Behavioral and Brain Sciences

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Behavioral and Brain Sciences VOLUME 16 An International Journal of Current Research NUMBER 1 MARCH 1993 and Theory with Open Peer Commentary Appearing in this issue, with Commentary . How we know our minds: The illusion of first-person knowledge Of intentionality Alison Gopnik The psychology of folk psychology Alvin I. Goldman A perspective for viewing the history of psychophysics David J. Murray Also, Continuing Commentary on "Sex differences in mathematical reasoning ability in intellectually talented preadolescents: Their nature, effects and possible causes" (Benbow) "Consciousness, explanatory inversion and cognitive science" (Searle) "The neuropsychology of schizophrenia" (Gray et al.) CAMBRIDGE Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 170.106.33.42, on 26 Sep 2021 at 10:41:10, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X00028612 ISSN 0140-525X Behavioral and Brain Sciences Editor Language and Language Disorders Max Coltheart/Macquarie U. Stevan Harnad Linguistics E-mail: [email protected] or Robert Freidin/Princeton [email protected] 20 Nassau St., Suite 240 Neurobiology Princeton, NJ 08542 Irving Kupfermann/Columbia Neurobehavioral Genetics Managing Editor Wim E. Crusio/Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique Nancy Simon Neuropsychology Chief Copy Editor Jeffrey A. Gray/lnst. Psychiatry, London John C. Marshall/Radcliffe Infirmary, Oxford Avis Kniffin Neurophysiology Associate Editors Sten Grillner/Karolinska Institutet Behavioral Biology Paleoneurology Jack P. Hailman/U. Wisconsin Stephen Jay Gould/Harvard Hubert Markl/U. Konstanz Perception Biosocial Behavior Bruce Bridgeman/U. California Glendon Schubert/U. Hawaii, Manoa Richard Gregory/U. Bristol Cognition and Artificial Intelligence Philosophy Zenon Pylyshyn/U. Western Ontario Daniel C. Dennett/Tufts Cognitive Development Gilbert Harman/Princeton Annette Karmiloff-Smith/MRC, London and MPI, Nijmegen Philosophy of Science Evolutionary Biology Adolf Grunbaum/U. Pittsburgh Michael T. Ghiselin/California Academy of Sciences Primatology Experimental Analysis of Behavior Horst D. Steklis/Rutgers A. Charles Catania/U. Maryland, Baltimore County Psychobiology History and Systems Victor H. Denenberg/U. Connecticut Julian Jaynes/Princeton David S. Olton/Johns Hopkins Language and Cognition Vision and Artificial Intelligence Philip Johnson-Laird/Princeton Stuart Sutherland/U. Sussex Editorial Policy Behavioral and Brain Sciences (BBS) is an Copying This journal is registered with the Copyright Clear- international journal providing a special service called Open ance Center (27 Congress St., Salem, MA 01970). Organiza- Peer Commentary* to researchers in any area of psychology, tions in the U.S.A. who are also registered with the CCC may neuroscience, behavioral biology, or cognitive science who therefore copy material (beyond the limits permitted by sec- wish to solicit, from fellow specialists within and across these tions 107 and 108 of U.S. Copyright Law) subject to payment BBS disciplines, multiple responses to a particularly signifi- to the CCC of the per-copy fee indicated in the code on the cant and controversial piece of work. (See Instructions for first page of the article. This consent does not extend to Authors and Commentators, inside back cover.) The pur- multiple copying for promotional or commercial purposes. pose of this service is to contribute to the communication, ISI Tear Sheet Service, 3501 Market Street, Philadelphia, criticism, stimulation, and particularly the unification of re- PA 19104, is authorized to supply single copies of separate search in the behavioral and brain sciences, from molecular articles for private use only. neurobiology to artificial intelligence and the philosophy of For all other use, permission should be sought from the mind. Cambridge or New York offices of the Press. Papers judged by the editors and referees to be appropri- Subscriptions Behavioral and Brain Sciences (ISSN ate for Commentary are circulated to a large number of com- 0140-525X) is published quarterly in March, June, September, mentators selected by the editors, referees, and author to and December. Four parts form a volume. The subscription provide substantive criticism, interpretation, elaboration, and price for institutions of Volume 16 (1993) is US $196.00 net pertinent complementary and supplementary material from a in the U.S.A. and Canada; £133.00 in the rest of the world; full cross-disciplinary perspective. The article, accepted for individuals US $80.00 net (£54.00); for BBS Associates commentaries, and the author's response then appear si- and for students (in the U.S.A. and Canada only) with proof of multaneously in BBS. eligibility with order US $46.00 net (£34.00); for APA, APS, Commentary on BBS articles may be provided by any and ASA members US $64.00 net (£34.00) with proof of qualified professional in the behavioral and brain sciences, eligibility with order. Subscription price includes postage. but much of it is drawn from a large body of BBS Associates Single parts cost US $50.00 net (£34.00) plus postage. who have become formally affiliated with the project. /nsf/fuf/ona/ordersmaybesenttoabookseller,or,intheU.S.A. Qualified professionals are eligible to become BBS Associ- and Canada direct to: Cambridge University Press, 40 West 20 ates if they have (1) been nominated by a current BBS Asso- Street, New York, NY 10011-4211; in the U.K. and rest of the ciate, (2) refereed for BBS, or (3) had a commentary or arti- world to: Cambridge University Press, The Edinburgh Building, cle accepted for publication. A special subscription rate is Shaftesbury Road, Cambridge CB22RU, England. Individuals available to Associates. Individuals interested in serving as must order direct from the Press. Second class postage paid at BBS Associates are asked to write the editor. New York, N.Y., and at additional mailing offices. Postmaster: This publication was supported in part by NIH Grant LM Send address changes in the U.S.A. and Canada to Behavioral 03539 from the National Library of Medicine. and Brain Sciences, Cambridge University Press, 40 West 20 Street, New York, NY 10011 -4211. Advertising Inquiries about advertising should be sent to 'Modelled on the 'CA Comment' service of the journal the Journals Promotion Department of the Cambridge or Current Anthropology. New York Office of Cambridge University Press. © 1993 Cambridge University Press Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 170.106.33.42, on 26 Sep 2021 at 10:41:10, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X00028612 Contents Volume 16:1 March 1993 Gopnik, A. How we know our minds: The illusion of first-person knowledge of intentionality 1 Goldman, A. I. The psychology of folk psychology 15 Open Peer Commentary Mele, A. Reporting on past psychological states: Armstrong, D. M. Causes are perceived Beliefs, desires and intentions 61 and introspected 29 Moore, C. & Barresi, J. Knowledge of the psychological Baron-Cohen, S. The concept of intentionality: states of self and others is not only theory-laden Invented or innate? 29 but also data-driven 61 Bartsch, K. & Estes, D. Are false beliefs Morris, W. E. & Richardson, R. C. Mismatching representative mental states? 30 categories? 62 Butterworth, G. Towards an ecology of mind 31 Morton, A. Heuristics and counterfactual Campbell, R. L. & Bickhard, M. H. Knowing levels self-knowledge 63 and the child's understanding of mind 33 Nichols, S. Developmental evidence and introspection 64 Cassidy, K. W. There's more to mental states Olson, D. R. & Astington, J. W. The role of concepts than meets the inner "I" 34 in perception and inference 65 Chalmers, D. J. Self-ascription without qualia: Perner, J. A plea for the second functionalist model A case study 35 and the insufficiency of simulation 66 Chandler, M. & Carpendale, J. The naked truth Pietroski, P. M. First-person authority and beliefs about first-person knowledge 36 as representations 67 Chater, N. Categorization, theories and folk Pillow, B. H. Limitations on first-person experience: psychology 37 Implications of the "extent" 69 Czyzewska, M. & Lewicki, P. How directly do we Plaut, D. C. & KarmilofT-Smith, A. Representational know our minds? 37 development and theory-of-mind computations 70 Daniel, S. The anthropology of folk psychology 38 Pratt, I. Matching and mental-state ascription 71 Dittrich, W. H. & Lea, S. E. G. Intentionality, mind Rachlin, H. Theory-theory theory 72 and folk psychology 39 Rakover, S. S. Theories of mind: Some Ericsson, K. A. Recall or regeneration of past mental methodological/conceptual problems, and an states: Toward an account in terms of cognitive alternative approach 73 processes 41 Rev, G. Why presume analyses are on-line? 74 Fetzer, J. H. Goldman has not defeated folk Rips, L. J. Qualities and relations in folk theories functionalism 42 of mind 75 Goldman, A. I. Competing accounts of belief-task Russell, J. On leaving your children wrapped performance 43 in thought 76 Gopnik, A. Theories and qualities 44 Saunders, B. A. C. Disenshrining the Cartesian self 77 Gordon, R. M. Self-ascription of belief and desire 45 Shoemaker, S. Special access lies down Gunderson, K. On behalf of phenomenological parity with theory-theory 78 for the attitudes 4g Siegal, M. Knowing children's minds 79 Gurd, J. M. & Marshall, J. C. Know my own mind? Stanovich, K. E. The developmental history 1 should be so lucky! 47 of an illusion 80 48 Sterelny, K. Categories, categorisation and Harris, P. L. First-person current 49 development: Introspective knowledge is no threat Heil, J. Unraveling introspection to functionalism 81 Hill, C. S. Qualitative characteristics, type materialism 50 Thompson, N. S. Why Alison Gopnik should be and the circularity of analytic functionalism a behaviorist 83 Horgan, T. Analytic functionalism without 51 Tomascllo, M. Where's the person? 84 representational functionalism 52 Velmans, M. Common sense, functional theories Jackson, F. Qualia for prepositional attitudes? 52 and knowledge of the mind 85 Johnson, C.
Recommended publications
  • Harnad (1994) Computation Is Just Interpretable Symbol Manipulation
    Computation Is Just Interpretable Symbol Manipulation: Cognition Isn't http://www.ecs.soton.ac.uk/~harnad/Papers/Harnad/harnad94.computa... Harnad, S. (1994) Computation Is Just Interpretable Symbol Manipulation: Cognition Isn't. Special Issue on "What Is Computation" Minds and Machines 4:379-390 [Also appears in French translation in "Penser l'Esprit: Des Sciences de la Cognition a une Philosophie Cognitive," V. Rialle & D. Fisette, Eds. Presses Universite de Grenoble. 1996] COMPUTATION IS JUST INTERPRETABLE SYMBOL MANIPULATION; COGNITION ISN'T Stevan Harnad Department of Psychology University of Southampton Highfield, Southampton SO17 1BJ UNITED KINGDOM email:[email protected] ftp://cogsci.ecs.soton.ac.uk/pub/harnad/ http://cogsci.ecs.soton.ac.uk/~harnad/ gopher://gopher.princeton.edu/11/.libraries/.pujournals phone: +44 703 592582 fax: +44 703 594597 ABSTRACT: Computation is interpretable symbol manipulation. Symbols are objects that are manipulated on the basis of rules operating only on the symbols' shapes , which are arbitrary in relation to what they can be interpreted as meaning. Even if one accepts the Church/Turing Thesis that computation is unique, universal and very near omnipotent, not everything is a computer, because not everything can be given a systematic interpretation; and certainly everything can't be given every systematic interpretation. But even after computers and computation have been successfully distinguished from other kinds of things, mental states will not just be the implementations of the right symbol systems, because of the symbol grounding problem: The interpretation of a symbol system is not intrinsic to the system; it is projected onto it by the interpreter.
    [Show full text]
  • Affective Sentience and Moral Protection
    Rochester Institute of Technology RIT Scholar Works Articles Faculty & Staff Scholarship 1-9-2021 Affective sentience and moral protection Russell Powell Boston University Irina Mikhalevich Rochester Institute of Technology Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.rit.edu/article Recommended Citation Powell, Russell and Mikhalevich, Irina (2020) Affective sentience and moral protection. Animal Sentience 29(35). DOI: 10.51291/2377-7478.1668 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty & Staff Scholarship at RIT Scholar Works. It has been accepted for inclusion in Articles by an authorized administrator of RIT Scholar Works. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Animal Sentience 2020.397: Powell & Mikhalevich Response to Commentary on Invertebrate Minds Affective sentience and moral protection Response to Commentary on Mikhalevich & Powell on Invertebrate Minds Russell Powell Department of Philosophy, Boston University Irina Mikhalevich Department of Philosophy, Rochester Institute of Technology Abstract: We have structured our response according to five questions arising from the commentaries: (i) What is sentience? (ii) Is sentience a necessary or sufficient condition for moral standing? (iii) What methods should guide comparative cognitive research in general, and specifically in studying invertebrates? (iv) How should we balance scientific uncertainty and moral risk? (v) What practical strategies can help reduce biases and morally dismissive attitudes toward invertebrates? Russell Powell, Associate Professor of Philosophy, Boston University, specializes in philosophical problems in evolutionary biology and bioethics. Website Irina Mikhalevich, Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Rochester Institute of Technology, specializes in conceptual and methodological problems in comparative cognitive science and their implications for the treatment of nonhuman animals.
    [Show full text]
  • Minds Without Spines: Evolutionarily Inclusive Animal Ethics
    Animal Sentience 2020.329: Mikhalevich & Powell on Invertebrate Minds Call for Commentary: Animal Sentience publishes Open Peer Commentary on all accepted target articles. Target articles are peer-reviewed. Commentaries are editorially reviewed. There are submitted commentaries as well as invited commentaries. Commentaries appear as soon as they have been reviewed, revised and accepted. Target article authors may respond to their commentaries individually or in a joint response to multiple commentaries. INSTRUCTIONS FOR COMMENTATORS Minds without spines: Evolutionarily inclusive animal ethics Irina Mikhalevich Department of Philosophy, Rochester Institute of Technology Russell Powell Department of Philosophy, Boston University Abstract: Invertebrate animals are frequently lumped into a single category and denied welfare protections despite their considerable cognitive, behavioral, and evolutionary diversity. Some ethical and policy inroads have been made for cephalopod molluscs and crustaceans, but the vast majority of arthropods, including the insects, remain excluded from moral consideration. We argue that this exclusion is unwarranted given the existing evidence. Anachronistic readings of evolution, which view invertebrates as lower in the scala naturae, continue to influence public policy and common morality. The assumption that small brains are unlikely to support cognition or sentience likewise persists, despite growing evidence that arthropods have converged on cognitive functions comparable to those found in vertebrates. The exclusion of invertebrates is also motivated by cognitive-affective biases that covertly influence moral judgment, as well as a flawed balancing of scientific uncertainty against moral risk. All these factors shape moral attitudes toward basal vertebrates too, but they are particularly acute in the arthropod context. Moral consistency dictates that the same standards of evidence and risk management that justify policy protections for vertebrates also support extending moral consideration to certain invertebrates.
    [Show full text]
  • A Resonant Message: Aligning Scholar Values and Open Access Objectives in OA Policy Outreach to Faculty and Graduate Students
    Please do not remove this page A Resonant Message: Aligning Scholar Values and Open Access Objectives in OA Policy Outreach to Faculty and Graduate Students Otto, Jane https://scholarship.libraries.rutgers.edu/discovery/delivery/01RUT_INST:ResearchRepository/12643424420004646?l#13643501240004646 Otto, J. (2016). A Resonant Message: Aligning Scholar Values and Open Access Objectives in OA Policy Outreach to Faculty and Graduate Students. In Journal of Librarianship and Scholarly Communication (Vol. 4). Rutgers University. https://doi.org/10.7282/T3HT2RMZ This work is protected by copyright. You are free to use this resource, with proper attribution, for research and educational purposes. Other uses, such as reproduction or publication, may require the permission of the copyright holder. Downloaded On 2021/10/02 11:21:37 -0400 A RESONANT MESSAGE 1 A Resonant Message: Aligning Scholar Values and Open Access Objectives in OA Policy Outreach to Faculty and Graduate Students A RESONANT MESSAGE 2 Abstract INTRODUCTION. Faculty contribution to the institutional repository is a major limiting factor in the successful provision of open access to scholarship, and thus to the advancement of research productivity and progress. Many have alluded to outreach messages through studies examining faculty concerns that underlie their reluctance to contribute, but specific open access messages demonstrated to resonate most with faculty have not been discussed with sufficient granularity. Indeed, many faculty benefits and concerns are likely either unknown to the faculty themselves, or unspoken, so the literature’s record of faculty benefits and perceptions of open access remains incomplete at best. DESCRIPTION OF PROGRAM. At Rutgers University, we have developed a targeted message that both addresses these unspoken/unknown concerns and benefits and speaks to the promise and inevitability of open access in a changing scholarly communication landscape.
    [Show full text]
  • DOING the RIGHT THING an Interview with Stevan Harnad (By
    DOING THE RIGHT THING An Interview With Stevan Harnad (by Mark Bekoff, Psychology Today, January 2015) https://www.psychologytoday.com/blog/animal-emotions/201501/doing-the-right-thing- interview-stevan-harnad MB: You’re Canada Research Chair in Cognitive Sciences at University of Quebec in Montreal and Professor of Web Science at University of Southampton in the UK: What do you actually do? SH: I do research on how the brain learns and communicates categories. Categorization is a very general cognitive capacity. I think it covers most of cognition. It just means doing the right thing with the right kind of thing: Eat what’s edible; avoid predators; and call a spade a “spade” (because most of language is categorization too). http://eprints.soton.ac.uk/261725/ And how do you do research on how the brain learns and communicates categories? Do you study animals’ brains? No. I study how humans do it, I try to model the mechanism generating that capacity computationally, and I test for clues and correlates with brain imagery (event- related potentials). Of these three methods, the third – observing and measuring brain events – is actually the least informative. Is that just because you can’t get deep enough into the brain, and manipulate it? No, even if we could manipulate people’s brains any way we wanted, what the brain can do, as an organ, is anything and everything we can do. The brain does not wear its functioning on its sleeve, to be read off by observation and manipulation, like the heart, which just pumps blood, or the lungs, which just pump air.
    [Show full text]
  • Stevan Harnad, University of Southampton, May 8, 1999
    Stevan Harnad, University of Southampton, May 8, 1999 [This is a revised draft of comments on the ebiomed proposal, sent to Harold Varmus earlier.] The following are my comments on: http://www.nih.gov/welcome/director/ebiomed/ebiomed.htm This extremely welcome and important initiative is deserving of the strongest support. The following recommendations are made in the interests of strengthening the proposal by clarifying some crucial central aspects and modifying or eliminating some minor, weaker aspects. E-BIOMED: A PROPOSAL FOR ELECTRONIC PUBLICATION IN THE BIOMEDICAL SCIENCES Prologue The full potential of electronic communication has yet to be realized. The scientific community has made only sparing use thus far of the Internet as a means to publish scientific work and to distribute it widely and without significant barriers to access. This generally accurate assessment of the current failure to exploit the full potential of the Internet for scientific publication has one prominent and extremely relevant and important exception. It would be much more accurate as well as helpful to note this explicitly from the outset, as this notable exception is very likely to be the model for all the rest of the disciplines: Physics is the exception (and to some degree, mathematics). It is now both an empirical and a historical fact that well over half of the current physics (journal) literature is freely available online from the Los Alamos Archive and its 14 mirror archives worldwide, and is being used by perhaps 50,000 physicists a day. http://xxx.lanl.gov/cgi-bin/show_monthly_submissions It would be misleading in the extreme to describe this as "sparing use"! Instead, it should be acknowledged that this has been a revolutionary change in Physics, and if there were a way to extend it to the other sciences (and the other learned disciplines) then the full potential of electronic communication WOULD indeed be realized.
    [Show full text]
  • The Symbol Grounding Problem
    The Symbol Grounding Problem http://www.ecs.soton.ac.uk/~harnad/Papers/Harnad/harnad90.sgproble... Harnad, S. (1990) The Symbol Grounding Problem. Physica D 42: 335-346. THE SYMBOL GROUNDING PROBLEM Stevan Harnad Department of Psychology Princeton University Princeton NJ 08544 [email protected] ABSTRACT: There has been much discussion recently about the scope and limits of purely symbolic models of the mind and about the proper role of connectionism in cognitive modeling. This paper describes the "symbol grounding problem": How can the semantic interpretation of a formal symbol system be made intrinsic to the system, rather than just parasitic on the meanings in our heads? How can the meanings of the meaningless symbol tokens, manipulated solely on the basis of their (arbitrary) shapes, be grounded in anything but other meaningless symbols? The problem is analogous to trying to learn Chinese from a Chinese/Chinese dictionary alone. A candidate solution is sketched: Symbolic representations must be grounded bottom-up in nonsymbolic representations of two kinds: (1) "iconic representations" , which are analogs of the proximal sensory projections of distal objects and events, and (2) "categorical representations" , which are learned and innate feature-detectors that pick out the invariant features of object and event categories from their sensory projections. Elementary symbols are the names of these object and event categories, assigned on the basis of their (nonsymbolic) categorical representations. Higher-order (3) "symbolic representations" , grounded in these elementary symbols, consist of symbol strings describing category membership relations (e.g., "An X is a Y that is Z"). Connectionism is one natural candidate for the mechanism that learns the invariant features underlying categorical representations, thereby connecting names to the proximal projections of the distal objects they stand for.
    [Show full text]
  • Stevan Harnad I Propose to Consider the Question, "Can Machines Think?"
    I propose to consider the question, "Can machines think http://www.ecs.soton.ac.uk/~harnad/Temp/turing.html To appear in: Epstein, Robert & Peters, Grace (Eds.) The Turing Test Sourcebook: Philosophical and Methodological Issues in the Quest for the Thinking Computer. Kluwer. ________________________________________________________________________ The Annotation Game: On Turing (1950) on Computing, Machinery, and Intelligence. Stevan Harnad I propose to consider the question, "Can machines think?" (Turing 1950) Turing starts on an equivocation. We know now that what he will go on to consider is not whether or not machines can think, but whether or not machines can do what thinkers like us can do -- and if so, how. Doing is performance capacity, empirically observable. Thinking (or cognition) is an internal state, its correlates empirically observable as neural activity (if we only knew which neural activity corresponds to thinking!) and its associated quality introspectively observable as our own mental state when we are thinking. Turing's proposal will turn out to have nothing to do with either observing neural states or introspecting mental states, but only with generating performance capacity (intelligence?) indistinguishable from that of thinkers like us. This should begin with definitions of... "machine" and "think"... [A] statistical survey such as a Gallup poll [would be] absurd. Instead of attempting such a definition I shall replace the question by another... in relatively unambiguous words. 1 of 28 11/09/06 12:57 I propose to consider the question, "Can machines think http://www.ecs.soton.ac.uk/~harnad/Temp/turing.html "Machine" will never be adequately defined in Turing's paper, although (what will eventually be known as) the "Turing Machine," the abstract description of a computer, will be.
    [Show full text]
  • Crowd-Sourced Peer Review: Substitute Or Supplement for the Current Outdated System?
    Crowd-Sourced Peer Review: Substitute or supplement for the current outdated system? blogs.lse.ac.uk/impactofsocialsciences/2014/08/21/crowd-sourced-peer-review-substitute-or-supplement/ 8/21/2014 The problem with peer review today is that there is so much research being produced that there are not enough experts with enough time to peer-review it all. As we look to address this problem, issues of standards and hierarchy remain unsolved. Stevan Harnad wonders whether crowd-sourced peer review could match, exceed, or come close to the benchmark of the current system. He predicts crowdsourcing will indeed be able to provide a supplement to the classical system, hopefully improving efficiency and accuracy, but not a substitute for it. If, as rumoured, Google builds a platform for depositing un-refereed research papers for “peer- reviewing” via crowd-sourcing, can this create a substitute for classical peer-review or will it merely supplement classical peer review with crowd-sourcing? In classical peer review, an expert (presumably qualified, and definitely answerable), an “action editor,” chooses experts (presumably qualified and definitely answerable), “referees,” to evaluate a submitted research paper in terms of correctness, quality, reliability, validity, originality, importance and relevance in order to determine whether it meets the standards of a journal with an established track-record for correctness, reliability, originality, quality, novelty, importance and relevance in a certain field. In each field there is usually a well-known hierarchy of journals, hence a hierarchy of peer-review standards, from the most rigorous and selective journals at the top all the way down to what is sometimes close to a vanity press at the bottom.
    [Show full text]
  • Animal Sentience: the Other-Minds Problem
    Animal Sentience 2018.100: Calvo on Reber on Origins of Mind Call for Commentary: Animal Sentience publishes Open Peer Commentary on all accepted target articles. Target articles are peer-reviewed. Commentaries are editorially reviewed. There are submitted commentaries as well as invited commentaries. Commentaries appear as soon as they have been revised and accepted. Target article authors may respond to their commentaries individually or in a joint response to multiple commentaries. Instructions: http://animalstudiesrepository.org/animsent/guidelines.html Inaugural Editorial Animal sentience: The other-minds problem Stevan Harnad Cognitive Sciences Institute Université du Québec à Montréal Abstract: The only feelings we can feel are our own. When it comes to the feelings of others, we can only infer them, based on their behavior — unless they tell us. This is the “other-minds problem.” Within our own species, thanks to language, this problem arises only for states in which people cannot speak (infancy, aphasia, sleep, anaesthesia, coma). Our species also has a uniquely powerful empathic or “mind-reading” capacity: We can (sometimes) perceive from the behavior of others when they are in states like our own. Our inferences have also been systematized and operationalized in biobehavioral science and supplemented by cognitive neuroimagery. Together, these make the other-minds problem within our own species a relatively minor one. But we cohabit the planet with other species, most of them very different from our own, and none of them able to talk. Inferring whether and what they feel is important not only for scientific but also for ethical reasons, because where feelings are felt, they can also be hurt.
    [Show full text]
  • Animal Sentience: the Other-Minds Problem
    Harnad, Stevan (2016) Animal sentience: The other-minds problem. Animal Sentience 1(1) DOI: 10.51291/2377-7478.1065 This article has appeared in the journal Animal Sentience, a peer-reviewed journal on animal cognition and feeling. It has been made open access, free for all, by WellBeing International and deposited in the WBI Studies Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Animal Sentience 2016.001: Harnad on Other Minds Call for Commentary: Animal Sentience publishes Open Peer Commentary on all accepted target articles. Target articles are peer-reviewed. Commentaries are editorially reviewed. There are submitted commentaries as well as invited commentaries. Commentaries appear as soon as they have been revised and accepted. Target article authors may respond to their commentaries individually or in a joint response to multiple commentaries. Instructions: http://animalstudiesrepository.org/animsent/guidelines.html Inaugural Editorial Animal sentience: The other-minds problem Stevan Harnad Cognitive Sciences Institute Université du Québec à Montréal Abstract: The only feelings we can feel are our own. When it comes to the feelings of others, we can only infer them, based on their behavior — unless they tell us. This is the “other-minds problem.” Within our own species, thanks to language, this problem arises only for states in which people cannot speak (infancy, aphasia, sleep, anaesthesia, coma). Our species also has a uniquely powerful empathic or “mind-reading” capacity: We can (sometimes) perceive from the behavior of others when they are in states like our own. Our inferences have also been systematized and operationalized in biobehavioral science and supplemented by cognitive neuroimagery.
    [Show full text]
  • In This Issue JULY 2017
    in this issue JULY 2017 ARTICLES 2 OA Advocates Weigh in on Democratization of Academic Journals: Scholastica Webinar Recap By Danielle Padula 4 ISMTE Asian-Pacific Conference 2017 Reported by Michael Willis, Tony Alves, Donald Samulack, PhD, Jennifer Deyton, and Charley Miao 16 ISMTE Member Profile: Kristen Overstreet By Kristen Overstreet MISCELLANEOUS 15 Committee Update 17 Grammatic Fanatic Comic 19 From the Forum 21 Calendar 10 th Anniversary ARTICLE https://dx.doi.org/10.18243/eon/2017.10.6.1 OA Advocates Weigh in on Democratization of Academic Journals: Scholastica Webinar Recap By Danielle Padula • The sustainability of current OA journal publishing Community Development Manager approaches Scholastica • Possibilities and challenges surrounding the de- mocratization of academic journals • Next steps to speed up the transition from subscription-based journals to OA • The role of technology in democratizing academic journal publishing • In recent years, the open access (OA) movement has been How nonprofit organizations and scholars can facili- gaining ground within the academic community, but despite tate sustainable OA increased efforts to make scholarship free for readers online, there are concerns about how to do so in a way that’sstruc- Stevan Harnad spoke to his longstanding call for universal turally and economically sustainable. Funding for OA journals, Green OA to solve the serials crisis, which would require all like budgets for serials, still comes primarily from academic researchers to make their works freely available in in- institutions. With some article-processing charges creeping stitutional repositories or preprint servers and thereby en- into the high thousands of dollars, there is concern that OA able libraries to cancel expensive journal subscriptions.
    [Show full text]