RUSSELL's HIDDEN BERGSONISM the Title Above Certainly Sounds

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

RUSSELL's HIDDEN BERGSONISM the Title Above Certainly Sounds APPENDIX I RUSSELL'S HIDDEN BERGSONISM The title above certainly sounds strange and even facetious; for Russell's attitude to Bergson was not only that of philosophical disagreement, but of positive, almost personal dislike. This dislike accounts for Russell's frequent misunderstandings and misrepresentations of Bergson's thought - the misrepresentations which often border on caricature. It is true that this caricaturing was due more to Russell's inattentive reading than to a conscious desire to ridicule. Russell's own reading of Bergson was accurately characterized by Russell himself when he wrote that "to read an author in order to refute him is not the way to understand him." (OKEW, 47)*). Sometimes, however, the desire to ridicule is clearly discernible; for instance when, ignoring all the distinctions which the author of Creative Evolution draws between instinct and intuition, he confuses them, adding with humor that intuition is strongest "in ants, bees and Bergson." (PB, 3.) In any case, inattentive reading is as much a sign of intellectual indifference or hostility as a distorting caricature. Whether the touch of personal animosity in Russell's attitude was due, as it was submitted, to his suspicion that Bergson "lured" Whitehead away from him, is not certainl , but it would not be too surprising; philosophers are human beings too, Russell more than any other. Although we pointed out a number of times the deep differences separating Bergson's thought from that of Russell, let us briefly recall those which are the most basic. In this way we shall have a contrasting backdrop against which the unintentional agreements between them will appear even more striking. One of Russell's sentences in Our Knowledge of the External World (1914) summarizes the contrast between his and Bergson's philosophy in the most concise way: "Both in thought and in feeling, to realize the unimportance of time is the gate of wisdom." (OKEW, 167). In Mysticism and Logic he repeated the same sentence, but somehow more cautiously: "Both in thought and in feeling, even 336 BERGSON AND MODERN PHYSICS though time be real, to realize the unimportance of time is the gate of wisdom." (ML 21-22; italics mine). But this note of caution disappears altogether in the sentences which immediatel} follow: That this is the case may be seen at once by asking ourselves why our feelings toward the past are so different from our feelings toward the future. The reason for this difference is wholly practical: our wishes can affect the future, not the past, the future is to some extent subject to our power, while the past is unalterably fixed. But every future will some day be past: if we see the past truly now, it must, when it was still future, have been just what we now see it to be, and what is now future must be just what we shall see it to be when it has become past. The felt difference of quality between past and future, therefore, is not an intrinsic difference, but only a difference in relation to us; to impartial contemplation, it ceases to exist. And impartiality of contemplation is, in the intellectual sphere, that very same virtue of disinterestedness which, in the sphere of action, appears as justice and unselfishness. Whoever wishes to see the world truly, to rise in thought above the tyranny of practical desires, must learn to overcome the difference of attitude towards past and future and to survey the whole stream of time in one comprehensive vision. It certainly would be difficult to find in the philosophical literature a passage which would be more anti-Bergsonian in spirit as well as in letter. It is a perfect illustration of the view that "all is given" (tout est donne) - the view which eliminates becoming, transforms the future into a concealed present and wipes out the qualitative differences between the successive phases of time. It is the view of all strict determinists from Democritus to Laplace, and Russell is merely consistent when he says that "it is a mere accident that we have no memory of the future". (OKEW, 234). It eliminates the concept of causation in its original and dynamical sense by substituting for it the relation of logical co-implication in which the future is deducible from the past and vice versa; thus there is not such a thing as "direction of time" or "asymmetry of becoming". In Russell's words: "We shall do better to allow the effect to be before the cause or simultaneous with it, because nothing of any scientific importance depends upon its being after the cause." (OKEW, 226.) This fundamental difference between Russell's and Bergson's views shows itself clearly in their attitude toward Plato and Zeno. While for Bergson, "the intelligible world" of ideas resembles the world of solids in its essential character except that its constitutive elements are "lighter, more diaphanous, easier for the intellect to deal with than the image of concrete things", for Russell in 1912 Plato's doctrine of ideas is one of the most successful attempts to solve the problem of the universals which RUSSELL'S HIDDEN BERGSONISM 337 he accepted with some terminological modifications. He was aware that this view leads to a very sharp kind of dualism: Thus thoughts and feelings, minds and physical objects exist. But universals do not exist in this sense; we shall say that they subsist or have being, where 'being' is opposed to 'existence' as being timeless. The world of universals, therefore, may be also described as the world of being. It is true that he somehow softens his commitment to Platonism by the following rather sober and remarkably impartial passage: The world of being is unchangeable, rigid, exact, delightful to the mathematician, the logician, the builder of metaphysical systems, and all who love perfection more than life. The world of existence is fleeting, vague, without sharp boundaries, without clear plan or arrangement, but it contains all thoughts and feelings, all the data of sense, and all physical objects, everything that can do either good or harm, everything that makes any difference to the value of life and the world. According to our tempera­ ments, we shall prefer the contemplation of the one or of the other. The one we do not prefer will probably seem to us a pale shadow of the one we prefer, and hardly worthy to be regarded as in any sense real. But the truth is that both have the same claim on our impartial attention, both are real, and both are important to the metaphysician. (P. 100; italics added.) The passages just quoted show clearly the complexity of Russell's mind as well as the resulting instability of his views. While explicitly admitting his preference for the realm of being, he still conceded then the reality of becoming only to deny - only after two years - the reality of time altogether while at the same time ridiculing Kant for degrading time to a mere appearance. (OKEW, 116-117). But in the passage just quoted another note creeps in - an uneasy awareness that the metaphysical preferences for either being or becoming are perhaps mere personal idiosyncracies, due to individual differences in temperament. A tendency to prefer the metaphysics of Being, together with an underlying note of radical scepticism are two characteristic features of Russell's thought. Comparison of Bergson's and Russell's attitude toward Zeno's para­ doxes will show again the basic contrast in their philosophical views, but at the same time will bring out in the most unexpected way certain hidden affinities. Bergson's view of Zeno's paradoxes was consistently held through all his books: the paradoxes arise from the fallacious assumption that motion and time are divisible in infinitum, that is, that the only parts of them which are indivisible are geometrical points and durationless instants. This assumption is based on the confusion of the movement 338 BERGSON AND MODERN PHYSICS itself with its motionless trace in space; it is this motionless trace, not the act of moving (la mobilite, Ie mouvant), which is infinitely divisible. "At bottom, the illusion arises from this, that the movement, once effected, has laid along its course a motionless trajectory on which we can count as many immobilities as we will. From this we conclude that the movement, while being effected, lays at each instant beneath it a position with which it coincides. We do not see that the trajectory is created in one stroke, although a certain time is required for it; and that though we can divide at will the trajectory once created, we cannot divide its creation, which is an act in progress and not a thing." 2) Russell's comment on Zeno in his Principles of Mathematics (1903) was significantly different: After two thousand years of continual refutation, these sophisms were reinstated, and made the foundation of a mathematical renaissance, by a German professor, who probably never dreamed of any connection between himself and Zeno. Weierstrass, by strictly banishing infinitesimals, has at last shown that we live in an unchanging world, and that the arrow, at every moment of its flight, is truly at rest. The only point where Zeno probably erred was in inferring (if he did infer) that, because there is no change, therefore the world must be in the same state at one time as at another. This conse­ quence by no means follows. (PM, 347; italics mine.) In other words, Russell agrees with Zeno that we are living in "an unchanging world"; but against Zeno he claims that the world is not in the same state at every moment.
Recommended publications
  • Implications for a Future Information Theory Based on Vacuum 1 Microtopology
    Getting Something Out of Nothing: Implications for a Future Information Theory Based on Vacuum 1 Microtopology William Michael Kallfelz 2 Committee for Philosophy and the Sciences University of Maryland at College Park Abstract (word count: 194) Submitted October 3, 2005 Published in IANANO Conference Proceedings : October 31-November 4, 2005 3 Contemporary theoretical physicists H. S. Green and David R. Finkelstein have recently advanced theories depicting space-time as a singular limit, or condensate, formed from fundamentally quantum micro topological units of information, or process (denoted respectively by ‘qubits,’ or ‘chronons.’) H. S. Green (2000) characterizes the manifold of space-time as a parafermionic statistical algebra generated fundamentally by qubits. David Finkelstein (2004a-c) models the space-time manifold as singular limit of a regular structure represented by a Clifford algebra, whose generators γ α represent ‘chronons,’ i.e., elementary quantum processes. Both of these theories are in principle experimentally testable. Green writes that his parafermionic embeddings “hav[e] an important advantage over their classical counterparts [in] that they have a direct physical interpretation and their parameters are in principle observable.” (166) David Finkelstein discusses in detail unique empirical ramifications of his theory in (2004b,c) which most notably include the removal of quantum field-theoretic divergences. Since the work of Shannon and Hawking, associations with entropy, information, and gravity emerged in the study of Hawking radiation. Nowadays, the theories of Green and Finkelstein suggest that the study of space-time lies in the development of technologies better able to probe its microtopology in controlled laboratory conditions. 1 Total word count, including abstract & footnotes: 3,509.
    [Show full text]
  • Stanislaw Piatkiewicz and the Beginnings of Mathematical Logic in Poland
    HISTORIA MATHEMATICA 23 (1996), 68±73 ARTICLE NO. 0005 Stanisøaw PiaËtkiewicz and the Beginnings of Mathematical Logic in Poland TADEUSZ BATO G AND ROMAN MURAWSKI View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE Department of Mathematics and Computer Science, Adam Mickiewicz University, ul. Matejki 48/49, 60-769 PoznanÂ, Poland provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector This paper presents information on the life and work of Stanisøaw PiaËtkiewicz (1849±?). His Algebra w logice (Algebra in Logic) of 1888 contains an exposition of the algebra of logic and its use in representing syllogisms. This was the ®rst original Polish publication on symbolic logic. It appeared 20 years before analogous works by èukasiewicz and Stamm. 1996 Academic Press, Inc. In dem Aufsatz werden Informationen zu Leben und Werk von Stanisøaw PiaËtkiewicz (1849±?) gegeben. Sein Algebra w logice (Algebra in der Logik) von 1888 enthaÈlt eine Darstel- lung der Algebra der Logik und ihre Anwendung auf die Syllogistik. PiaËtkiewicz' Schrift war die erste polnische Publikation uÈ ber symbolische Logik. Sie erschien 20 Jahre vor aÈhnlichen Arbeiten von èukasiewicz und Stamm. 1996 Academic Press, Inc. W pracy przedstawiono osobeË i dzieøo Stanisøawa PiaËtkiewicza (1849±?). W szczego lnosÂci analizuje sieË jego rozpraweË Algebra w logice z roku 1888, w kto rej zajmowaø sieË on nowymi no wczas ideami algebry logiki oraz ich zastosowaniami do sylogistyki. Praca ta jest pierwszaË oryginalnaË polskaË publikacjaË z zakresu logiki symbolicznej. Ukazaøa sieË 20 lat przed analog- icznymi pracami èukasiewicza i Stamma. 1996 Academic Press, Inc. MSC 1991 subject classi®cations: 03-03, 01A55.
    [Show full text]
  • Supervised Language Modeling for Temporal Resolution of Texts
    Supervised Language Modeling for Temporal Resolution of Texts Abhimanu Kumar Matthew Lease Jason Baldridge Dept. of Computer Science School of Information Department of Linguistics University of Texas at Austin University of Texas at Austin University of Texas at Austin [email protected] [email protected] [email protected] ABSTRACT describe any form of communication without cables (e.g. internet We investigate temporal resolution of documents, such as deter- access). As such, the word wireless embodies implicit time cues, mining the date of publication of a story based on its text. We a notion we might generalize by inferring its complete temporal describe and evaluate a model that build histograms encoding the distribution as well as that of all other words. By harnessing many probability of different temporal periods for a document. We con- such implicit cues in combination across a document, we might fur- struct histograms based on the Kullback-Leibler Divergence be- ther infer a unique temporal distribution for the overall document. tween the language model for a test document and supervised lan- As in prior document dating studies, we partition the timeline guage models for each interval. Initial results indicate this language (and document collection) to infer an unique language model (LM) modeling approach is effective for predicting the dates of publica- underlying each time period [10, 14]. While prior work consid- tion of short stories, which contain few explicit mentions of years. ered texts from the past 10-20 years, our work is more historically- oriented, predicting publication dates for historical works of fiction.
    [Show full text]
  • 24° Congresso UECI TOSSIGNANO (BO-Imola) Villa Santa Maria
    Unione Esperantista Cattolica Italiana U.E.C.I IDO Fare24° clicCongresso per modificare UECI lo stile del sottotitolo dello schema TOSSIGNANO (BO-Imola) Villa Santa Maria - 4-8 giugno 2010 www.ueci.it 4 I protagonisti • Louis Couturat era un matematico, logico e glottoteta francese, noto per i suoi contributi allo sviluppo delle logica formale. • Fu fondatore della Delegazione per l'adozione di una lingua ausiliaria internazionale. (Ris-Orangis , 17 gennaio 1868 – 3 agosto 1914) 2424° Congresso UECI 4-8 GIUGNO 2010 Il marchese Louis de Beaufront • Il marchese Louis de Beaufront (1855 – 1935) è stato un linguista, glottoteta ed esperantista francese. • La sua vita rimane piena di misteri: si seppe dopo la sua morte che non era marchese, che era di padre sconosciuto e che il suo vero nome era in realtà Louis Chevreux. Precettore privato al servizio di ricche famiglie, celibe. • Consacrò tutto il suo tempo libero alla diffusione della lingua, creò le basi del movimento esperantista. 24° Congresso UECI 4-8 GIUGNO 2010 • Alcune divergenze lo opposero all'iniziatore della lingua, Ludwik Lejzer Zamenhof e alla maggioranza degli esperantisti francesi. • Non partecipò al primo congresso esperantista di Boulogne-sur- Mer dove fu adottato il Fundamento de Esperanto, cioè le norme intangibili che garantiscono la stabilità della lingua. • Louis de Beaufront creò l’IDO come tentativo di creare una versione più semplice dell'esperanto. • Ido in esperanto significa discendente ma è anche l'abbreviazione di esperantido 24° Congresso UECI 4-8 GIUGNO 2010 LA STORIA • Nell'ottobre 1907, a Parigi, un comitato internazionale di 12 membri si riunì per scegliere la lingua artificiale più adatta alla comunicazione internazionale.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 2 the Combinatory
    Chapter 2 The Combinatory 1. Although Leibniz generally supported and adopted the logic of the Schools, while at the same time correcting and completing it, it would be a mistake to believe that his own logic was only a development or refinement of that of Aristotle. Leibniz himself suggests the opposite, when, after having bestowed on Aristotle through the mouth of Theophilus, the sumptuous praise we have read above (Chap. 1, §1), he has Philalethes deliver the following compliment: “You appear to defend common logic, but I see clearly that what you are presenting belongs to a much higher logic, which stands to the common sort as erudition does to the letters of the alphabet.”1 It is to this higher logic and not to that of Aristotle that he gives the title “universal mathematics.”2 And it is this that we must now investigate and explain. However novel Leibniz’s logic was to be, the root idea was nonetheless suggested to him by Aristotle, as he reports in several passages.3 He was not yet twelve years old when he immersed himself with pleasure in the intricacies of scholastic logic: he delighted in the books of Zabarella, Rubio, and Fonseca, and he read Suarez as easily as Milesian fables or novels. Already eager for innovation and tormented by the desire to invent, he cast onto paper criticisms and projects of reform; he acknowledged later that he experienced great pleasure in rereading the drafts he had written when he was fourteen years old. At that age, he had an idea that was to be the germ of his entire logic.
    [Show full text]
  • Photogenic Venus: the "Cinematographic Turn" and Its Alternatives in Nineteenth-Century France
    Photogenic Venus: The "Cinematographic Turn" and Its Alternatives in Nineteenth-Century France The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Canales, Jimena. 2002. Photogenic Venus: The "cinematographic turn" and its alternatives in nineteenth-century France. Isis 93, no. 4: 585-613. Published Version http://dx.doi.org/10.1086/375953 Citable link http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:3210601 Terms of Use This article was downloaded from Harvard University’s DASH repository, and is made available under the terms and conditions applicable to Other Posted Material, as set forth at http:// nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of- use#LAA Photogenic Venus The “Cinematographic Turn” and Its Alternatives in Nineteenth-Century France By Jimena Canales* ABSTRACT During the late nineteenth century, scientists around the world disagreed as to the types of instruments and methods that should be used for determining the most important con- stant of celestial mechanics: the solar parallax. Venus’s 1874 transit across the sun was seen as the best opportunity for ending decades of debate. However, a mysterious “black drop” that appeared between Venus and the sun and individual differences in observations of the phenomenon brought traditional methods into disrepute. To combat these difficulties, the astronomer Jules Janssen devised a controversial new instrument, the “photographic revolver,” that photographed Venus at regular intervals. Another solution came from phys- icists, who rivaled the astronomers’ dominance in precision measurements by deducing the solar parallax from physical measurements of the speed of light.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:Quant-Ph/0206117V3 1 Sep 2002
    Preprint NSF-ITP-02-62 A SIMPLE QUANTUM EQUATION FOR DECOHERENCE AND DISSIPATION (†) Erasmo Recami Facolt`adi Ingegneria, Universit`astatale di Bergamo, Dalmine (BG), Italy; INFN—Sezione di Milano, Milan, Italy; and Kavli Institute for Theoretical Physics, UCSB, CA 93106, USA. Ruy H. A. Farias LNLS - Synchrotron Light National Laboratory; Campinas, S.P.; Brazil. [email protected] Abstract – Within the density matrix formalism, it is shown that a simple way to get decoherence is through the introduction of a “quantum” of time (chronon): which implies replacing the differential Liouville–von Neumann equation with a finite-difference version of it. In this way, one is given the possibility of using a rather simple quantum equation to describe the decoherence effects due to dissipation. Namely, the mere introduction (not of a “time-lattice”, but simply) of a “chronon” allows us to go on from differential to finite-difference equations; and in particular to write down the quantum-theoretical equations (Schroedinger equation, Liouville–von Neumann equation,...) in three different ways: “retarded”, “symmetrical”, and “advanced”. One of such three formulations —the arXiv:quant-ph/0206117v3 1 Sep 2002 retarded one— describes in an elementary way a system which is exchanging (and losing) energy with the environment; and in its density-matrix version, indeed, it can be easily shown that all non-diagonal terms go to zero very rapidly. keywords: quantum decoherence, interaction with the environment, dissipation, quan- tum measurement theory, finite-difference equations, chronon, Caldirola, density-matrix formalism, Liouville–von Neumann equation (†) This reasearch was supported in part by the N.S.F. under Grant No.PHY99-07949; and by INFN and Murst/Miur (Italy).
    [Show full text]
  • The Esperantist Background of René De Saussure's Work
    Chapter 1 The Esperantist background of René de Saussure’s work Marc van Oostendorp Radboud University and The Meertens Institute ené de Saussure was arguably more an esperantist than a linguist – R somebody who was primarily inspired by his enthusiasm for the language of L. L. Zamenhof, and the hope he thought it presented for the world. His in- terest in general linguistics seems to have stemmed from his wish to show that the structure of Esperanto was better than that of its competitors, and thatit reflected the ways languages work in general. Saussure became involved in the Esperanto movement around 1906, appar- ently because his brother Ferdinand had asked him to participate in an inter- national Esperanto conference in Geneva; Ferdinand himself did not want to go because he did not want to become “compromised” (Künzli 2001). René be- came heavily involved in the movement, as an editor of the Internacia Scienca Re- vuo (International Science Review) and the national journal Svisa Espero (Swiss Hope), as well as a member of the Akademio de Esperanto, the Academy of Es- peranto that was and is responsible for the protection of the norms of the lan- guage. Among historians of the Esperanto movement, he is also still known as the inventor of the spesmilo, which was supposed to become an international currency among Esperantists (Garvía 2015). At the time, the interest in issues of artificial language solutions to perceived problems in international communication was more widespread in scholarly cir- cles than it is today. In the western world, German was often used as a language of e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • How Peircean Was the “'Fregean' Revolution” in Logic?
    HOW PEIRCEAN WAS THE “‘FREGEAN’ REVOLUTION” IN LOGIC? Irving H. Anellis Peirce Edition, Institute for American Thought Indiana University – Purdue University at Indianapolis Indianapolis, IN, USA [email protected] Abstract. The historiography of logic conceives of a Fregean revolution in which modern mathematical logic (also called symbolic logic) has replaced Aristotelian logic. The preeminent expositors of this conception are Jean van Heijenoort (1912–1986) and Don- ald Angus Gillies. The innovations and characteristics that comprise mathematical logic and distinguish it from Aristotelian logic, according to this conception, created ex nihlo by Gottlob Frege (1848–1925) in his Begriffsschrift of 1879, and with Bertrand Rus- sell (1872–1970) as its chief This position likewise understands the algebraic logic of Augustus De Morgan (1806–1871), George Boole (1815–1864), Charles Sanders Peirce (1838–1914), and Ernst Schröder (1841–1902) as belonging to the Aristotelian tradi- tion. The “Booleans” are understood, from this vantage point, to merely have rewritten Aristotelian syllogistic in algebraic guise. The most detailed listing and elaboration of Frege’s innovations, and the characteristics that distinguish mathematical logic from Aristotelian logic, were set forth by van Heijenoort. I consider each of the elements of van Heijenoort’s list and note the extent to which Peirce had also developed each of these aspects of logic. I also consider the extent to which Peirce and Frege were aware of, and may have influenced, one another’s logical writings. AMS (MOS) 2010 subject classifications: Primary: 03-03, 03A05, 03C05, 03C10, 03G27, 01A55; secondary: 03B05, 03B10, 03E30, 08A20; Key words and phrases: Peirce, abstract algebraic logic; propositional logic; first-order logic; quantifier elimina- tion, equational classes, relational systems §0.
    [Show full text]
  • Saussure Esperantista
    UNIVERSITÀ DEGLI STUDI DI PARMA Facoltà di Lettere e Filosofia Corso di Laurea in Civiltà letterarie e Storia delle civiltà RELAZIONE FINALE SAUSSURE ESPERANTISTA Relatore: Chiar.mo Prof. Davide Astori Correlatore: Char.ma Prof.ssa Fabienne Winkler Laureanda: Stefania Rinaldi Matricola n.175562 ANNO ACCADEMICO 2009/2010 1 INDICE Introduzione............................................................................................3 1 Breve storia della nascita dell'esperanto..............................................5 2 René de Saussure...................................................................................15 2.1. Notizie biografiche, inserimento e movimenti all'interno dell'ambiente esperantista.................................................15 2.2. Le origini della Nuova Lingua: Il Nov-Esperanto, o Esperanto II.........................................................................20 2.3. La moneta unica per un'unica Nazione: Lo Spesmilo.....29 2.4. Il ricordo di René de Saussure...........................................32 3 René, Ferdinand e l'Esperanto.................................................................37 4 Bibliografia analitica della vita di René de Saussure..........................43 5 Conclusioni....................................................................................................55 6 Appendice......................................................................................................57 7 Bibliografia....................................................................................................63
    [Show full text]
  • Electro-Gravity Via Geometric Chronon Field
    Physical Science International Journal 7(3): 152-185, 2015, Article no.PSIJ.2015.066 ISSN: 2348-0130 SCIENCEDOMAIN international www.sciencedomain.org Electro-Gravity via Geometric Chronon Field Eytan H. Suchard1* 1Geometry and Algorithms, Applied Neural Biometrics, Israel. Author’s contribution The sole author designed, analyzed and interpreted and prepared the manuscript. Article Information DOI: 10.9734/PSIJ/2015/18291 Editor(s): (1) Shi-Hai Dong, Department of Physics School of Physics and Mathematics National Polytechnic Institute, Mexico. (2) David F. Mota, Institute of Theoretical Astrophysics, University of Oslo, Norway. Reviewers: (1) Auffray Jean-Paul, New York University, New York, USA. (2) Anonymous, Sãopaulo State University, Brazil. (3) Anonymous, Neijiang Normal University, China. (4) Anonymous, Italy. (5) Anonymous, Hebei University, China. Complete Peer review History: http://sciencedomain.org/review-history/9858 Received 13th April 2015 th Original Research Article Accepted 9 June 2015 Published 19th June 2015 ABSTRACT Aim: To develop a model of matter that will account for electro-gravity. Interacting particles with non-gravitational fields can be seen as clocks whose trajectory is not Minkowsky geodesic. A field, in which each such small enough clock is not geodesic, can be described by a scalar field of time, whose gradient has non-zero curvature. This way the scalar field adds information to space-time, which is not anticipated by the metric tensor alone. The scalar field can’t be realized as a coordinate because it can be measured from a reference sub-manifold along different curves. In a “Big Bang” manifold, the field is simply an upper limit on measurable time by interacting clocks, backwards from each event to the big bang singularity as a limit only.
    [Show full text]
  • Interlingvistiko
    Interlingvistiko Enkonduko en la sciencon pri planlingvoj 1 2 Universitato Adam Mickiewicz – Uniwersytet im. Adama Mickiewicza Interlingvistikaj Studoj – Studia Interlingwistyki Vĕra Barandovská-Frank Interlingvistiko Enkonduko en la sciencon pri planlingvoj Poznań 2020 3 Interlingvistikaj Studoj 1 Redaktanto de la serio – Redaktor serii: Ilona Koutny Redaktanto de la volumo – Redaktor tomu: Ilona Koutny Reviziantoj – Recenzenci: Wim Jansen, Ida Stria Bildo en la titolpaĝo – Obraz na okładce: Katalin Kováts Plano de titolpaĝo – Projekt okładki: Ilona Koutny © Teksto – Tekst: Vĕra Barandovská-Frank © Bildo – Obraz na okładce: Katalin Kováts © Eldono – Edycja: Wydawnictwo Rys Publikigita kun subteno de Akademio Internacia de la Sciencoj San Marino dofinansowane przez Międzynarodową Akademię Nauk San Marino Wydanie I Poznań 2020 ISBN 978-83-65483-88-1 Wydanie: Wydawnictwo Rys Dąbrówka, ul. Kolejowa 41 62-070 Dopiewo tel. 600 44 55 80 e-mail: [email protected] www.wydawnictworys.com 4 Enhavtabelo Antaŭparolo ..................................................................................................................... 9 Enkonduko .................................................................................................................... 11 1. Interlingvistiko kiel scienco ..................................................................................... 15 2. Antikvaj interlingvoj ................................................................................................ 27 2.1. La aramea lingvo ............................................................................................
    [Show full text]