Absolute Generality Towards a Modal Approach

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Absolute Generality Towards a Modal Approach Corso di Dottorato di ricerca in Filosofia e Scienze della Formazione ciclo XXX° Tesi di Ricerca Absolute Generality Towards a Modal Approach SSD: M-FIL 02; M-FIL 05 Coordinatore del Dottorato ch. prof.ssa Emanuela Scribano Supervisore ch. prof. Paolo Pagani Dottorando Filippo Costantini Matricola 820866 2 Summary Introduction p. 4 Chapter 1: Basic Law V and the Origin of Paradox p. 12 Chapter 2: Introduction to Indefinite Extensibility p. 24 Chapter 3: The Inexpressibility Objection p. 48 Chapter 4: Against Schematism p. 65 Chapter 5: From First-order to Higher-order Logic p. 81 Chapter 6: The Domain Principle and Indefinite Extensibility p. 139 Chapter 7: A theory of Concepts p. 153 Appendix: Indefinite Extensibility without Intuitionism p. 194 Conclusion p. 209 References p. 214 3 INTRODUCTION This dissertation defends the idea that absolute general discourses are possible, i.e. sometimes the quantifiers in our sentences range over absolutely everything. However, it also defends the idea that there are indefinitely extensible concepts, i.e. concepts associated with an indefinitely extensible sequence of objects falling under them. Prima facie, the two ideas seem incompatible and, as a matter of fact, indefinite extensibility has been used to challenge absolute generality1. The reason of this apparent incompatibility is that the standard theory of quantification requires a domain for the quantifiers to range over: if the quantifier is absolutely general, then its domain2 of quantification must contain absolutely everything. But if concepts as those of set, ordinal, cardinal etc. are indefinitely extensible, then also the concept of object (or the concept of ‘being self-identical’) is indefinitely extensible, since sets, ordinals and cardinals are objects. But this implies that no all-inclusive domain exists: given a domain, it is possible to find new objects not present in it. My strategy to argue for absolute generality and indefinite extensibility consists in arguing that standard quantification is not the only form of generality. One of the main thesis of the whole work is the claim that there exists a form of generality which behaves differently from standard quantification. This generality, which is formally captured by means of a modal approach to quantification, is firstly introduced in chapter 2, and then developed in chapters 6 and 7. The general context in which this work has been developed is the debate on absolute generality. This is a highly interesting debate on quantifiers: is it possible to quantify over everything? Is there a totally unrestricted quantification over an all-inclusive domain? In the contemporary discussion, one of the first scholar to raise doubts about the possibility of meaningful sentences about everything was Russell. Speaking about the paradoxes (both set-theoretic and semantics) Russell writes: Thus it is necessary […] to construct our logic without mentioning3 such things as “all propositions” or “all properties”, and without even having to say that we are excluding such things. The exclusion must result naturally and inevitably from our positive doctrines, which must make it plain that “all propositions” and “all properties” are meaningless phrases. (Russell [1908], p. 226). 1 For instance, Glanzberg [2004], Hellman [2006] and Button [2011] uses ideas connected to indefinite extensibility to challenge the possibility of absolute generality. 2 As I shall make clear in the following chapters (especially chapter 6), when I say that no all-inclusive domain exists, the word ‘domain’ denotes either a set or a plurality (in the sense of plural logic). 3 It is well-known that Russell was very sloppy with the use-mention distinction. Here he says that we should not mention things as “all propositions”, but by saying “all propositions” he is just mentioning it! What he should have said is that, although we cannot use such expressions, we can certainly mention it. 4 If we cannot speak of all propositions or all properties, a fortiori, we cannot meaningfully speak of everything. Russell’s doubts did not meet many supporters. The standard view during the twentieth century was to regard standard first-order unrestricted quantification as unproblematic. Quine’s essay On what there is is a case in point: to the question “what is there?” Quine answered ‘Everything’, where “Everything” is an unrestricted first-order quantifier. At a naïve sight, it seems weird to question the possibility of absolute general discourses. How is it possible to fail to refer to everything, if I intend to refer to everything? Of course, everybody acknowledges that many occurrences of ‘everything’ in our sentences are restricted to some particular domain. If I say, “all bottles of beers are empty”, it is unlikely that ‘all bottles’ refers to absolutely all bottles on this earth; rather it is likely it refers to some restricted domain of bottles, i.e. the bottle in my house4. But certainly, we can speak of everything, if we intend to. Or at least this seems to be the case. Williamson [2003] fully articulates what he dubs as naïve absolutism, i.e. the intuitive view according to which there are no problem in quantifying over everything. Naïve absolutism is supported by a number of different examples where it seems clear that we manage to achieve absolute generality. For instance, ontological and metaphysical discourses seem to presuppose absolute general claims5. Quine’s answer above presupposes that ‘everything’ is to be taken as totally unrestricted. But also, logic requires unrestricted quantification. The laws of logic are valid not just in some restricted domain, but in all domains. Therefore, it seems that we need absolute generality to state them. In any case, there are also examples from ordinary talk. If you deny that there exists something, let’s say Pegasus, then you are committed to the sentence ‘Everything is such that it is not Pegasus’. Here the quantifier must be taken as absolutely unrestricted, if that sentence has its intended meaning; otherwise, if the quantifier has only a restricted domain, then the truth of that sentence is compatible with the existence of (an object equal to) Pegasus in a broader domain6. In addition, standard logic seems to suggest the possibility that unrestricted quantification is present also when the quantifiers are restricted. Suppose you say that ‘all dogs bark’ or that ‘there exist a black swan’. These are examples of restricted quantification: the first quantifier is restricted to the domain of dogs, while the second one is restricted to the domain of swans. These sentences are usually formalized as follows: ∀�(�� → ��) and ∃�(�� ∧ ���), where � =being a dog; � =barking; � =being a swan; �� =being black. In both cases, the quantifier lies outside the parenthesis, and binds the whole formula inside the parenthesis (it binds, respectively, the formulas �� → �� and �� ∧ ���), not only the formulas that respectively say that we are speaking 4 Stanley and Szabo [2000] provides an insightful analysis of how quantifier domain restriction works in natural language. I shall not bother with this topic in the present work. 5 For a different opinion, see Glanzberg [2004]. 6 This is a form of the inexpressibility objection, which we have deeply analyzed in chapter 3. More reasons to support the plausibility of unrestricted quantification can be found in Williamson [2003]. 5 of dogs (��) and swans (��). This standard way of formalization leads quite naturally to think that the range of the quantifier is always everything, and the predicate � and � select a sub-domain of everything. If this is the case, then every restricted quantification should be analyzed as composed by an unrestricted quantifier, and a predicate that restricts its domain7. What we have just seen suggests that naïve absolutism enjoys prima facie plausibility. However, it has been challenged in many ways. In the literature, there are four big objections that have been raised. They are the objection from paradox, the objection from the indeterminacy of reference, the objection from ontological relativity and the objection from sortal restriction. We shall now briefly explain what these objections amount to. The objection from paradox. This is the most important objection, and the one more discussed in this dissertation. So, we just outline here his general aspect. The set theoretic paradoxes show that no universal set exists. Because, if it existed, then we could consider the set R of all non-self-membered sets. But if R belongs to itself, it does not belong to itself; if it does not belong to itself, it belongs to itself. We thus have a contradiction. The universal set thus cannot exist. But since standard model theoretic semantics is based on set theory, unrestricted quantification over everything needs the universal set as its own domain of quantification. The non-existence of this set implies that no unrestricted quantification is possible. A slightly different version of the argument exploits the paradoxes to show that any domain can be expanded. Suppose you consider a domain D, which purports to be the domain of everything (the universal set). Then you can derive Russell’s paradox. But at this point you can exploit the paradox to argue that the set R is not one of the objects included in D. Therefore, you can expand D by adding R to it. In this way, you find a more comprehensive domain �v = � ∪ �. But D was arbitrary. Any domain that presents itself as the all-inclusive domain can be expanded. This is the argument at the root of indefinite extensibility. More on this in chapters 1 and 2. The objection from indeterminacy of reference. This objection is based on the Löwenheim-Skolem theorem for first-order logic. Since the theorem claims that a first- order theory with an infinite model has models of any other infinite cardinality, and in particular it has a countable model, the objection claims that if we have a first-order theory whose quantifiers are supposed to be absolutely unrestricted, then it is undetermined if they range over everything or over a countable subset of everything.
Recommended publications
  • Redalyc.Sets and Pluralities
    Red de Revistas Científicas de América Latina, el Caribe, España y Portugal Sistema de Información Científica Gustavo Fernández Díez Sets and Pluralities Revista Colombiana de Filosofía de la Ciencia, vol. IX, núm. 19, 2009, pp. 5-22, Universidad El Bosque Colombia Available in: http://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=41418349001 Revista Colombiana de Filosofía de la Ciencia, ISSN (Printed Version): 0124-4620 [email protected] Universidad El Bosque Colombia How to cite Complete issue More information about this article Journal's homepage www.redalyc.org Non-Profit Academic Project, developed under the Open Acces Initiative Sets and Pluralities1 Gustavo Fernández Díez2 Resumen En este artículo estudio el trasfondo filosófico del sistema de lógica conocido como “lógica plural”, o “lógica de cuantificadores plurales”, de aparición relativamente reciente (y en alza notable en los últimos años). En particular, comparo la noción de “conjunto” emanada de la teoría axiomática de conjuntos, con la noción de “plura- lidad” que se encuentra detrás de este nuevo sistema. Mi conclusión es que los dos son completamente diferentes en su alcance y sus límites, y que la diferencia proviene de las diferentes motivaciones que han dado lugar a cada uno. Mientras que la teoría de conjuntos es una teoría genuinamente matemática, que tiene el interés matemático como ingrediente principal, la lógica plural ha aparecido como respuesta a considera- ciones lingüísticas, relacionadas con la estructura lógica de los enunciados plurales del inglés y el resto de los lenguajes naturales. Palabras clave: conjunto, teoría de conjuntos, pluralidad, cuantificación plural, lógica plural. Abstract In this paper I study the philosophical background of the relatively recent (and in the last few years increasingly flourishing) system of logic called “plural logic”, or “logic of plural quantifiers”.
    [Show full text]
  • Collapse, Plurals and Sets 421
    doi: 10.5007/1808-1711.2014v18n3p419 COLLAPSE,PLURALS AND SETS EDUARDO ALEJANDRO BARRIO Abstract. This paper raises the question under what circumstances a plurality forms a set. My main point is that not always all things form sets. A provocative way of presenting my position is that, as a result of my approach, there are more pluralities than sets. Another way of presenting the same thesis claims that there are ways of talking about objects that do not always collapse into sets. My argument is related to expressive powers of formal languages. Assuming classical logic, I show that if all plurality form a set and the quantifiers are absolutely general, then one gets a trivial theory. So, by reductio, one has to abandon one of the premiss. Then, I argue against the collapse of the pluralities into sets. What I am advocating is that the thesis of collapse limits important applications of the plural logic in model theory, when it is assumed that the quantifiers are absolutely general. Keywords: Pluralities; absolute generality; sets; hierarchies. We often say that some things form a set. For instance, every house in Beacon Hill may form a set. Also, all antimatter particles in the universe, all even numbers, all odd numbers, and in general all natural numbers do so. Naturally, following this line of thought, one might think that the plurality of all things constitutes a set. And al- though natural language allows us, by means of its plural constructions, to talk about objects without grouping them in one entity, there are also nominalization devices to turn constructions involving high order expressive resources into others that only make use of first order ones.
    [Show full text]
  • Plurals and Mereology
    Journal of Philosophical Logic (2021) 50:415–445 https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-020-09570-9 Plurals and Mereology Salvatore Florio1 · David Nicolas2 Received: 2 August 2019 / Accepted: 5 August 2020 / Published online: 26 October 2020 © The Author(s) 2020 Abstract In linguistics, the dominant approach to the semantics of plurals appeals to mere- ology. However, this approach has received strong criticisms from philosophical logicians who subscribe to an alternative framework based on plural logic. In the first part of the article, we offer a precise characterization of the mereological approach and the semantic background in which the debate can be meaningfully reconstructed. In the second part, we deal with the criticisms and assess their logical, linguistic, and philosophical significance. We identify four main objections and show how each can be addressed. Finally, we compare the strengths and shortcomings of the mereologi- cal approach and plural logic. Our conclusion is that the former remains a viable and well-motivated framework for the analysis of plurals. Keywords Mass nouns · Mereology · Model theory · Natural language semantics · Ontological commitment · Plural logic · Plurals · Russell’s paradox · Truth theory 1 Introduction A prominent tradition in linguistic semantics analyzes plurals by appealing to mere- ology (e.g. Link [40, 41], Landman [32, 34], Gillon [20], Moltmann [50], Krifka [30], Bale and Barner [2], Chierchia [12], Sutton and Filip [76], and Champollion [9]).1 1The historical roots of this tradition include Leonard and Goodman [38], Goodman and Quine [22], Massey [46], and Sharvy [74]. Salvatore Florio [email protected] David Nicolas [email protected] 1 Department of Philosophy, University of Birmingham, Birmingham, United Kingdom 2 Institut Jean Nicod, Departement´ d’etudes´ cognitives, ENS, EHESS, CNRS, PSL University, Paris, France 416 S.
    [Show full text]
  • Beyond Plurals
    Beyond Plurals Agust´ınRayo philosophy.ucsd.edu/arayo July 10, 2008 I have two main objectives. The first is to get a better understanding of what is at issue between friends and foes of higher-order quantification, and of what it would mean to extend a Boolos-style treatment of second-order quantification to third- and higher- order quantification. The second objective is to argue that in the presence of absolutely general quantification, proper semantic theorizing is essentially unstable: it is impossible to provide a suitably general semantics for a given language in a language of the same logical type. I claim that this leads to a trilemma: one must choose between giving up absolutely general quantification, settling for the view that adequate semantic theorizing about certain languages is essentially beyond our reach, and countenancing an open-ended hierarchy of languages of ever ascending logical type. I conclude by suggesting that the hierarchy may be the least unattractive of the options on the table. 1 Preliminaries 1.1 Categorial Semantics Throughout this paper I shall assume the following: Categorial Semantics Every meaningful sentence has a semantic structure,1 which may be represented 1 as a certain kind of tree.2 Each node in the tree falls under a particular se- mantic category (e.g. `sentence', `quantifier’, `sentential connective'), and has an intension that is appropriate for that category. The semantic category and intension of each non-terminal node in the tree is determined by the semantic categories and intensions of nodes below it. Although I won't attempt to defend Categorial Semantics here,3 two points are worth emphasizing.
    [Show full text]
  • Plural Reference.Pdf
    OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST PROOF, 11/12/2015, SPi Plurality and Unity Dictionary: NOSD 0002624321.INDD 1 11/12/2015 3:07:20 PM OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST PROOF, 11/12/2015, SPi Dictionary: NOSD 0002624321.INDD 2 11/12/2015 3:07:20 PM OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST PROOF, 11/12/2015, SPi Plurality and Unity Logic, Philosophy, and Linguistics !"#$!" %& Massimiliano Carrara, Alexandra Arapinis, and Friederike Moltmann Dictionary: NOSD 0002624321.INDD 3 11/12/2015 3:07:20 PM OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST PROOF, 11/12/2015, SPi Great Clarendon Street, Oxford, OX' (DP, United Kingdom Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries © the several contributors ')*( +e moral rights of the authors have been asserted First Edition published in ')*( Impression: * All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, by licence or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this work in any other form and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press *,- Madison Avenue, New York, NY *))*(, United States of America British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Control Number: ')*.,//0/.
    [Show full text]
  • Semantics and the Plural Conception of Reality
    Philosophers’ volume 14, no. 22 ccording to a traditional view, reality is singular. Socrates and Imprint july 2014 A Plato are philosophers; each of them has the property of being a philosopher.1 Being a philosopher is a singular property in that it is instantiated separately by Socrates and by Plato. The property of being a philosopher, like the property of being human, has the higher-order property of being instantiated. The property of being instantiated is singular too. It is instantiated separately by the property of being a SEMANTICS AND philosopher and by the property of being human. If we generalize these ideas, we obtain what may be called the singular conception of reality. This is the view that reality encompasses entities belonging to THE PLURAL two main categories: objects and singular properties of various orders.2 The singular conception of reality offers a simple picture of what there is, and it offers a simple picture of the semantics of singular pred- ication. A basic predication of the form S(t), composed of a singular CONCEPTION OF term t and a singular predicate S, is true in a given interpretation of the language if and only if, relative to that interpretation, the object denoted by t instantiates the property denoted by S. REALITY A broader conception of reality, however, has been advocated. The Romans conquered Gaul. This is not something that any Roman did separately. They conquered Gaul jointly. According to advocates of the broader conception of reality, conquering Gaul is a plural property, one that is instantiated jointly by the Romans.
    [Show full text]
  • Early Russell on Types and Plurals of Analytical Philosophy Kevin C
    Journal FOR THE History Early Russell ON TYPES AND PlurALS OF Analytical Philosophy KeVIN C. Klement VOLUME 2, Number 6 In 1903, in The Principles of Mathematics (PoM), Russell endorsed an account of classes whereupon a class fundamentally is to be Editor IN Chief considered many things, and not one, and used this thesis to SandrA Lapointe, McMaster University explicate his first version of a theory of types, adding that it formed the logical justification for the grammatical distinction Editorial BoarD between singular and plural. The view, however, was short- Juliet Floyd, Boston University lived—rejected before PoM even appeared in print. However, GrEG Frost-Arnold, Hobart AND William Smith Colleges aside from mentions of a few misgivings, there is little evidence Henry Jackman, YORK University about why he abandoned this view. In this paper, I attempt to Chris Pincock, Ohio State University clarify Russell’s early views about plurality, arguing that they Mark TExtor, King’S College London did not involve countenancing special kinds of plural things RicharD Zach, University OF Calgary distinct from individuals. I also clarify what his misgivings about these views were, making it clear that while the plural understanding of classes helped solve certain forms of Russell’s PrODUCTION Editor paradox, certain other Cantorian paradoxes remained. Finally, Ryan Hickerson, University OF WESTERN OrEGON I aim to show that Russell’s abandonment of something like plural logic is understandable given his own conception of Editorial Assistant logic and philosophical aims when compared to the views and Daniel Harris, CUNY GrADUATE Center approaches taken by contemporary advocates of plural logic.
    [Show full text]
  • Nominalism in the Philosophy of Mathematics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy) 9/16/13 2:21 PM
    Nominalism in the Philosophy of Mathematics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy) 9/16/13 2:21 PM Open access to the SEP is made possible by a world-wide funding initiative. Please Read How You Can Help Keep the Encyclopedia Free Nominalism in the Philosophy of Mathematics First published Mon Sep 16, 2013 Nominalism about mathematics (or mathematical nominalism) is the view according to which either mathematical objects, relations, and structures do not exist at all, or they do not exist as abstract objects (they are neither located in space-time nor do they have causal powers). In the latter case, some suitable concrete replacement for mathematical objects is provided. Broadly speaking, there are two forms of mathematical nominalism: those views that require the reformulation of mathematical (or scientific) theories in order to avoid the commitment to mathematical objects (e.g., Field 1980; Hellman 1989), and those views that do not reformulate mathematical or scientific theories and offer instead an account of how no commitment to mathematical objects is involved when these theories are used (e.g., Azzouni 2004). Both forms of nominalism are examined, and they are assessed in light of how they address five central problems in the philosophy of mathematics (namely, problems dealing with the epistemology, the ontology, and the application of mathematics as well as the use of a uniform semantics and the proviso that mathematical and scientific theories be taken literally). 1. Two views about mathematics: nominalism and platonism 2. Five Problems 2.1 The epistemological problem of mathematics 2.2 The problem of the application of mathematics 2.3 The problem of uniform semantics 2.4 The problem of taking mathematical discourse literally 2.5 The ontological problem 3.
    [Show full text]
  • Much Ado About the Many 47
    PRINCIPIA 25(1): 45–58 (2021) doi: 10.5007/1808-1711.2021.e70853 Published by NEL — Epistemology and Logic Research Group, Federal University of Santa Catarina (UFSC), Brazil. MUCH ADO ABOUT THE MANY JONATHAN MAI Goethe University, Frankfurt, GERMANY [email protected] Abstract. English distinguishes between singular quantifiers like ‘a donkey’ and plural quan- tifiers like ‘some donkeys’. Pluralists hold that plural quantifiers range in an unusual,irre- ducibly plural way over common objects, namely individuals from first-order domains and not over set-like objects. The favoured framework of pluralism is plural first-order logic, PFO, an interpreted first-order language that is capable of expressing plural quantification. Plural- ists argue for their position by claiming that the standard formal theory based on PFO is both ontologically neutral and really logic. These properties are supposed to yield many important applications concerning second-order logic and set theory that alternative theories suppos- edly cannot deliver. I will show that there are serious reasons for rejecting at least the claim of ontological innocence. Doubt about innocence arises on account of the fact that, when prop- erly spelled out, the PFO-semantics for plural quantifiers is committed to set-like objects. The correctness of my worries presupposes the principle that for every plurality there is a coextensive set. Pluralists might reply that this principle leads straight to paradox. However, as I will argue, the true culprit of the paradox is the assumption that every definite condition determines a plurality. The course of the discussion will proceed in three steps: First I outline the debate between singularists and pluralists, then I define the syntax and semantics of PFO and finally I present my argument for the claim that PFO’s semantics is committed to set-like objects.
    [Show full text]
  • The Mereological Foundation of Megethology
    The Mereological foundation of Megethology Massimiliano Carrara, Enrico Martino FISPPA Department, University of Padua (Italy) April 24, 2015 Abstract In Mathematics is megethology (Lewis, 1993) David K. Lewis pro- poses a structuralist reconstruction of classical set theory based on mereology. In order to formulate suitable hypotheses about the size of the universe of individuals without the help of set-theoretical notions, he uses the device of Boolos' plural quantification for treating second order logic without commitment to set-theoretical entities. In this paper we show how, assuming the existence of a pairing function on atoms, as the unique assumption non expressed in a mere- ological language, a mereological foundation of set theory is achievable within first order logic. Furthermore, we show how a mereological cod- ification of ordered pairs is achievable with a very restricted use of the notion of plurality without plural quantification. 1 1 Introduction David Lewis (Lewis, 1993) proposes a reconstruction of classical set theory grounded on mereology and plural quantification (see also (Lewis, 1991)).1 Mereology is the theory of parthood relation. One of its first formaliza- tions is Leonard and Goodman Calculus of individuals ((Leonard & Good- man, 1940), 33-40).2 Plural quantification is a reinterpretation of second order monadic logic, proposed by Boolos in (Boolos, 1984), (Boolos, 1985).3 In Boolos' perspective second order monadic logic is ontologically innocent: contrary to the most accredited view, it doesn't entail any commitment to classes or to properties but only to individuals, as first order logic does. Acccording to Boolos, second order quantification differs from first order quantification only in that it refers to individuals plurally, while the latter refers to individuals singularly.
    [Show full text]
  • The Many and the One: a Philosophical Study of Plural Logic
    OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 12/6/2021, SPi The Many and the One OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 12/6/2021, SPi OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 12/6/2021, SPi The Many and the One A Philosophical Study of Plural Logic SALVATORE FLORIO AND ØYSTEIN LINNEBO 1 OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 12/6/2021, SPi 3 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford, OX2 6DP, United Kingdom Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries © Salvatore Florio and Øystein Linnebo 2021 The moral rights of the authors have been asserted First Edition published in 2021 Impression: 1 Some rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, for commercial purposes, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, by licence or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. This is an open access publication, available online and distributed under the terms ofa Creative Commons Attribution – Non Commercial – No Derivatives 4.0 International licence (CC BY-NC-ND 4.0), a copy of which is available at http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of this licence should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press 198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016, United States of America British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Control Number: 2020951752 ISBN 978–0–19–879152–2 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780198791522.001.0001 Printed and bound by CPI Group (UK) Ltd, Croydon, CR0 4YY Links to third party websites are provided by Oxford in good faith and for information only.
    [Show full text]
  • Plurals and Mereology Salvatore Florio, David Nicolas
    Plurals and Mereology Salvatore Florio, David Nicolas To cite this version: Salvatore Florio, David Nicolas. Plurals and Mereology. Journal of Philosophical Logic, Springer Verlag, 2021, 50 (3), pp.415-445. 10.1007/s10992-020-09570-9. ijn_02978254v2 HAL Id: ijn_02978254 https://jeannicod.ccsd.cnrs.fr/ijn_02978254v2 Submitted on 20 May 2021 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Distributed under a Creative Commons Attribution| 4.0 International License Journal of Philosophical Logic (2021) 50:415–445 https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-020-09570-9 Plurals and Mereology Salvatore Florio1 · David Nicolas2 Received: 2 August 2019 / Accepted: 5 August 2020 / Published online: 26 October 2020 © The Author(s) 2020 Abstract In linguistics, the dominant approach to the semantics of plurals appeals to mere- ology. However, this approach has received strong criticisms from philosophical logicians who subscribe to an alternative framework based on plural logic. In the first part of the article, we offer a precise characterization of the mereological approach and the semantic background in which the debate can be meaningfully reconstructed. In the second part, we deal with the criticisms and assess their logical, linguistic, and philosophical significance.
    [Show full text]