ECE4330 Lecture 2: Math Review (Continued) Prof

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

ECE4330 Lecture 2: Math Review (Continued) Prof ECE4330 Lecture 2: Math Review (continued) Prof. Mohamad Hassoun Trigonometric Identities (continued): 2휋 2 sin 푥 cos 푥 = sin 2푥 cos(휔푡) → 휔 = 2휋푓, 휔 = (rad/sec) 푇 1 (sin 푥)2 + (cos 푥)2 = 1 푇 = , 푓 is the Hz frequency; 푇 is the period 푓 (cos 푥)2− (sin 푥)2 = cos 2푥 1 (cos 푥)2 = (1 + cos 2푥) Note: (cos 푥)2 ≡ cos2 푥 2 1 (sin 푥)2 = (1 − cos 2푥) 2 1 (cos 푥)3 = (3 cos 푥 + cos 3푥) 4 1 (sin 푥)3 = (3 sin 푥 − sin 3푥) 4 sin(푥 ± 푦) = sin 푥 cos 푦 ± cos 푥 sin 푦 휋 휋 휋 [Example: sin(푥 ± ) = sin(푥) cos ( ) ± cos(푥) sin ( ) = ±cos (푥)] 2 2 2 cos(푥 ± 푦) = cos 푥 cos 푦 ∓ sin 푥 sin 푦 [Example: cos(푥 ± 휋) = cos(푥) cos(휋) ∓ sin(푥) sin(휋) = −cos (푥) tan 푥 ± tan 푦 tan(푥 ± 푦) = 1 ∓ tan 푥 tan 푦 1 sin 푥 sin 푦 = [cos(푥 − 푦) − cos(푥 + 푦)] 2 1 cos 푥 cos 푦 = [cos(푥 − 푦) + cos(푥 + 푦)] 2 1 sin 푥 cos 푦 = [sin(푥 − 푦) + sin(푥 + 푦)] 2 Example. Find sin(15°) using trigonometric identities (no calculator) sin(15°) = sin(45° − 30°) θ cos θ sin θ = sin(45°) cos(30°) − cos(45°) sin(30°) 휋 1 2 3 2 1 6 − 2 (30°) √3 √ √ √ √ √ 6 = − = ≈ 0.259 2 2 2 2 2 2 4 휋 (45°) √2 √2 4 2 2 Example. Express cos4(푥) as the sum of simple sinusoids. 1 (cos 푥 )4 = cos 푥 (cos 푥)3 = cos 푥 [ (3 cos 푥 + cos 3푥)] 4 3 1 = (cos 푥)2 + cos 푥 cos 3푥 4 4 3 1 1 1 = ( ) (1 + cos 2푥) + ( ) [cos(−2푥) + cos(4푥)] 4 2 4 2 3 3 1 1 = + cos 2푥 + cos 2푥 + cos 4푥 8 8 8 8 3 1 1 = + cos 2푥 + cos 4푥 8 2 8 Note that the result includes a constant term, a sinusoid at 휔0 = 2 and a sinusoid at frequency 4. These are called harmonic (multiple) frequencies. Formulas for exponentiated sinusoids as sum of pure sinusoids: n even: 푛 −1 2 푛 1 푛 2 푛 (cos 푥) = (푛) + ∑ ( ) cos[(푛 − 2푘)푥] 2푛 2푛 푘 2 푘=0 푛 −1 2 푛 푛 1 푛 2 ( −푘) 푛 (sin 푥) = (푛) + ∑(−1) 2 ( ) cos[(푛 − 2푘)푥] 2푛 2푛 푘 2 푘=0 n odd: 푛−1 2 2 푛 (cos 푥)푛 = ∑ ( ) cos[(푛 − 2푘)푥] 2푛 푘 푘=0 푛−1 2 푛−1 2 ( −푘) 푛 (sin 푥)푛 = ∑(−1) 2 ( ) sin[(푛 − 2푘)푥] 2푛 푘 푘=0 With the binomial coefficient: 0! = 1 푛 푛! ( ) = 푓표푟 0 ≤ 푘 ≤ 푛 n! = (1)(2)(3)…(n) 푘 푘! (푛 − 푘)! Example. Express cos4(푥) as a sum of pure sinusoids. 1 4! 2 4 4 (cos 푥)4 = ( ) + [( ) cos((4 − 0)푥) + ( ) cos((4 − 2)푥)] 24 2! (4 − 2)! 16 0 1 3 1 3 1 1 = + [cos 4푥 + 4 cos 2푥] = + cos 2푥 + cos 4푥 8 8 8 2 8 Your turn: Expand the following expressions as a sum of pure sinusoids, cos5 푥 = ? sin4 푥 = ? (a) Employing Trig identities and (b) Employing the formulas. Your turn: Use Mathcad to plot 푓(푥) = cos푛(푥) for 푛 = 20 and 200. Your turn (challenge): Solve for 훽 as a function of 푘 and 훼 in the equation, sin(훼) − sin(훽) + 푘푠푖푛(훼 + 훽) = 0. −2푘+(1+푘2)cos (훼) Ans. 훽 = 푐표푠−1 { } 1−2푘푐표푠(훼)+푘2 Has the same frequency Example. Show that 푎 cos 푥 + 푏 sin 푥 = 퐶 cos(푥 + 휃 ) where −푏 퐶 = √푎2 + 푏2 푎푛푑 휃 = tan−1 푎 Employing the trig identity cos(푥 + 푦) = cos 푥 cos 푦 − sin 푥 sin 푦, we may write: C cos(푥 + 휃) = (퐶 cos 휃) cos 푥 + (− 퐶 sin 휃) sin 푥 Let 푎 = 퐶푐표푠(휃) and 푏 = −퐶푠푖푛(휃), then 푎2 + 푏2 = 퐶2(cos 휃)2 + (−퐶)2(sin 휃)2 = 퐶2[(cos 휃)2 + (sin 휃)2] = 퐶2 Therefore, 퐶 = √푎2 + 푏2 −푏 퐶 푠푖푛휃 −푏 and = = 푡푎푛 휃 → 휃 = 푡푎푛−1 푎 퐶 푐표푠휃 푎 Example. Express 푓(푡) = cos(푡) + sin(푡) as a single sinusoid. Solution: a = 1 , b = 1 퐶 = √12 + 12 = √2 −푏 −1 −휋 휃 = tan−1 = tan−1 ( ) = tan−1(−1) = 푎 1 4 휋 푓(푡) = √2 cos (푡 − ) 4 −푏 Caution when evaluating tan−1 ( ) 퐰퐢퐭퐡 풂 < 0 using a calculator: 푎 If you use your calculator to find the inverse tangent and if 푎 < 0, then you must add (or subtract) 휋 to (from) the answer. Example. Express −2 cos(푡) − 3 sin(푡) as a single sinusoid. Here,푎 = −2; 푏 = −3. Then, −푏 3 tan−1 ( ) = tan−1 ( ) = −0.983 radians (calculator answer) 푎 −2 Since 푎 < 0, we need to add (or subtract) 휋, 휃 = −0.983 ± 3.1416 = 2.159 (or − 4.1246) 퐶 = √(−2)2 + (−3)2 = √4 + 9 = √13 푓(푡) = √13 cos(푡 + 2.159); we choose the smaller angle (in absolute value) Matlab and Mathcad have the atan2 function that automatically adjusts the angle. Here is the syntax. Mathcad syntax: atan2(denominator, numerator) Example: atan2(-2,3) = 2.159 Matlab syntax: atan2(numerator, denominator) Example: atan2(3,-2) = 2.159 Your turn: Express the following functions as a single cosine function. Verify your answer by plotting the functions. 휋 푓(푥) = cos(푥) − sin(푥) , 푓(푥) = − cos(푥) + sin(푥) , 푓(푥) = cos(푥) + sin (푥 + ) 3 Complex Numbers Representations: Cartesian, polar, phasor, and exponential z ∈ C, 푗 ≜ √−1 (or 푗2 = −1) Re (z) = a Im (z) = b Cartesian representation: z = a + jb We may represent the complex number in polar form as Polar representation: z = (r, θ) where, r = |z| is the magnitude of z θ = ∠푧 is the angle of z Phasor notation: z = |z| ∠푧 Employing the Pythagorean Theorem we may write, 2 2 푟 = √푎 + 푏 a 푏 푏 tan 휃 = → 휃 = tan−1 ( ) 푎 푎 푎 = 푟 cos 휃 푏 = 푟 sin 휃 Therefore, we have the following relation between the Cartesian and polar representations: z = a + jb = r (cos 휃 + j sin 휃) Euler’s Identity: 푒푗휃 = 푐표푠 휃 + 푗 푠푖푛 휃 Leonhard Euler(1707 – 1783) was a pioneering Swiss mathematician and physicist. (Euler’s Identity will be proved in the next lecture) 푗휋 1 − −휋 −휋 Example: = 푒 2 = cos + 푗 sin = 0 + 푗(−1) = −푗 푗휋 2 2 푒 2 Exponential form of complex numbers: z = a + jb = r (cos 휃 + j sin 휃) = r푒푗θ = |푧|푒푗∠푧 Example. Express z = 2 + j3 in exponential form. 푟 = √22 + 32 = √13 3 휃 = tan−1 ( ) = 0.983 푟푎푑푖푎푛푠 2 z = (√13 , 0.983) = √13푒푗 (0.983) Polar form exponential form or: ∠0.983 in phasor notation √13 Conjugate of a complex number: z = a + jb = r푒푗휃 푧∗ = 푎 − 푗푏 = 푟푒−j휃 Properties of the imaginary unit (푗): 2 푗2 = (√−1) = −1 , 푗3 = 푗푗2 = −푗, 푗4 = (−1)(−1) = +1 , 푒푡푐. 1 1 푗 푗 푗 Also, 푗−1 = = = = = −푗 or, 푗−1 = 푗−1(1) = 푗−1푗4 = 푗3 = −푗 푗 푗 푗 푗2 −1 Algebra of complex numbers z = a + jb z + 푧∗= (a + jb) + (a – jb) = 2a So, we may write: z + 푧∗ = 2 Re{푧} 푧푧∗ = (푎 + 푗푏) ∙ (푎 − 푗푏) = 푎2 − 푗푎푏 + 푗푎푏 − 푗2푏2 = 푎2 + 푏2 = |푧|2 = 푟2 Therefore, we may write: 푧푧∗ = |푧|2 Dividing by the conjugate: 푧 푟푒푗휃 = = 푒푗(휃−(−휃)) = 푒2푗휃 = 1∠2휃 푧∗ 푟푒−푗휃 1 −푗휃 Note that we used the fact that = 푒 푒푗휃 Matlab: Cartesian to polar conversion (built-in functions) Let 푧 = −2 + 푗 Alternative Matlab method: Mathcad: Cartesian to polar conversion: Summary of Matlab/Mathcad/TI-89 Complex number instructions: Assume z = a + jb (j is the imaginary unit i) Mathcad: (use i from the menu or define j as √−1 ) Re(z), Im(z), 푧̅, |z|, arg(z) [also: angle(a,b), atan2(a,b)] Note: Conjugate operation is obtained by holding down the Shift key and then pressing the ” key Matlab: (i is built-in) real(z), imag(z), conj(z), abs(z), angle(z), atan2(b,a), [angle, r] = cart2pol(a,b), [a, b] = pol2cart(angle, r) (angle in radians) TI-89 (syntax is similar to Matlab): real(z), imag(z), conj(z), abs(z), angle(z) (Here, the imaginary unit is i located above the “CATALOG” key) Exponential Form Matlab: Computer Example CB.1, Page 10 of Lathi’s Text. Part(a): Part(b): Reciprocal: Given (z = a + jb) 1 1 1 (푎 − 푗푏) 푎 − 푗푏 푧∗ = = = = 푧 푎 + 푗푏 (푎 + 푗푏)(푎 − 푗푏) 푎2 + 푏2 |푧|2 1 푧∗ ∴ = 푧 |푧|2 Reciprocal with the exponential representation: 1 1 1 푧 = 푟푒푗휃 → = = 푒−푗휃 푧 푟푒푗휃 푟 Division of two complex numbers: 푗휃1 푗휃2 푧1 = 푟1푒 ; 푧2 = 푟2푒 푗휃1 푧1 푟1푒 푟1 푗(휃1− 휃2) = 푗휃 = 푒 푧2 푟2푒 2 푟2 (recall, phasors: 푟1∠휃1 , 푟2∠휃2) 푟1∠휃1 푟1 = ∠(휃1 − 휃2) 푟2∠휃2 푟2 Squaring: 2 푧2 = (푟푒푗휃) = 푟2푒푗2휃 Eulers′ Formula → 푒푗휋 = cos(휋) + 푗푠푖푛(휋) = −1 + 푗0 = −1 푒푗휋 + 1 = 0 The most beautiful formula (theorem) in mathematics! In the fall 1988 issue of Mathematical Intelligencer, a scholarly journal of mathematics (published by Springer-Verlag), there was the call for a vote on the most beautiful theorem in mathematics. The readers, consisting of mostly mathematicians, voted Euler’s formula as the most beautiful. In fact, three out of the five most beautiful theorems of mathematics in that survey were contributed by Euler (they ranked first second and fifth).
Recommended publications
  • Fermat, Leibniz, Euler, and the Gang: the True History of the Concepts Of
    FERMAT, LEIBNIZ, EULER, AND THE GANG: THE TRUE HISTORY OF THE CONCEPTS OF LIMIT AND SHADOW TIZIANA BASCELLI, EMANUELE BOTTAZZI, FREDERIK HERZBERG, VLADIMIR KANOVEI, KARIN U. KATZ, MIKHAIL G. KATZ, TAHL NOWIK, DAVID SHERRY, AND STEVEN SHNIDER Abstract. Fermat, Leibniz, Euler, and Cauchy all used one or another form of approximate equality, or the idea of discarding “negligible” terms, so as to obtain a correct analytic answer. Their inferential moves find suitable proxies in the context of modern the- ories of infinitesimals, and specifically the concept of shadow. We give an application to decreasing rearrangements of real functions. Contents 1. Introduction 2 2. Methodological remarks 4 2.1. A-track and B-track 5 2.2. Formal epistemology: Easwaran on hyperreals 6 2.3. Zermelo–Fraenkel axioms and the Feferman–Levy model 8 2.4. Skolem integers and Robinson integers 9 2.5. Williamson, complexity, and other arguments 10 2.6. Infinity and infinitesimal: let both pretty severely alone 13 3. Fermat’s adequality 13 3.1. Summary of Fermat’s algorithm 14 arXiv:1407.0233v1 [math.HO] 1 Jul 2014 3.2. Tangent line and convexity of parabola 15 3.3. Fermat, Galileo, and Wallis 17 4. Leibniz’s Transcendental law of homogeneity 18 4.1. When are quantities equal? 19 4.2. Product rule 20 5. Euler’s Principle of Cancellation 20 6. What did Cauchy mean by “limit”? 22 6.1. Cauchy on Leibniz 23 6.2. Cauchy on continuity 23 7. Modern formalisations: a case study 25 8. A combinatorial approach to decreasing rearrangements 26 9.
    [Show full text]
  • Connes on the Role of Hyperreals in Mathematics
    Found Sci DOI 10.1007/s10699-012-9316-5 Tools, Objects, and Chimeras: Connes on the Role of Hyperreals in Mathematics Vladimir Kanovei · Mikhail G. Katz · Thomas Mormann © Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2012 Abstract We examine some of Connes’ criticisms of Robinson’s infinitesimals starting in 1995. Connes sought to exploit the Solovay model S as ammunition against non-standard analysis, but the model tends to boomerang, undercutting Connes’ own earlier work in func- tional analysis. Connes described the hyperreals as both a “virtual theory” and a “chimera”, yet acknowledged that his argument relies on the transfer principle. We analyze Connes’ “dart-throwing” thought experiment, but reach an opposite conclusion. In S, all definable sets of reals are Lebesgue measurable, suggesting that Connes views a theory as being “vir- tual” if it is not definable in a suitable model of ZFC. If so, Connes’ claim that a theory of the hyperreals is “virtual” is refuted by the existence of a definable model of the hyperreal field due to Kanovei and Shelah. Free ultrafilters aren’t definable, yet Connes exploited such ultrafilters both in his own earlier work on the classification of factors in the 1970s and 80s, and in Noncommutative Geometry, raising the question whether the latter may not be vulnera- ble to Connes’ criticism of virtuality. We analyze the philosophical underpinnings of Connes’ argument based on Gödel’s incompleteness theorem, and detect an apparent circularity in Connes’ logic. We document the reliance on non-constructive foundational material, and specifically on the Dixmier trace − (featured on the front cover of Connes’ magnum opus) V.
    [Show full text]
  • TME Volume 5, Numbers 2 and 3
    The Mathematics Enthusiast Volume 5 Number 2 Numbers 2 & 3 Article 27 7-2008 TME Volume 5, Numbers 2 and 3 Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umt.edu/tme Part of the Mathematics Commons Let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y Recommended Citation (2008) "TME Volume 5, Numbers 2 and 3," The Mathematics Enthusiast: Vol. 5 : No. 2 , Article 27. Available at: https://scholarworks.umt.edu/tme/vol5/iss2/27 This Full Volume is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks at University of Montana. It has been accepted for inclusion in The Mathematics Enthusiast by an authorized editor of ScholarWorks at University of Montana. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Montana Mathematics Enthusiast ISSN 1551-3440 VOL. 5, NOS.2&3, JULY 2008, pp.167-462 Editor-in-Chief Bharath Sriraman, The University of Montana Associate Editors: Lyn D. English, Queensland University of Technology, Australia Claus Michelsen, University of Southern Denmark, Denmark Brian Greer, Portland State University, USA Luis Moreno-Armella, University of Massachusetts-Dartmouth International Editorial Advisory Board Miriam Amit, Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, Israel. Ziya Argun, Gazi University, Turkey. Ahmet Arikan, Gazi University, Turkey. Astrid Beckmann, University of Education, Schwäbisch Gmünd, Germany. John Berry, University of Plymouth,UK. Morten Blomhøj, Roskilde University, Denmark. Robert Carson, Montana State University- Bozeman, USA. Mohan Chinnappan, University of Wollongong, Australia. Constantinos Christou, University of Cyprus, Cyprus. Bettina Dahl Søndergaard, University of Aarhus, Denmark. Helen Doerr, Syracuse University, USA. Ted Eisenberg, Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, Israel.
    [Show full text]
  • Math 3010 § 1. Treibergs Final Exam Name: Practice Problems March 30
    Math 3010 x 1. Final Exam Name: Practice Problems Treibergs March 30, 2018 Here are some problems soluble by methods encountered in the course. I have tried to select problems ranging over the topics we've encountered. Admittedly, they were chosen because they're fascinating to me. As such, they may have solutions that are longer than the questions you might expect on an exam. But some of them are samples of homework problems. Here are a few of my references. References. • Carl Boyer, A History of the Calculus and its Conceptual Development, Dover Publ. Inc., New York, 1959; orig. publ. The Concepts of the Calculus, A Critical and Historical Discussion of the Derivative and the Integral, Hafner Publ. Co. Inc., 1949. • Carl Boyer, A History of Mathematics, Princeton University Press, Princeton 1985 • Lucas Bunt, Phillip Jones, Jack Bedient, The Historical Roots of Elementary mathematics, Dover, Mineola 1988; orig. publ. Prentice- Hall, Englewood Cliffs 1976 • David Burton, The History of Mathmatics, An Introduction, 7th ed., McGraw Hill, New York 2011 • Ronald Calinger, Classics of Mathematics, Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs 1995; orig. publ. Moore Publ. Co. Inc., 1982 • Victor Katz, A History of Mathematics An introduction, 3rd. ed., Addison-Wesley, Boston 2009 • Morris Kline, Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times, Oxford University Press, New York 1972 • John Stillwell, Mathematics and its History, 3rd ed., Springer, New York, 2010. • Dirk Struik, A Concise History of Mathematics, Dover, New York 1967 • Harry N. Wright, First Course in Theory of Numbers, Dover, New York, 1971; orig. publ. John Wiley & Sons, Inc., New York, 1939.
    [Show full text]
  • Mathematical Conquerors, Unguru Polarity, and the Task of History
    Journal of Humanistic Mathematics Volume 10 | Issue 1 January 2020 Mathematical Conquerors, Unguru Polarity, and the Task of History Mikhail Katz Bar-Ilan University Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.claremont.edu/jhm Part of the Mathematics Commons Recommended Citation Katz, M. "Mathematical Conquerors, Unguru Polarity, and the Task of History," Journal of Humanistic Mathematics, Volume 10 Issue 1 (January 2020), pages 475-515. DOI: 10.5642/jhummath.202001.27 . Available at: https://scholarship.claremont.edu/jhm/vol10/iss1/27 ©2020 by the authors. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons License. JHM is an open access bi-annual journal sponsored by the Claremont Center for the Mathematical Sciences and published by the Claremont Colleges Library | ISSN 2159-8118 | http://scholarship.claremont.edu/jhm/ The editorial staff of JHM works hard to make sure the scholarship disseminated in JHM is accurate and upholds professional ethical guidelines. However the views and opinions expressed in each published manuscript belong exclusively to the individual contributor(s). The publisher and the editors do not endorse or accept responsibility for them. See https://scholarship.claremont.edu/jhm/policies.html for more information. Mathematical Conquerors, Unguru Polarity, and the Task of History Mikhail G. Katz Department of Mathematics, Bar Ilan University [email protected] Synopsis I compare several approaches to the history of mathematics recently proposed by Blåsjö, Fraser–Schroter, Fried, and others. I argue that tools from both mathe- matics and history are essential for a meaningful history of the discipline. In an extension of the Unguru–Weil controversy over the concept of geometric algebra, Michael Fried presents a case against both André Weil the “privileged ob- server” and Pierre de Fermat the “mathematical conqueror.” Here I analyze Fried’s version of Unguru’s alleged polarity between a historian’s and a mathematician’s history.
    [Show full text]
  • Small Oscillations of the Pendulum, Euler's Method, and Adequality
    SMALL OSCILLATIONS OF THE PENDULUM, EULER’S METHOD, AND ADEQUALITY VLADIMIR KANOVEI, KARIN U. KATZ, MIKHAIL G. KATZ, AND TAHL NOWIK Abstract. Small oscillations evolved a great deal from Klein to Robinson. We propose a concept of solution of differential equa- tion based on Euler’s method with infinitesimal mesh, with well- posedness based on a relation of adequality following Fermat and Leibniz. The result is that the period of infinitesimal oscillations is independent of their amplitude. Keywords: harmonic motion; infinitesimal; pendulum; small os- cillations Contents 1. Small oscillations of a pendulum 1 2. Vector fields, walks, and integral curves 3 3. Adequality 4 4. Infinitesimal oscillations 5 5. Adjusting linear prevector field 6 6. Conclusion 7 Acknowledgments 7 References 7 arXiv:1604.06663v1 [math.HO] 13 Apr 2016 1. Small oscillations of a pendulum The breakdown of infinite divisibility at quantum scales makes irrel- evant the mathematical definitions of derivatives and integrals in terms ∆y of limits as x tends to zero. Rather, quotients like ∆x need to be taken in a certain range, or level. The work [Nowik & Katz 2015] developed a general framework for differential geometry at level λ, where λ is an infinitesimal but the formalism is a better match for a situation where infinite divisibility fails and a scale for calculations needs to be fixed ac- cordingly. In this paper we implement such an approach to give a first rigorous account “at level λ” for small oscillations of the pendulum. 1 2 VLADIMIR KANOVEI, K. KATZ, MIKHAIL KATZ, AND TAHL NOWIK In his 1908 book Elementary Mathematics from an Advanced Stand- point, Felix Klein advocated the introduction of calculus into the high- school curriculum.
    [Show full text]
  • Fermat's Dilemma: Why Did He Keep Mum on Infinitesimals? and The
    FERMAT’S DILEMMA: WHY DID HE KEEP MUM ON INFINITESIMALS? AND THE EUROPEAN THEOLOGICAL CONTEXT JACQUES BAIR, MIKHAIL G. KATZ, AND DAVID SHERRY Abstract. The first half of the 17th century was a time of in- tellectual ferment when wars of natural philosophy were echoes of religious wars, as we illustrate by a case study of an apparently innocuous mathematical technique called adequality pioneered by the honorable judge Pierre de Fermat, its relation to indivisibles, as well as to other hocus-pocus. Andr´eWeil noted that simple appli- cations of adequality involving polynomials can be treated purely algebraically but more general problems like the cycloid curve can- not be so treated and involve additional tools–leading the mathe- matician Fermat potentially into troubled waters. Breger attacks Tannery for tampering with Fermat’s manuscript but it is Breger who tampers with Fermat’s procedure by moving all terms to the left-hand side so as to accord better with Breger’s own interpreta- tion emphasizing the double root idea. We provide modern proxies for Fermat’s procedures in terms of relations of infinite proximity as well as the standard part function. Keywords: adequality; atomism; cycloid; hylomorphism; indi- visibles; infinitesimal; jesuat; jesuit; Edict of Nantes; Council of Trent 13.2 Contents arXiv:1801.00427v1 [math.HO] 1 Jan 2018 1. Introduction 3 1.1. A re-evaluation 4 1.2. Procedures versus ontology 5 1.3. Adequality and the cycloid curve 5 1.4. Weil’s thesis 6 1.5. Reception by Huygens 8 1.6. Our thesis 9 1.7. Modern proxies 10 1.8.
    [Show full text]
  • A BRIEF TOUR of FERMAT's CALCULUS 1. Introduction If Isaac
    A BRIEF TOUR OF FERMAT'S CALCULUS JOHN D. LORCH Abstract. We examine some of the beautiful and surprisingly substantial contributions which Pierre de Fermat made to the development of calculus. In the process, we emphasize the importance of the limit concept and we introduce alternative viewpoints of both di®erentiation and integration. 1. Introduction If Isaac Newton \stood on the shoulders of giants" then, when it came to the development of calculus, he certainly stood on the shoulders of French mathemati- cian Pierre de Fermat (1601-1665). Fermat, a key ¯gure in an era of unprecedented mathematical development, is popularly known for his contributions to number the- ory and probability. However, he also made beautiful and substantial contributions to the beginnings of calculus. Our purpose is to present some of Fermat's work in calculus (cloaked in modern terms) featuring his method of adequality. Fermat's viewpoint is rich in important ideas, including: ² An alternate approach to di®erentiation and integration which is both clever and beautiful. ² The importance of a formal limit concept and the Fundamental Theorem of Calculus. ² Yet another illustration of the power of geometric series. ² A foray into the history of mathematics, featuring one of the greatest math- ematicians of all time. 2. Ad-equality and Fermat's tangent line problem Fermat's work on the tangent line problem likely began sometime in the 1620's as an extension of Viete's work on the theory of equations. Responding to inquiries, in 1636 he prepared a short document outlining his method (see [1]). In the document he describes the following situation: Consider a parabola with corresponding axis of symmetry (see Figure 1).
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1210.7750V1 [Math.HO] 29 Oct 2012 Tsml Ehdo Aiaadmnm;Rfato;Selslaw
    ALMOST EQUAL: THE METHOD OF ADEQUALITY FROM DIOPHANTUS TO FERMAT AND BEYOND MIKHAIL G. KATZ, DAVID M. SCHAPS, AND STEVEN SHNIDER Abstract. We analyze some of the main approaches in the liter- ature to the method of ‘adequality’ with which Fermat approached the problems of the calculus, as well as its source in the παρισoτης´ of Diophantus, and propose a novel reading thereof. Adequality is a crucial step in Fermat’s method of finding max- ima, minima, tangents, and solving other problems that a mod- ern mathematician would solve using infinitesimal calculus. The method is presented in a series of short articles in Fermat’s col- lected works [66, p. 133-172]. We show that at least some of the manifestations of adequality amount to variational techniques ex- ploiting a small, or infinitesimal, variation e. Fermat’s treatment of geometric and physical applications sug- gests that an aspect of approximation is inherent in adequality, as well as an aspect of smallness on the part of e. We question the rel- evance to understanding Fermat of 19th century dictionary defini- tions of παρισoτης´ and adaequare, cited by Breger, and take issue with his interpretation of adequality, including his novel reading of Diophantus, and his hypothesis concerning alleged tampering with Fermat’s texts by Carcavy. We argue that Fermat relied on Bachet’s reading of Diophantus. Diophantus coined the term παρισoτης´ for mathematical pur- poses and used it to refer to the way in which 1321/711 is ap- proximately equal to 11/6. Bachet performed a semantic calque in passing from pariso¯o to adaequo.
    [Show full text]
  • Who Gave You the Cauchy-Weierstrass Tale? The
    WHO GAVE YOU THE CAUCHY–WEIERSTRASS TALE? THE DUAL HISTORY OF RIGOROUS CALCULUS ALEXANDRE BOROVIK AND MIKHAIL G. KATZ0 Abstract. Cauchy’s contribution to the foundations of analysis is often viewed through the lens of developments that occurred some decades later, namely the formalisation of analysis on the basis of the epsilon-delta doctrine in the context of an Archimedean con- tinuum. What does one see if one refrains from viewing Cauchy as if he had read Weierstrass already? One sees, with Felix Klein, a parallel thread for the development of analysis, in the context of an infinitesimal-enriched continuum. One sees, with Emile Borel, the seeds of the theory of rates of growth of functions as devel- oped by Paul du Bois-Reymond. One sees, with E. G. Bj¨orling, an infinitesimal definition of the criterion of uniform convergence. Cauchy’s foundational stance is hereby reconsidered. Contents 1. Introduction 2 2. A reappraisal of Cauchy’s foundational stance 4 2.1. Cauchy’s theory of orders of infinitesimals 4 2.2. How does a null sequence become a Cauchy infinitesimal? 8 2.3. An analysis of Cours d’Analyse and its infinitesimals 11 2.4. Microcontinuity and Cauchy’s sum theorem 14 2.5. Five common misconceptions in the Cauchy literature 16 arXiv:1108.2885v3 [math.HO] 16 Oct 2012 3. Comments by modern authors 18 3.1. Gilain’s limit 18 3.2. Felscher’s Bestiarium infinitesimale 19 3.3. D’Alembert or de La Chapelle? 24 3.4. Brillou¨et-Belluot: epsilon-delta, period 25 3.5.
    [Show full text]
  • The Method of Adequality from Diophantus to Fermat and Beyond
    Almost Equal: the Method of Adequality from Diophantus to Fermat and Beyond Mikhail G. Katz, David M. Schaps, and Steven Shnider Bar Ilan University We analyze some of the main approaches in the literature to the method of ‘adequality’ with which Fermat approached the problems of the calculus, as well as its source in the parisâth§ of Diophantus, and propose a novel read- ing thereof. Adequality is a crucial step in Fermat’s method of ªnding max- ima, minima, tangents, and solving other problems that a modern mathema- tician would solve using inªnitesimal calculus. The method is presented in a series of short articles in Fermat’s collected works (Tannery and Henry 1981, pp. 133–172). We show that at least some of the manifestations of adequality amount to variational techniques exploiting a small, or inªn- itesimal, variation e. Fermat’s treatment of geometric and physical applica- tions suggests that an aspect of approximation is inherent in adequality, as well as an aspect of smallness on the part of e. We question the relevance to understanding Fermat of 19th century dictionary deªnitions of parisâth§ and adaequare, cited by Breger, and take issue with his interpretation of adequality, including his novel reading of Diophantus, and his hypothesis concerning alleged tampering with Fermat’s texts by Carcavy. We argue that Fermat relied on Bachet’s reading of Diophantus. Diophantus coined the term parisâth§ for mathematical purposes and used it to refer to the way in which 1321/711 is approximately equal to 11/6. Bachet performed a se- mantic calque in passing from parisoo to adaequo.
    [Show full text]
  • Topics in Programming Languages, a Philosophical Analysis Through the Case of Prolog
    i Topics in Programming Languages, a Philosophical Analysis through the case of Prolog Luís Homem Universidad de Salamanca Facultad de Filosofia A thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor en Lógica y Filosofía de la Ciencia Salamanca 2018 ii This thesis is dedicated to family and friends iii Acknowledgements I am very grateful for having had the opportunity to attend classes with all the Epimenides Program Professors: Dr.o Alejandro Sobrino, Dr.o Alfredo Burrieza, Dr.o Ángel Nepomuceno, Dr.a Concepción Martínez, Dr.o Enrique Alonso, Dr.o Huberto Marraud, Dr.a María Manzano, Dr.o José Miguel Sagüillo, and Dr.o Juan Luis Barba. I would like to extend my sincere thanks and congratulations to the Academic Com- mission of the Program. A very special gratitude goes to Dr.a María Manzano-Arjona for her patience with the troubles of a candidate with- out a scholarship, or any funding for the work, and also to Dr.o Fer- nando Soler-Toscano, for his quick and sharp amendments, corrections and suggestions. Lastly, I cannot but offer my heartfelt thanks to all the members and collaborators of the Center for Philosophy of Sciences of the University of Lisbon (CFCUL), specially Dr.a Olga Pombo, who invited me to be an integrated member in 2011. iv Abstract Programming Languages seldom find proper anchorage in philosophy of logic, language and science. What is more, philosophy of language seems to be restricted to natural languages and linguistics, and even philosophy of logic is rarely framed into programming language topics. Natural languages history is intrinsically acoustics-to-visual, phonetics- to-writing, whereas computing programming languages, under man– machine interaction, aspire to visual-to-acoustics, writing-to-phonetics instead, namely through natural language processing.
    [Show full text]