of Rights, these understandings will Thesis. Christopher would like to establish a framework for interpreting its role in American governance and thank the Adrian Tinsley Program jurisprudence. for Undergraduate Research and the Unlike their Federalist counterparts, the nature of whose political theory Bridgewater State College Foundation is widely agreed upon, the Anti-Federalists continue to stir debate over for their generous support of his how to characterize their political philosophy. Various interpretations have research through an Adrian Tinsley categorized the Anti-Federalists as classical republicans, modern republicans and liberals. This inability to arrive at a consensus is perhaps best illustrated Program Summer Grant. by Gordon Wood’s work on the subject. In Creation of the American Republic, Wood characterized the Anti-Federalists as traditionalists operating from a republican political worldview.1 Subsequently, Wood has revised his position on the Anti-Federalists, describing the Anti-Federalists as political innovators who break from traditional republican political principals and embrace liberal ones.2 These contrasting analyses are endemic of the disagreement that permeates scholarship on Anti-Federalist political philosophy. Given the diversity of opinions and lack of consensus over the nature of Anti-Federalist political thought, a more narrowly focused study that simultaneously tests for both liberal and republican influences in Anti-Federalist thought is warranted. The opportunity for such a study is provided in the writings of the Anti- Federalist Cato. Focusing on Cato allows for a natural experiment as his political theory can be compared to three other works of political theory that present political philosophy using the motif of the Roman statesman Cato the Younger. These three Catos – Plutarch’s “Life of Cato the Younger,” 46 • THE UNDERGRADUATE REVIEW • 2009 BRIDGEWATER STATE COLLEGE Joseph Addison’s Cato: A Tragedy and John Trenchard and Furthermore, all citizens must possess the ability to partake Thomas Gordon’s Cato’s Letters: OR, Essays on Liberty, Civil in directly selecting the governors.10 If not all of the citizenry and Religious, and Other Important Subjects – correspond to the are able to participate in the selection of the members of their classical republican, modern republican and liberal traditions, government, than those in power would be able to perpetuate respectively. Implementation of this natural experiment reveals their own authority.11 This continuation in power would that in regards to the mechanisms required for the supervision occur by using a numerical minority to elect a government and safe operation of government and the ills of the governors of a composition that is both favorable to the governors and possessing interests divergent from those of the governed, the not what the totality of the electorate would have chosen.12 Anti-Federalist Cato operates from the basis of a liberal political Additionally, the other fundamental manner in which these theory. mechanisms operate is to create constant competition among those seeking office to demonstrate who among them can best Liberalism: An Overview serve the people as the frequency with which they must answer In the liberal tradition, men preexist government and only to the people for their actions prevents them from following create it for their “mutual preservation and defense,” so that their own course independent of the people’s will.13 Thus, the they may enjoy liberty, which they possess as a natural right, structures of government are designed specifically to maintain and its benefits.3 In order to ensure that government serves these the people’s freedom from arbitrary rule. ends, a number of safeguards are implemented by which the people can monitor their government and influence its actions. Despite its being formed by the consent of the governed, Cato These mechanisms include numerous representatives, frequent does not see government as something that can be left alone elections and rotation in office.4 Such precautions serve to bind to run its course. When it comes to preserving the ends of the interests of the governors to those of the governed, which government, “a general presumption that rulers will govern is essential to ensuring that those in government act for the well is not a sufficient security;” a sentiment that Trenchard benefit of the people as “most men will act for interest against and Gordon’s Cato shares.14 To ensure the proper operation duty, as often as they dare.”5 This supremacy of interest over of government, the people must supervise their government.15 duty necessitates that government be structured in such a way Perhaps the most direct way that the people are able to do this as to make it in men’s interest to do their duty. Hence the use is through a participatory representation, a subject on which of frequent elections to create constant competition among the Cato refers his readers to the writings of the Anti-Federalist people for elected positions.6 This constant competition makes Brutus on the grounds that “this subject has been so ably and it in the interest of those in government to do their duty, as if fully treated by a writer under the signature of Brutus, that they do not, they will simply be voted out of office in the near I shall content myself with referring you to him thereon.”16 future.7 Liberal government is thus structured so as to give the Cato’s referral serves as grounds for consideration of the two people control in ensuring that it protects their liberty instead writers’ views on representation in tandem, as two disciples of of curtailing it. the same principles of representation. Political Liberty: The Centrality of Representation Before examining the nature of representation according to While liberty is the great end for which government it formed, Brutus, it is important to first consider the role representation it is not a monolithic concept. Cato’s understanding of liberty plays in Brutus’s conception of government. To Brutus, is twofold. The first type of liberty that Cato is concerned with government has no natural right to its authority, and therefore is political liberty. Political liberty takes the form of freedom draws its legitimacy from the consent of those who choose to from government tyranny. Accordingly, Cato advocates placing form it.17 The reason men decide to thus leave the state of nature numerous restrictions upon the governors that are designed by forming government is that in each individual pursuing his to preserve the people’s liberty. These protections serve to own ends in the state of nature, “the possessions or enjoyments prevent the consolidation of power into one of a few hands of one were sacrificed to the views and designs of another; thus with sufficient time to use them to establish and perpetuate the weak were prey to the strong, the simple and unwary were despotism.8 Fundamentally, these safeguards are designed to subject to impositions from those who were more crafty and make the governors accountable and responsive to the people. designing. In this state of things, every individual was insecure.”18 This is particularly evident when Cato insists on the direct To alleviate this insecurity, men consent among themselves to election of the executive on the grounds that otherwise “the form government with the purpose of protecting their natural president cannot represent
Recommended publications
  • Mill and Pettit on Freedom, Domination, and Freedom-As-Domination
    Prolegomena 18 (1) 2019: 27–50 doi: 10 .26362/20190102 Mill and Pettit on Freedom, Domination, and Freedom-as-Domination Tim Beaumont School of Foreign Languages, Shenzhen University, Guangdong, P .R . China beaumonttim@hotmail .com ORIGINAL SCIENTIFIC ARTICLE – RECEIVED: 29/11/18 ACCEPTED: 11/04/19 abstract: Pettit endorses a ‘republican’ conception of social freedom of the person as consisting of a state of non-domination, and takes this to refute Mill’s ‘liberal’ claim that non-domineering but coercive interference can compromise social freedom of choice . This paper argues that Pettit’s interpretation is true to the extent that Mill believes that the legitimate, non-arbitrary and just coercion of would-be dominators, for the sake of preventing them from dominating others, can render them unfree to choose to do so without rendering them socially unfree (qua dominated) persons in their own right . However, contra Pettit, Mill is correct to reject the ‘republican’ view for at least two reasons . Firstly, it enables him to avoid commitment to the implausi- ble implication that would-be dominators who sincerely deny any interest in a shared system of basic liberties are automatically rendered unfree persons by the coercion necessary to uphold such a system . Secondly, it enables him to avoid begging the question against ‘immoralists’ like Nietzsche, whose opposition to systems of recip- rocal non-domination is at least partly motivated by the losses of social freedom of choice they entail for those they deem to be worthy of dominating others . key words: Domination, freedom, liberalism, liberty, John Stuart Mill, Friedrich Nietzsche, Philip Pettit, republicanism .
    [Show full text]
  • Thomas Jefferson and the Ideology of Democratic Schooling
    Thomas Jefferson and the Ideology of Democratic Schooling James Carpenter (Binghamton University) Abstract I challenge the traditional argument that Jefferson’s educational plans for Virginia were built on mod- ern democratic understandings. While containing some democratic features, especially for the founding decades, Jefferson’s concern was narrowly political, designed to ensure the survival of the new republic. The significance of this piece is to add to the more accurate portrayal of Jefferson’s impact on American institutions. Submit your own response to this article Submit online at democracyeducationjournal.org/home Read responses to this article online http://democracyeducationjournal.org/home/vol21/iss2/5 ew historical figures have undergone as much advocate of public education in the early United States” (p. 280). scrutiny in the last two decades as has Thomas Heslep (1969) has suggested that Jefferson provided “a general Jefferson. His relationship with Sally Hemings, his statement on education in republican, or democratic society” views on Native Americans, his expansionist ideology and his (p. 113), without distinguishing between the two. Others have opted suppressionF of individual liberties are just some of the areas of specifically to connect his ideas to being democratic. Williams Jefferson’s life and thinking that historians and others have reexam- (1967) argued that Jefferson’s impact on our schools is pronounced ined (Finkelman, 1995; Gordon- Reed, 1997; Kaplan, 1998). because “democracy and education are interdependent” and But his views on education have been unchallenged. While his therefore with “education being necessary to its [democracy’s] reputation as a founding father of the American republic has been success, a successful democracy must provide it” (p.
    [Show full text]
  • Republican Citizenship Richard Dagger University of Richmond, [email protected]
    University of Richmond UR Scholarship Repository Political Science Faculty Publications Political Science 2002 Republican Citizenship Richard Dagger University of Richmond, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.richmond.edu/polisci-faculty-publications Part of the American Politics Commons, and the Political Theory Commons Recommended Citation Dagger, Richard. "Republican Citizenship." In Handbook of Citizenship Studies, edited by Engin F. Isin and Bryan S. Turner, 145-57. Thousand Oaks: Sage Publications, 2002. This Book Chapter is brought to you for free and open access by the Political Science at UR Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Political Science Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of UR Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 9 Republican Citizenship RICHARD DAGGER To speak of republican citizenship is to risk There might also be no need for this confusion, at least in the United States, chapter if it were not for the revival of where it is often necessary to explain that scholarly interest in republicanism in recent one is referring to 'small-r' republicanism years. Such a revival has definitely rather than a position taken by the Republi­ occurred, though, and occurred simultane­ can Party. But just as one may be a democrat ously with a renewed interest in citizenship. without being a Democrat, so one may be a This coincidence suggests that republican republican without being a Republican. The citizenship is well worth our attention, not ideas of democracy and the republic are far only for purposes of historical understand­ older than any political party and far richer ing but also as a way of thinking about than any partisan label can convey - rich citizenship in the twenty-first century.
    [Show full text]
  • Republicanism
    ONIVI C C Re PUBLICANISM ANCIENT LESSONS FOR GLOBAL POLITICS EDIT ED BY GEOFFREY C. KELLOW AND NeVEN LeDDY ON CIVIC REPUBLICANISM Ancient Lessons for Global Politics EDITED BY GEOFFREY C. KELLOW AND NEVEN LEDDY On Civic Republicanism Ancient Lessons for Global Politics UNIVERSITY OF ToronTO PRESS Toronto Buffalo London © University of Toronto Press 2016 Toronto Buffalo London www.utppublishing.com Printed in the U.S.A. ISBN 978-1-4426-3749-8 Printed on acid-free, 100% post-consumer recycled paper with vegetable- based inks. Library and Archives Canada Cataloguing in Publication On civic republicanism : ancient lessons for global politics / edited by Geoffrey C. Kellow and Neven Leddy. Includes bibliographical references. ISBN 978-1-4426-3749-8 (bound) 1. Republicanism – History. I. Leddy, Neven, editor II.Kellow, Geoffrey C., 1970–, editor JC421.O5 2016 321.8'6 C2015-906926-2 CC-BY-NC-ND This work is published subject to a Creative Commons Attribution Non-commercial No Derivative License. For permission to publish commercial versions please contact University of Toronto Press. University of Toronto Press acknowledges the financial assistance to its publishing program of the Canada Council for the Arts and the Ontario Arts Council, an agency of the Government of Ontario. an Ontario government agency un organisme du gouvernement de l’Ontario Funded by the Financé par le Government gouvernement of Canada du Canada Contents Preface: A Return to Classical Regimes Theory vii david edward tabachnick and toivo koivukoski Introduction 3 geoffrey c. kellow Part One: The Classical Heritage 1 The Problematic Character of Periclean Athens 15 timothy w.
    [Show full text]
  • Socialism and Republicanism in Imperial Germany
    chapter 8 Socialism and Republicanism in Imperial Germany In November 1918, German Social Democrats were suddenly confronted with the need to establish a new republican state order in Germany following the collapse of the Empire. In light of the difficulties Social Democrats experi- enced in founding a stable and viable republic in 1918–19, the question of their prior understanding of republicanism – including the importance attached to the issue within the party – merits closer attention. Theoretically, the Social Democratic Party in Imperial Germany was opposed in principle to the mon- archical state. This opposition was manifested in a number of ways, such as refusing to take part in demonstrations of loyalty to the crown, in the Reichstag, for example, a policy that precluded Social Democrats from taking up a Vice- President’s (i.e. Deputy Speaker’s) position in the parliament when the party’s numbers would have justified it.The demand that the German empire be trans- formed into a democratic republic, however, was generally muted in the party’s public agitation. Robert Michels, during the time in which he identified with the left of the party, criticised it for placing too little emphasis on agitation for a republic: this he saw as ‘a mistake, that may be half attributed to a certain degree of complacency in the party, but […] equally to our monarchical institu- tions [themselves] with their rubbery law paragraphs on lèse-majesté’.1 Perhaps it was a demonstration of the effectiveness of the latter that Michels published his own most trenchant critiques of the reign of Kaiser Wilhelm II in the rel- ative safety of Italy, in Italian.2 It is clear that the Social Democratic Party was, to some extent, constrained by the prevailing laws from making open attacks on the monarchy.
    [Show full text]
  • Augustine's Contribution to the Republican Tradition
    Grand Valley State University ScholarWorks@GVSU Peer Reviewed Articles Political Science and International Relations 2010 Augustine’s Contribution to the Republican Tradition Paul J. Cornish Grand Valley State University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gvsu.edu/pls_articles Part of the Political Science Commons Recommended Citation Cornish, Paul J., "Augustine’s Contribution to the Republican Tradition" (2010). Peer Reviewed Articles. 10. https://scholarworks.gvsu.edu/pls_articles/10 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Political Science and International Relations at ScholarWorks@GVSU. It has been accepted for inclusion in Peer Reviewed Articles by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks@GVSU. For more information, please contact [email protected]. article Augustine’s Contribution to the EJPT Republican Tradition European Journal of Political Theory 9(2) 133–148 © The Author(s), 2010 Reprints and permission: http://www. Paul J. Cornish Grand Valley State University sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.nav [DOI: 10.1177/1474885109338002] http://ejpt.sagepub.com abstract: The present argument focuses on part of Augustine’s defense of Christianity in The City of God. There Augustine argues that the Christian religion did not cause the sack of Rome by the Goths in 410 ce. Augustine revised the definitions of a ‘people’ and ‘republic’ found in Cicero’s De Republica in light of the impossibility of true justice in a world corrupted by sin. If one returns these definitions ot their original context, and accounts for Cicero’s own political teachings, one finds that Augustine follows Cicero’s republicanism on several key points.
    [Show full text]
  • MACHIAVELLI, TOCQUEVILLE and NIETZSCHE on AUTHORITY and EQUALITY Mikael Hörnqvist, Uppsala University
    THE FEW AND THE MANY: MACHIAVELLI, TOCQUEVILLE AND NIETZSCHE ON AUTHORITY AND EQUALITY Mikael Hörnqvist, Uppsala University Machiavelli In Machiavelli’s writings the ruling few go under many different names. In the ancient context they are often simply called “the Senate,” but he also refers to them as i grandi, gli ottimati, la nobilità and i potenti. The fact that the aristocratic element here appears under a wide variety of names, it could be argued, reflects the open nature of the class structure of early sixteenth century Florence in general, and its ruling class, the Reggimento, in particular. It also seems to suggest that Machiavelli considers the ruling elite to be too complex and fleeting a phenomenon to be fixed or contained in a single name. Machiavelli’s account of the relation between the people and the nobles displays a similar complexity. On the one hand, throughout the Discourses, he describes the Plebs as gullible and easily deceived and the nobles as shrewd and cunning. But far from condemning the elite’s manipulation of the populace’s religious beliefs for political ends, Machiavelli praises it and even exhorts his contemporaries to revive it, as he puts it, by reinterpreting Christianity “according to virtue.” He contrasts the Roman Senate, which according to him (D.I.38) “always judged things as they should be judged and always took the less bad policy for the better,” to the rash, undisciplined and imprudent elites of modern Florence. But on the other hand, it could be argued, Machiavelli endorses an aggressive and ferocious form of popular republicanism in which the general populace, acting as “the guardians of liberty,” controls the elites by often harsh and brutal methods.
    [Show full text]
  • Political Legacy: John Locke and the American Government
    POLITICAL LEGACY: JOHN LOCKE AND THE AMERICAN GOVERNMENT by MATTHEW MIYAMOTO A THESIS Presented to the Department of Political Science and the Robert D. Clark Honors College in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Bachelor of Science January 2016 An Abstract of the Thesis of Matthew Miyamoto for the degree of Bachelor of Science in the Department of Political Science to be taken January, 2016 Title: Political Legacy: John Locke and the American Government Professor Dan Tichenor John Locke, commonly known as the father of classical liberalism, has arguably influenced the United States government more than any other political philosopher in history. His political theories include the quintessential American ideals of a right to life, liberty, and property, as well as the notion that the government is legitimized through the consent of the governed. Locke's theories guided the founding fathers through the creation of the American government and form the political backbone upon which this nation was founded. His theories form the foundation of principal American documents such as the Declaration of Independence, the Constitution, and the Bill of Rights, and they permeate the speeches, writings, and letters of our founding fathers. Locke's ideas define our world so thoroughly that we take them axiomatically. Locke's ideas are our tradition. They are our right. This thesis seeks to understand John Locke's political philosophy and the role that he played in the creation of the United States government. .. 11 Acknowledgements I would like to thank Professor Dan Tichenor for helping me to fully examine this topic and guiding me through my research and writing.
    [Show full text]
  • Liberalism, Republicanism and the Public Philosophy of American
    Liberalism, Republicanism and the Public Philosophy of American Democracy I Introduction Political philosophers can be placed on a spectrum according to how they view the relationship between philosophy and social institutions. At one extreme, a naive a priorism considers social institutions only to the extent that they are necessary for the practical realization of, supposedly timeless, philosophical principles. At the other extreme, are certain Marxists and post-structuralists for whom philosophy is no more than an expression of specific social institutions: a particular discursive practice which occupies no privileged critical vantage- point in relation to other institutions. In this paper, I shall look at the relationship between philosophy and institutions in the context of a critical examination of the work of the contemporary Harvard political philosopher, Michael Sandel. Sandel made his name in the early nineteen-eighties with his first book, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice1, a fierce and eloquent critique of the work of his Harvard colleague, John Rawls. The extraordinary resonance of his original polemic 1 Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982. The recently published second edition (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998) contains a new preface and final chapter responding to Rawls’s Political Liberalism (New York, N.Y.: Columbia University Press, 1993) as well as a very useful supplementary bibliography of the most important contributions to the debate that Liberalism and the Limits of Justice has provoked. Since, as far as the main body of the text is concerned, the two editions are identical, I shall specify an edition only when referring to this new material. 1 has elicited important clarifications of Rawls’s position on the part of Rawls’s followers and Rawls himself.2 But Sandel’s work recommends itself in the present context for another reason.
    [Show full text]
  • JS Mill's Political Thought
    P1: JZZ 0521860202pre CUFX079B/Urbinati 0 521 86020 2 cupusbw December 26, 2006 7:38 This page intentionally left blank ii P1: JZZ 0521860202pre CUFX079B/Urbinati 0 521 86020 2 cupusbw December 26, 2006 7:38 J. S. MILL’S POLITICAL THOUGHT The year 2006 marked the two hundredth anniversary of John Stuart Mill’s birth. Although his philosophical reputation has varied greatly in the interven- ing years, it is now clear that Mill ranks among the most influential modern political thinkers. Yet despite his enduring influence, and perhaps also because of it, the breadth and complexity of Mill’s political thought is often under- appreciated. Although his writings remain a touchstone for debates over liberty and liberalism, many other important dimensions of his political philosophy have until recently been mostly ignored or neglected. This volume aims, first, to correct such neglect by illustrating the breadth and depth of Mill’s political writings. It does so by drawing togetheracollection of essays whose authors explore underappreciated elements of Mill’s political philosophy, including his democratic theory, his writings on international relations and military inter- ventions, and his treatments of socialism and despotism. Second, the volume shows how Mill’s thinking remains pertinent to our own political life in three broad areas – democratic institutions and culture, liberalism, and international politics – and offers a critical reassessment of Mill’s political philosophy in light of recent political developments and transformations. Nadia Urbinati
    [Show full text]
  • Republicanism, Rights: a Comment on Pangle
    University of Chicago Law School Chicago Unbound Journal Articles Faculty Scholarship 1990 Republicanism, Rights: A Comment on Pangle Cass R. Sunstein Follow this and additional works at: https://chicagounbound.uchicago.edu/journal_articles Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Cass R. Sunstein, "Republicanism, Rights: A Comment on Pangle," 66 Chicago-Kent Law Review 177 (1990). This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at Chicago Unbound. It has been accepted for inclusion in Journal Articles by an authorized administrator of Chicago Unbound. For more information, please contact [email protected]. REPUBLICANISM, RIGHTS: A COMMENT ON PANGLE CASS R. SUNSTEIN* Professor Pangle's essay revolves around a fairly straightforward narrative. The period of classical republicanism placed a high premium on virtue and responsibility; its conception of freedom presupposed rule, not license: its rulers were to be chosen on the basis of wisdom and char- acter; it had no real place for rights. The early liberals, symbolized by Machiavelli, largely abandoned these commitments. Seeing selfishness as the usual motivating force of human behavior, they inaugurated a new emphasis on rights, and they disparaged virtue. The American founding, influenced above all by the early liberals, reflected at most a diluted belief in the republican commitments. The framers' main goal was the protec- tion of rights. For them, self-interest was the ordinary motivating source of human behavior. American-style republicanism was egalitarian, liber- tarian, and democratic; it saw as its chief goal the protection and foster- ing of individual rights. As time has gone on, the American departure from republicanism has become all the more conspicuous, and also troubling.
    [Show full text]
  • Contrasted Revolutions
    REVIEWS John Sidel, Republicanism, Communism, Islam: Cosmopolitan Origins of Revolution in Southeast Asia Cornell University Press: Ithaca ny 2021, $39.95, hardback 324 pp, 978 1501755613 Saskia Schäfer CONTRASTED REVOLUTIONS The standardized designation ‘Southeast Asia’—two words, un-hyphenated, capitalized—originated in the Pacific War. The Allies divided the world into warzones. Mountbatten’s South East Asia Command (seac) comprised most of what was to be wrested from Japan that was not already in the China thea- tre or a former us possession (and included some territory no longer typically placed in Southeast Asia: Sri Lanka; the Andaman, Nicobar and Laccadive Islands; Christmas Island; the Maldives). In 1945, Washington established the Department of Southeast Asia Affairs. The following year a depart- ment of ‘Southeast Asian Affairs’ sprouted up at soas, joined by another at Yale in 1947. Diffusion of the term was rapid and far-reaching. Before the Second World War, Chinese-speakers had referred to the region with a variety of terms and epithets, if mostly as Nanyang—‘South Sea’—but today they more commonly use 东南亚—‘Eastsouth Asia’ (whereas, in compound designations of a region, European languages put the vertical north–south axis before the horizontal east–west, in Chinese the horizontal east–west axis comes first). One place where the term has not acquired purchase is the region itself, whose inhabitants rarely identify as ‘Southeast Asians’. If the exact contours of Southeast Asia were not determined until after the war, however, the region as a whole had long shared certain broad features. It is the part of the globe where several of the major religious tra- ditions intersect or overlap: Catholicism abutting Islam in the Philippines; the Sanskrit-sphere underlying the more recent arrival of Islam in the new left review 129 may june 2021 125 126 nlr 129 Malay-speaking world; Buddhism surrounding islands of Protestant Christianity in Myanmar.
    [Show full text]