Einselection Without Pointer States

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Einselection Without Pointer States Einselection without pointer states Einselection without pointer states - Decoherence under weak interaction Christian Gogolin Universit¨atW¨urzburg 2009-12-16 C. Gogolin j Universit¨atW¨urzburg j 2009-12-16 1 / 26 Einselection without pointer states j Introduction New foundation for Statistical Mechanics X Thermodynamics X Statistical Mechanics Second Law ergodicity equal a priory probabilities Classical Mechanics [2, 3] C. Gogolin j Universit¨atW¨urzburg j 2009-12-16 2 / 26 Einselection without pointer states j Introduction New foundation for Statistical Mechanics X Thermodynamics X Statistical Mechanics Second Law ergodicity ? equal a priory probabilities Classical Mechanics ? [2, 3] C. Gogolin j Universit¨atW¨urzburg j 2009-12-16 2 / 26 Einselection without pointer states j Introduction New foundation for Statistical Mechanics X Thermodynamics X Statistical Mechanics [2, 3] C. Gogolin j Universit¨atW¨urzburg j 2009-12-16 2 / 26 Einselection without pointer states j Introduction New foundation for Statistical Mechanics X Thermodynamics X Statistical Mechanics * Quantum Mechanics X [2, 3] C. Gogolin j Universit¨atW¨urzburg j 2009-12-16 2 / 26 quantum mechanical orbitals discrete energy levels coherent superpositions hopping Einselection without pointer states j Introduction Why do electrons hop between energy eigenstates? C. Gogolin j Universit¨atW¨urzburg j 2009-12-16 3 / 26 discrete energy levels hopping Einselection without pointer states j Introduction Why do electrons hop between energy eigenstates? quantum mechanical orbitals coherent superpositions C. Gogolin j Universit¨atW¨urzburg j 2009-12-16 3 / 26 Einselection without pointer states j Introduction Why do electrons hop between energy eigenstates? quantum mechanical orbitals discrete energy levels coherent superpositions hopping C. Gogolin j Universit¨atW¨urzburg j 2009-12-16 3 / 26 Einselection without pointer states j Introduction Table of contents 1 Technical introduction 2 Setup 3 Subsystem equilibration 4 Decoherence under weak interaction C. Gogolin j Universit¨atW¨urzburg j 2009-12-16 4 / 26 Einselection without pointer states j Technical introduction Technical introduction C. Gogolin j Universit¨atW¨urzburg j 2009-12-16 5 / 26 Include classical randomness ρ, 2 M(H) = j ih j X Tr[ρ] = hijρjii = 1 hAiρ = Tr[A ρ] i y − i H t ρt = Ut ρ0 Ut Ut = e mixtures: ρ = p 1 + (1 − p) 2 Einselection without pointer states j Technical introduction Quantum Mechanics on one slide Pure Quantum Mechanics j i 2 H A = Ay h j i = 1 hAi = h jAj i − i H t j ti = Ut j 0i Ut = e C. Gogolin j Universit¨atW¨urzburg j 2009-12-16 6 / 26 X Tr[ρ] = hijρjii = 1 hAiρ = Tr[A ρ] i y − i H t ρt = Ut ρ0 Ut Ut = e mixtures: ρ = p 1 + (1 − p) 2 Einselection without pointer states j Technical introduction Quantum Mechanics on one slide Pure Quantum Mechanics j i 2 H A = Ay h j i = 1 hAi = h jAj i − i H t j ti = Ut j 0i Ut = e Include classical randomness ρ, 2 M(H) = j ih j C. Gogolin j Universit¨atW¨urzburg j 2009-12-16 6 / 26 y − i H t ρt = Ut ρ0 Ut Ut = e mixtures: ρ = p 1 + (1 − p) 2 Einselection without pointer states j Technical introduction Quantum Mechanics on one slide Pure Quantum Mechanics j i 2 H A = Ay h j i = 1 hAi = h jAj i − i H t j ti = Ut j 0i Ut = e Include classical randomness ρ, 2 M(H) = j ih j X Tr[ρ] = hijρjii = 1 hAiρ = Tr[A ρ] i C. Gogolin j Universit¨atW¨urzburg j 2009-12-16 6 / 26 mixtures: ρ = p 1 + (1 − p) 2 Einselection without pointer states j Technical introduction Quantum Mechanics on one slide Pure Quantum Mechanics j i 2 H A = Ay h j i = 1 hAi = h jAj i − i H t j ti = Ut j 0i Ut = e Include classical randomness ρ, 2 M(H) = j ih j X Tr[ρ] = hijρjii = 1 hAiρ = Tr[A ρ] i y − i H t ρt = Ut ρ0 Ut Ut = e C. Gogolin j Universit¨atW¨urzburg j 2009-12-16 6 / 26 Einselection without pointer states j Technical introduction Quantum Mechanics on one slide Pure Quantum Mechanics j i 2 H A = Ay h j i = 1 hAi = h jAj i − i H t j ti = Ut j 0i Ut = e Include classical randomness ρ, 2 M(H) = j ih j X Tr[ρ] = hijρjii = 1 hAiρ = Tr[A ρ] i y − i H t ρt = Ut ρ0 Ut Ut = e mixtures: ρ = p 1 + (1 − p) 2 C. Gogolin j Universit¨atW¨urzburg j 2009-12-16 6 / 26 1 deff ( ) = 1 deff ( ) = d d = max Tr[A ρ] − Tr[A σ] 0≤A≤1 Effective dimension 1 deff (ρ) = Tr(ρ2) Time average 1 Z T ! = hρtit = lim ρt dt T !1 T 0 Einselection without pointer states j Technical introduction Technical introduction Trace distance 1 D(ρ, σ) = kρ − σk 2 1 C. Gogolin j Universit¨atW¨urzburg j 2009-12-16 7 / 26 1 deff ( ) = 1 deff ( ) = d d Effective dimension 1 deff (ρ) = Tr(ρ2) Time average 1 Z T ! = hρtit = lim ρt dt T !1 T 0 Einselection without pointer states j Technical introduction Technical introduction Trace distance 1 D(ρ, σ) = kρ − σk 2 1 = max Tr[A ρ] − Tr[A σ] 0≤A≤1 C. Gogolin j Universit¨atW¨urzburg j 2009-12-16 7 / 26 1 deff ( ) = 1 deff ( ) = d d Time average 1 Z T ! = hρtit = lim ρt dt T !1 T 0 Einselection without pointer states j Technical introduction Technical introduction Trace distance 1 D(ρ, σ) = kρ − σk 2 1 = max Tr[A ρ] − Tr[A σ] 0≤A≤1 Effective dimension 1 deff (ρ) = Tr(ρ2) C. Gogolin j Universit¨atW¨urzburg j 2009-12-16 7 / 26 1 deff ( ) = d d Time average 1 Z T ! = hρtit = lim ρt dt T !1 T 0 Einselection without pointer states j Technical introduction Technical introduction Trace distance 1 D(ρ, σ) = kρ − σk 2 1 = max Tr[A ρ] − Tr[A σ] 0≤A≤1 Effective dimension 1 deff (ρ) = deff ( ) = 1 Tr(ρ2) C. Gogolin j Universit¨atW¨urzburg j 2009-12-16 7 / 26 Time average 1 Z T ! = hρtit = lim ρt dt T !1 T 0 Einselection without pointer states j Technical introduction Technical introduction Trace distance 1 D(ρ, σ) = kρ − σk 2 1 = max Tr[A ρ] − Tr[A σ] 0≤A≤1 Effective dimension 1 1 deff (ρ) = deff ( ) = 1 deff ( ) = d Tr(ρ2) d C. Gogolin j Universit¨atW¨urzburg j 2009-12-16 7 / 26 Einselection without pointer states j Technical introduction Technical introduction Trace distance 1 D(ρ, σ) = kρ − σk 2 1 = max Tr[A ρ] − Tr[A σ] 0≤A≤1 Effective dimension 1 1 deff (ρ) = deff ( ) = 1 deff ( ) = d Tr(ρ2) d Time average 1 Z T ! = hρtit = lim ρt dt T !1 T 0 C. Gogolin j Universit¨atW¨urzburg j 2009-12-16 7 / 26 Explicit construction P 1 expand in basis: j i = i ci jii hijji = δij 2 choose ci from a normal distribution P 2 3 normalize 1 = i jcij h j i = 1 Einselection without pointer states j Technical introduction Choosing random states Mathematical construction Haar measure on SU(n) −! \uniform" distribution µ(V ) = µ(UV ) U j0i = j i Prfj ig = PrfU j ig C. Gogolin j Universit¨atW¨urzburg j 2009-12-16 8 / 26 Einselection without pointer states j Technical introduction Choosing random states Mathematical construction Haar measure on SU(n) −! \uniform" distribution µ(V ) = µ(UV ) U j0i = j i Prfj ig = PrfU j ig Explicit construction P 1 expand in basis: j i = i ci jii hijji = δij 2 choose ci from a normal distribution P 2 3 normalize 1 = i jcij h j i = 1 C. Gogolin j Universit¨atW¨urzburg j 2009-12-16 8 / 26 Einselection without pointer states j Setup Setup C. Gogolin j Universit¨atW¨urzburg j 2009-12-16 9 / 26 Einselection without pointer states j Setup Setup System, HS; H S Bath, HB; H B H SB S B ρt = TrB[ t] ρt = TrS[ t] 1 S Tr[(AS ⊗ B) t] = Tr[AS ρt ] reduced state ! locally observable C. Gogolin j Universit¨atW¨urzburg j 2009-12-16 10 / 26 1 S Tr[(AS ⊗ B) t] = Tr[AS ρt ] reduced state ! locally observable Einselection without pointer states j Setup Setup System, HS; H S Bath, HB; H B H SB S B ρt = TrB[ t] ρt = TrS[ t] d t dt = i [ t; H ] C. Gogolin j Universit¨atW¨urzburg j 2009-12-16 10 / 26 H 0 + H 0 / 1 Tr[H S] = Tr[H B] = Tr[H SB] = 0 Assumption A Hamiltonian has non{degenerate energy gaps iff: Ek − El = Em − En =) k = l ^ m = n or k = m ^ l = n Einselection without pointer states j Setup A very weak assumption on the Hamiltonian H = H S ⊗1 + 1 ⊗ H B + H SB C. Gogolin j Universit¨atW¨urzburg j 2009-12-16 11 / 26 Assumption A Hamiltonian has non{degenerate energy gaps iff: Ek − El = Em − En =) k = l ^ m = n or k = m ^ l = n Einselection without pointer states j Setup A very weak assumption on the Hamiltonian H = H 0 + H S ⊗1 + 1 ⊗ H B + H SB H 0 / 1 Tr[H S] = Tr[H B] = Tr[H SB] = 0 C. Gogolin j Universit¨atW¨urzburg j 2009-12-16 11 / 26 Einselection without pointer states j Setup A very weak assumption on the Hamiltonian H = H 0 + H S ⊗1 + 1 ⊗ H B + H SB H 0 / 1 Tr[H S] = Tr[H B] = Tr[H SB] = 0 Assumption A Hamiltonian has non{degenerate energy gaps iff: Ek − El = Em − En =) k = l ^ m = n or k = m ^ l = n C.
Recommended publications
  • Arxiv:Quant-Ph/0105127V3 19 Jun 2003
    DECOHERENCE, EINSELECTION, AND THE QUANTUM ORIGINS OF THE CLASSICAL Wojciech Hubert Zurek Theory Division, LANL, Mail Stop B288 Los Alamos, New Mexico 87545 Decoherence is caused by the interaction with the en- A. The problem: Hilbert space is big 2 vironment which in effect monitors certain observables 1. Copenhagen Interpretation 2 of the system, destroying coherence between the pointer 2. Many Worlds Interpretation 3 B. Decoherence and einselection 3 states corresponding to their eigenvalues. This leads C. The nature of the resolution and the role of envariance4 to environment-induced superselection or einselection, a quantum process associated with selective loss of infor- D. Existential Interpretation and ‘Quantum Darwinism’4 mation. Einselected pointer states are stable. They can retain correlations with the rest of the Universe in spite II. QUANTUM MEASUREMENTS 5 of the environment. Einselection enforces classicality by A. Quantum conditional dynamics 5 imposing an effective ban on the vast majority of the 1. Controlled not and a bit-by-bit measurement 6 Hilbert space, eliminating especially the flagrantly non- 2. Measurements and controlled shifts. 7 local “Schr¨odinger cat” states. Classical structure of 3. Amplification 7 B. Information transfer in measurements 9 phase space emerges from the quantum Hilbert space in 1. Action per bit 9 the appropriate macroscopic limit: Combination of einse- C. “Collapse” analogue in a classical measurement 9 lection with dynamics leads to the idealizations of a point and of a classical trajectory. In measurements, einselec- III. CHAOS AND LOSS OF CORRESPONDENCE 11 tion replaces quantum entanglement between the appa- A. Loss of the quantum-classical correspondence 11 B.
    [Show full text]
  • A Model-Theoretic Interpretation of Environmentally-Induced
    A model-theoretic interpretation of environmentally-induced superselection Chris Fields 815 East Palace # 14 Santa Fe, NM 87501 USA fi[email protected] November 28, 2018 Abstract The question of what constitutes a “system” is foundational to quantum mea- surement theory. Environmentally-induced superselection or “einselection” has been proposed as an observer-independent mechanism by which apparently classical sys- tems “emerge” from physical interactions between degrees of freedom described com- pletely quantum-mechanically. It is shown here that einselection can only generate classical systems if the “environment” is assumed a priori to be classical; einselection therefore does not provide an observer-independent mechanism by which classicality can emerge from quantum dynamics. Einselection is then reformulated in terms of positive operator-valued measures (POVMs) acting on a global quantum state. It is shown that this re-formulation enables a natural interpretation of apparently-classical systems as virtual machines that requires no assumptions beyond those of classical arXiv:1202.1019v2 [quant-ph] 13 May 2012 computer science. Keywords: Decoherence, Einselection, POVMs, Emergence, Observer, Quantum-to-classical transition 1 Introduction The concept of environmentally-induced superselection or “einselection” was introduced into quantum mechanics by W. Zurek [1, 2] as a solution to the “preferred-basis problem,” 1 the problem of selecting one from among the arbitrarily many possible sets of basis vectors spanning the Hilbert space of a system of interest. Zurek’s solution was brilliantly simple: it transferred the preferred basis problem from the observer to the environment in which the system of interest is embedded, and then solved the problem relative to the environment.
    [Show full text]
  • Decoherence and the Transition from Quantum to Classical—Revisited
    Decoherence and the Transition from Quantum to Classical—Revisited Wojciech H. Zurek This paper has a somewhat unusual origin and, as a consequence, an unusual structure. It is built on the principle embraced by families who outgrow their dwellings and decide to add a few rooms to their existing structures instead of start- ing from scratch. These additions usually “show,” but the whole can still be quite pleasing to the eye, combining the old and the new in a functional way. What follows is such a “remodeling” of the paper I wrote a dozen years ago for Physics Today (1991). The old text (with some modifications) is interwoven with the new text, but the additions are set off in boxes throughout this article and serve as a commentary on new developments as they relate to the original. The references appear together at the end. In 1991, the study of decoherence was still a rather new subject, but already at that time, I had developed a feeling that most implications about the system’s “immersion” in the environment had been discovered in the preceding 10 years, so a review was in order. While writing it, I had, however, come to suspect that the small gaps in the landscape of the border territory between the quantum and the classical were actually not that small after all and that they presented excellent opportunities for further advances. Indeed, I am surprised and gratified by how much the field has evolved over the last decade. The role of decoherence was recognized by a wide spectrum of practic- 86 Los Alamos Science Number 27 2002 ing physicists as well as, beyond physics proper, by material scientists and philosophers.
    [Show full text]
  • Decoherence, Einselection, and the Quantum Origins of the Classical
    REVIEWS OF MODERN PHYSICS, VOLUME 75, JULY 2003 Decoherence, einselection, and the quantum origins of the classical Wojciech Hubert Zurek Theory Division, LANL, Mail Stop B210, Los Alamos, New Mexico 87545 (Published 22 May 2003) The manner in which states of some quantum systems become effectively classical is of great significance for the foundations of quantum physics, as well as for problems of practical interest such as quantum engineering. In the past two decades it has become increasingly clear that many (perhaps all) of the symptoms of classicality can be induced in quantum systems by their environments. Thus decoherence is caused by the interaction in which the environment in effect monitors certain observables of the system, destroying coherence between the pointer states corresponding to their eigenvalues. This leads to environment-induced superselection or einselection, a quantum process associated with selective loss of information. Einselected pointer states are stable. They can retain correlations with the rest of the universe in spite of the environment. Einselection enforces classicality by imposing an effective ban on the vast majority of the Hilbert space, eliminating especially the flagrantly nonlocal ‘‘Schro¨ dinger-cat states.’’ The classical structure of phase space emerges from the quantum Hilbert space in the appropriate macroscopic limit. Combination of einselection with dynamics leads to the idealizations of a point and of a classical trajectory. In measurements, einselection replaces quantum entanglement between
    [Show full text]
  • 'Einselection' of Pointer Observables
    ‘Einselection’ of Pointer Observables: The New H-Theorem? Ruth E. Kastner † 16 June 2014 to appear in Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics ABSTRACT. In attempting to derive irreversible macroscopic thermodynamics from reversible microscopic dynamics, Boltzmann inadvertently smuggled in a premise that assumed the very irreversibility he was trying to prove: ‘molecular chaos.’ The program of ‘Einselection’ (environmentally induced superselection) within Everettian approaches faces a similar ‘Loschmidt’s Paradox’: the universe, according to the Everettian picture, is a closed system obeying only unitary dynamics, and it therefore contains no distinguishable environmental subsystems with the necessary ‘phase randomness’ to effect einselection of a pointer observable. The theoretically unjustified assumption of distinguishable environmental subsystems is the hidden premise that makes the derivation of einselection circular. In effect, it presupposes the ‘emergent’ structures from the beginning. Thus the problem of basis ambiguity remains unsolved in Everettian interpretations. 1. Introduction The decoherence program was pioneered by Zurek, Joos, and Zeh, 1 and has become a widely accepted approach for accounting for the appearance of stable macroscopic objects. In particular, decoherence has been used as the basis of arguments that sensible, macroscopic ‘pointer observables’ of measuring apparatuses are ‘einselected’ – selected preferentially by the environment. An important application of ‘einselection’ is in Everettian or ‘Many Worlds’ Interpretations (MWI), a class of interpretations that view all ‘branches’ of the quantum state as equally real. MWI abandons the idea of non-unitary collapse and allows only the unitary Schrödinger evolution of the quantum state. It has long been known that MWI suffers from a ‘basis arbitrariness’ problem; i.e., it has no way of explaining why the ‘splitting’ of worlds or of macroscopic objects such as apparatuses and observes occurs with respect to realistic bases that one would expect.
    [Show full text]
  • Decoherence and Einselection in Equilibrium in an Adapted Caldeira Leggett Model
    Decoherence and einselection in equilibrium in an adapted Caldeira Leggett model Andreas Albrecht Center for Quantum Mathematics and Physics (QMAP) and Department of Physics UC Davis Seminar University of Nottingham April 4, 2019 Supported by the US Department of Energy 4/4/19 A. Albrecht Nottingham seminar 1 Outline 1. Motivations 2. Introduction to einselection and the toy model 3. Einselection in equilibrium (technical explorations and overall assessment) 4. Eigenstate Einselection Hypothesis (if there is time) 5. Conclusions 4/4/19 A. Albrecht Nottingham seminar 2 Outline 1. Motivations 2. Introduction to einselection and the toy model 3. Einselection in equilibrium (technical explorations and overall assessment) 4. Eigenstate Einselection Hypothesis (if there is time) With A. Arrasmith 5. Conclusions 4/4/19 A. Albrecht Nottingham seminar 3 Outline 1. Motivations 2. Introduction to einselection and the toy model 3. Einselection in equilibrium (technical explorations and overall assessment) 4. Eigenstate Einselection Hypothesis (if there is time) 5. Conclusions 4/4/19 A. Albrecht Nottingham seminar 4 Comments on the arrow of time in cosmology (at board) 4/4/19 A. Albrecht Nottingham seminar 5 Q: What features of the universe are correlated with classicality? • Arrow of time? • Locality? • Etc. 4/4/19 A. Albrecht Nottingham seminar 6 Q: What features of the universe are correlated with classicality? • Arrow of time? • Locality? • Etc. ➔ Explore the process of einselection in a toy model, relate to AoT, etc. 4/4/19 A. Albrecht Nottingham seminar 7 Q: What features of the universe are correlated with classicality? • Arrow of time? • Locality? • Etc.Related to the emergence of classical ➔ Explore the process of einselection in a toy model, relate to AoT, etc.
    [Show full text]
  • Decoherence: an Explanation of Quantum Measurement
    Decoherence: An Explanation of Quantum Measurement Jason Gross\ast Massachusetts Institute of Technology, 77 Massachusetts Ave., Cambridge, MA 02139-4307 (Dated: May 5, 2012) The description of the world given by quantum mechanics is at odds with our classical experience. Most of this conflict resides in the concept of \measurement". After explaining the originsof the controversy, and introducing and explaining some of the relevant mathematics behind density matrices and partial trace, I will introduce decoherence as a way of describing classical measurements from an entirely quantum perspective. I will discuss basis ambiguity and the problem of information flow in a system + observer model, and explain how introducing the environment removes this ambiguity via environmentally-induced superselection. I will use a controlled not gate as a toy model of measurement; including a one-bit environment will provide an example of how interaction can pick out a preferred basis, and included an N-bit environment will give a toy model of decoherence. I. INTRODUCTION function over each independent observable. Moreover, the law of superposition, which states that any linear For any physicist who learns classical mechanics before combination of valid quantum states is also valid, gives quantum mechanics, the theory of quantum mechanics at rise to states that do not seem to correspond to any clas- first appears to be a strange and counter-intuitive wayto sical system anyone has experienced. The most famous describe the world. The correspondence between classical example of such a state is that of Schr\"odinger'shypo- experience and quantum theory is not obvious, and has thetical cat, which is in a superposition of being alive been at the core of debates about the interpretation of and being dead.
    [Show full text]
  • Decoherence and the Transition from Quantum to Classical—Revisited
    Decoherence and the Transition from Quantum to Classical—Revisited Wojciech H. Zurek This paper has a somewhat unusual origin and, as a consequence, an unusual struc- ture. It is built on the principle embraced by families who outgrow their dwellings and decide to add a few rooms to their existing structures instead of starting from scratch. These additions usually “show,” but the whole can still be quite pleasing to the eye, combining the old and the new in a functional way. What follows is such a “remodeling” of the paper I wrote a dozen years ago for Physics Today (1991). The old text (with some modifications) is interwoven with the new text, but the additions are set off in boxes throughout this article and serve as a commentary on new developments as they relate to the original. The references appear together at the end. In 1991, the study of decoherence was still a rather new subject, but already at that time, I had developed a feeling that most implications about the system’s “immersion” in the environment had been discovered in the preceding 10 years, so a review was in order. While writing it, I had, however, come to suspect that the small gaps in the land- scape of the border territory between the quantum and the classical were actually not that small after all and that they presented excellent opportunities for further advances. Indeed, I am surprised and gratified by how much the field has evolved over the last decade. The role of decoherence was recognized by a wide spectrum of practicing physicists as well as, beyond physics proper, by material scientists and philosophers.
    [Show full text]
  • Quantum Theory of the Classical
    QUANTUM THEORY OF THE CLASSICAL Wojciech Hubert Zurek (to be continued by Mike Zwolak and Jess Ridel) “BEYOND DECOHERENCE” Quantum Jumps (discrete outcomes from unitary evolutions) Quantum Origins of Probability (from entanglement) Quantum Darwinism (the origin of “objective reality”) WHZ, Nature Physics March 2009 Quantum Theory of the Classical PROGRAM: Take the core “quantum” postulates of textbook * quantum theory and investigate whether they can account for the quantum-classical transition. 0. State of a composite system is a vector in the Q tensor product of constituent Hilbert spaces. U C 1. States correspond to vectors in Hilbert space. A R (“Quantum Superposition Principle”) N E 2. Evolutions are unitary (e.g. generated by T D Schroedinger equation). (“Unitarity”) U O 3. Immediate repetition of a measurement } M yields the same outcome. (“Repeatability”) 4. (a) Outcomes are restricted to orthonormal states {|sk>} (eigenstates of the measured observable). (b) One outcome is seen each time. 2 5. Probability of an outcome |sk> given state |ƒ> is pk=|<sk|ƒ>| . (“Born’s Rule”) *Postulates according to Dirac DECOHERENCE, POINTER BASIS, AND EINSELECTION* S E H , σ σ = 0 [ SE i i ] ⎛ ⎞ Interaction α σ ⊗ ε = Φ t EntanglementH i i SE ( ) ΦSE (0) = ψS ⊗ ε0 = ⎜ α i σ i ⎟ ⊗ ε0 SE ∑ i ∑ i ⎝ i ⎠ 2 REDUCED DENSITY MATRIX ρS (t) = TrE ΦSE (t) ΦSE (t) = ∑α i σ i σ i € i EINSELECTION* leads to POINTER STATES Stable states, tend to appear near diagonal€ of ρ t after decoherence time; € S ( ) Pointer states are effectively€ classical! They preserve correlations: they are left unperturbed€ by the “environmental monitoring”.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:2105.14040V1 [Quant-Ph] 28 May 2021 (ACL) Model
    Adapted Caldeira-Leggett Model Andreas Albrecht∗ and Rose Baunachy Center for Quantum Mathematics and Physics and Department of Physics and Astronomy UC Davis, One Shields Ave, Davis CA. Andrew Arrasmithz Theoretical Division, Los Alamos National Laboratory, Los Alamos, NM USA. (Dated: June 1, 2021) We preset a variant of the Caldeira-Leggett (CL) model of a harmonic oscillator coupled to an environment. The CL model is a standard tool for studying the physics of decoherence. Our \adapted Caldeira-Leggett" (ACL) model is built in a finite Hilbert space which makes it suitable for numerical studies. Taking a numerical approach allows us to avoid the limitations of standard approximation schemes used with the CL model. We are able to evolve the ACL model in a fully reversible unitary manner, without the built-in time asymmetry and other assumptions that come with the master equation methods typically used. We have used the ACL model to study new topics in the field of decoherence and einselection where the full unitary evolution is essential to our work. Those results (reported in companion papers) include an examination of the relationship between einselection and the arrow of time, and studies of the very earliest stages of einselection. This paper provides details about the ACL model and our numerical methods. Our numerical approach makes it straightforward to explore and plot any property of the physical system. Thus we believe the examples and illustrations we present here may provide a helpful resource for those wishing to improve their familiarity with standard decoherence results, as well as those looking to probe the underpinnings of our companion papers.
    [Show full text]
  • Decoherence and the Classical Limit of Quantum Mechanics
    Universit´a degli Studi di Genova Dipartimento di Fisica Scuola di Dottorato Ciclo XIV Decoherence and the Classical Limit of Quantum Mechanics Valia Allori December 2001 2 Contents 1 Introduction 7 1.1 What Converges to What? ...................... 8 1.2 The Appeal to Decoherence ..................... 11 1.3 Beyond Standard Quantum Mechanics ............... 12 1.4 Classical Limit as a Scaling Limit .................. 13 1.5 Organization of the Thesis ...................... 15 1.6 Acknowledgments ........................... 16 2 Bohmian Mechanics 17 2.1 What is Quantum Mechanics About? ................ 17 2.2 The State of a System and The Dynamical Laws .......... 19 2.3 Bohmian Mechanics and Newtonian Mechanics ........... 20 2.4 Nonlocality and Hidden Variables .................. 21 2.5 The Quantum Equilibrium Hypothesis ............... 23 2.6 The Collapse of the Wave Function ................. 24 2.7 Bohmian Mechanics and the Quantum Potential .......... 26 3 Classical Limit in Bohmian Mechanics 29 3.1 Motion in an External Potential ................... 30 3.2 Conjecture on Classicality ...................... 32 3.3 Closeness of Laws and Closeness of Trajectories .......... 38 3.4 On the Hamilton-Jacobi Formulation ................ 41 4 Special Families 43 4.1 Quasi Classical Wave Functions ................... 43 3 4 CONTENTS 4.2 Slowly Varying Potentials ...................... 45 4.3 Convergence of Probability Distributions .............. 48 4.4 Propagation of Classical Probability Distributions ......... 49 5 Local Plane Wave Structure 53 5.1 The Notion of Local Plane Wave .................. 53 5.2 Local Plane Waves and the Quantum Potential .......... 56 5.3 The Ehrenfest–Goldstein Argument ................. 57 5.4 Some Remarks on L ......................... 59 5.5 Some Simple Examples of L ..................... 60 5.6 Refinement of the Conjecture ...................
    [Show full text]
  • A New Application of the Modal-Hamiltonian Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics: the Problem of Optical Isomerism
    A new application of the modal-Hamiltonian interpretation of quantum mechanics: the problem of optical isomerism ∗ Sebastian Fortin – Olimpia Lombardi – Juan Camilo Martínez González ∗∗ CONICET – Universidad de Buenos Aires 1.- Introduction The modal interpretations of quantum mechanics found their roots in the works of van Fraassen (1972, 1974), who claimed that the quantum state always evolves unitarily (with no collapse) and determines what may be the case: which physical properties the system may possess, and which properties the system may have at later times. On this basis, in the 1980s several authors presented realist interpretations that can be viewed as belonging to a “modal family”: realist, non-collapse interpretations of the standard formalism of the theory, according to which any quantum system possesses definite properties at all times, and the quantum state assigns probabilities to the possible properties of the system. Given the contextuality of quantum mechanics (Kochen and Specker 1967), the members of the family differ to each other in its rule of definite-value ascription, which picks out, from the set of all observables of a quantum system, the subset of definite-valued properties, that is, the preferred context (see Lombardi and Dieks 2014 and references therein). The traditional modal interpretations, based on the biorthogonal decomposition or on the spectral-decomposition of the quantum state (Kochen 1985, Dieks 1988, 1989, Vermaas and Dieks 1995) faced some difficulties. On the one hand, given the multiple factorizability of a given Hilbert space, their rules of definite-value ascription may lead to contradictions of the Kochen-Specker variety (Bacciagaluppi 1995, Vermaas 1997).
    [Show full text]