Hegel and the Phenomenology of Spirit Will Be Essential Reading 32 for All Students of Modern Philosophy and All Those Coming to Hegel for the first Time

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Hegel and the Phenomenology of Spirit Will Be Essential Reading 32 for All Students of Modern Philosophy and All Those Coming to Hegel for the first Time Routledge Philosophy GuideBook to 1 2 3 4 5 6 Hegel 7 8 and the Phenomenology of Spirit 9 10 11 12 13 ‘a very clear, accessible, philosophical introduction to Hegel’s 14 prodigious Phenomenology of Spirit . Stern’s interpretation is 15 distinctive, and yet accessible, useful, and stimulating for students and professionals alike . Stern’s new introduction is very 16 welcome indeed.’ 17 Kenneth R. Westphal, University of East Anglia 18 19 The Phenomenology of Spirit is Hegel’s most influential and famous 20 work. It is essential to understanding Hegel’s philosophical system and 21 why he remains a major figure in Western Philosophy. This GuideBook is a clear and accessible introduction to this complex text. It sets out 22 Hegel’s important notion of ‘dialectic’ and explores Hegel’s treatment 23 of the object, the subject, freedom, ethical life, faith and philosophy 24 itself. 25 Robert Stern discusses these topics in non-Hegelian language, 26 making Hegel’s work accessible to all readers of this GuideBook. He 27 provides a background to Hegel’s life and work and a careful explo- 28 ration of each section of the Phenomenology of Spirit. Stern sheds light 29 on Hegel’s method, aims and philosophical ambitions, and assesses the 30 continuing importance of his work to contemporary philosophy. 31 Hegel and the Phenomenology of Spirit will be essential reading 32 for all students of modern philosophy and all those coming to Hegel for the first time. 33 34 Robert Stern is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Sheffield. 35 He is the author of Hegel, Kant and the Structure of the Object (1990), 36 and editor of G. W. F. Hegel: Critical Assessments (1993). 37 Folio 1 Routledge 2 m Philosophy 3 GuideBooks 4 5 Edited by Tim Crane and Jonathan Wolff 6 University College London 7 8 Hegel and the Phenomenology of Spirit 9 Robert Stern 10 Berkeley and the Principles of Human Knowledge 11 Robert J. Fogelin 12 Aristotle on Ethics Gerard J. Hughes 13 14 Hume on Religion David O’Connor 15 Leibniz and the Monadology Anthony Savile 16 The Later Heidegger George Pattison 17 18 Hegel on History Joseph McCarney 19 Hume on Morality James Baillie 20 Kant and the Critique of Pure Reason Sebastian Gardner 21 22 Mill on Liberty Jonathan Riley 23 Mill on Utilitarianism Roger Crisp 24 Wittgenstein and the Philosophical Investigations 25 Marie McGinn 26 27 Plato and the Republic Nickolas Pappas 28 Locke on Government D. A. Lloyd Thomas 29 Locke on Human Understanding E. J. Lowe 30 31 Spinoza and the Ethics Genevieve Lloyd 32 33 34 35 36 37 LONDON AND NEW YORK Folio ROUTLEDGE Routledge Philosophy GuideBook to 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 Hegel 8 9 10 and the 11 12 13 Phenomenology 14 15 of Spirit 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 I Robert Stern 37 Folio First published 2002 British Library Cataloguing in by Routledge Publication Data 11 New Fetter Lane, A catalogue record for this book is London EC4P 4EE available from the British Library Simultaneously published in Library of Congress Cataloging the USA and Canada in Publication Data by Routledge Stern, Robert, 1962– 29 West 35th Street, Routledge philosophy guidebook to New York, NY 10001 Hegel and the Phenomenology of spirit/Robert Stern. Routledge is an imprint of p. cm. – (Routledge philosophy the Taylor & Francis Group guidebooks) This edition published in the Includes bibliographical references Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2002. and index. 1. Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, © 2002 Robert Stern 1770–1831. Phaenomenologie des Geistes. I. Title: Hegel and the Phenomenology of spirit. II. Title. All rights reserved. No part of this III. Series. book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilized in any form or by any B2929 .S65 2001 electronic, mechanical, or other means, 193–dc21 2001049064 now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, ISBN 0–415–21787–3 (hbk) or in any information storage or ISBN 0–415–21788–1 (pbk) retrieval system, without permission in ISBN 0-203-20504-9 Master e-book ISBN writing from the publishers. ISBN 0-203-20507-3 (Glassbook Format) Contents Chapter 1 1 2 3 4 Contents 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 Preface and acknowledgements vii 18 Introduction xi 19 List of abbreviations xvii 20 21 1 The Phenomenology in context 1 22 23 Hegel and his times 1 24 The place of the Phenomenology in Hegel’s 25 life and works 4 26 Hegel’s system 11 27 The role of the Phenomenology 21 28 The Preface and the Introduction 30 29 30 31 2 The dialectic of the object 43 32 Sense-certainty 43 33 Perception 51 34 Force and the Understanding 59 35 The transition to Self-consciousness 66 36 37 v Folio CONTENTS 1 3 The dialectic of the subject 71 2 3 Mastership and Servitude 71 4 Stoicism, Scepticism, and the Unhappy Consciousness 85 5 6 4 The dialectic of Reason 97 7 8 Rationalism and idealism 97 9 Observing Reason 102 10 Active Reason 114 11 Practical Reason 124 12 13 5 The dialectic of Spirit 135 14 15 True Spirit: Ethical Life 135 16 Self-Alienated Spirit: Culture 147 17 Spirit That Is Certain Of Itself: Morality 168 18 19 6 The dialectic of Religion 183 20 21 Natural Religion 183 22 Religion in the Form of Art 186 23 The Revealed Religion 190 24 25 26 7 Philosophy as dialectic 195 27 Absolute Knowing 195 28 Conclusion 198 29 30 Notes 203 31 Further reading 207 32 Bibliography 213 33 Index 231 34 35 36 37 Folio vi Preface Chapter 1 1 2 3 4 Preface and 5 6 acknowledgements 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 ‘A great man condemns posterity to the necessity of 19 explicating him’ (NA: 574). Written as an isolated 20 aphorism, it is unclear whether in making this claim, 21 Hegel was thinking of himself or others: but there is 22 no doubt that in his case, this necessity still holds. As 23 a great thinker, Hegel continues to exert an enormous 24 influence on our time; so in order to comprehend 25 ourselves, we must continually strive to come to terms 26 with his thought, and to understand it anew. 27 This book is a contribution to this process, 28 intended to shed light on the Phenomenology of Spirit 29 for those who are approaching this work for the first 30 time, and who are looking for some way through the 31 labyrinth. I have therefore endeavoured to make my 32 commentary as clear as possible, and to relate it closely 33 to the text. Of course, as Hegel perhaps foresaw, a rich 34 tradition of interpretation has grown up around the 35 Phenomenology, particularly since the 1930s; but for 36 reasons of space and accessibility, I have not been able 37 vii Folio PREFACE AND ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS 1 to reflect critically on other interpretations in any detail here, although 2 I have provided references and further reading. I have also assumed 3 that my audience will primarily be English speaking, so I have used 4 standard translations where available, making amendments when 5 necessary (see the Bibliography for further details). 6 I have been helped in this project by many individuals. I would 7 first like to thank Tim Crane and Jo Wolff for inviting me to under- 8 take it (and for waiting for me until I was able to do so). I am 9 particularly grateful to those members of staff and postgraduates at the 10 University of Sheffield who participated in a reading group on the 11 Phenomenology, accompanied by a draft of my commentary, who led 12 me to clarify my thoughts and writing in a number of ways: Leif 13 Wenar, Dominique Kuenzle, Mark Day, and Kathryn Wilkinson were 14 particularly helpful (and stalwart) in this regard. I am also grateful to 15 the two classes of students who took my course on the Phenomenology, 16 and who acted as a testing ground for the suitability of my text for its 17 intended audience. Other individuals who have offered helpful 18 comments and guidance at various times include: Gary Browning, 19 Matthew Festenstein, Terry Pinkard, Nicholas Walker, Robert Wokler, 20 and Heather Worden. I owe an especially large debt to those who acted 21 as readers of the manuscript for Routledge: Fred Beiser, Stephen 22 Houlgate, Ken Westphal, and Jo Wolff. All of them made a number 23 of suggestions and constructive criticisms, which have improved the 24 final book (although, of course, not all disagreements between us on 25 matters of interpretation have been settled, and none of them should 26 be held responsible for the views expressed here). Finally, Routledge 27 also provided considerable support on the editorial side, where Muna 28 Khogali and Tony Bruce were efficient and encouraging throughout. 29 Hegel may have anticipated the drive for explication that his 30 work would provoke; he certainly anticipated its dangers, emphasizing 31 in the Preface of the Phenomenology how hard fair-minded explica- 32 tion can be: 33 This concern with aim or results, with differentiating and passing 34 judgement on various thinkers is therefore an easier task than it 35 might seem. For instead of getting involved with the real issue, 36 this kind of activity is always away beyond it; instead of tarrying 37 Folio viii PREFACE AND ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS with it, and losing itself in it, this kind of knowing is forever 1 grasping at something new; it remains essentially preoccupied 2 with itself instead of being preoccupied with the real issue and 3 surrendering to it.
Recommended publications
  • Curriculum Vitae
    JAMES VAN CLEVE [email protected] October 17, 2018 Addresses School of Philosophy Home: Summer: University of Southern California 458 Stanford Drive 98 Sefton Drive Los Angeles, CA 90089 Claremont, CA 91711 Cranston, RI 02905 213-740-4084 909-625-5473 401-941-6513 Education B.A., The University of Iowa, 1969 M.A., The University of Rochester, 1972 Ph.D., The University of Rochester, 1974 (Dissertation Title: The Role of the Given in Empirical Knowledge) Professional Appointments University of Southern California: Professor of Philosophy, beginning Fall 2005. Visiting Professor of Philosophy, 2002-2003, Spring 2004, and Spring 2005. Brown University, Adjunct Professor, 2005-2018 Brown University: Professor of Philosophy, 1987-2005. Chair, Department of Philosophy, 1986-1991 and 1999-2003. Associate Professor, 1979-87; Assistant Professor, 1973-1979. Massachusetts Institute of Technology: Visiting Professor, Fall 2018 University of Iowa: Visiting Professor of Philosophy, Spring 2002. Duke University: Visiting Professor of Philosophy, Spring 1989, Fall 1991, and Spring 1993. Jadavpur University (Calcutta, India): Fulbright Visiting Professor, July 1980- February 1981. Honors and Awards Woodrow Wilson Dissertation Fellowship, 1972-73. Brown University Summer Stipend for Faculty Research, 1974. Brown University Wriston Fellowship ("to recognize significant previous accomplishments in innovative teaching or curricular improvement"), 1978. Fulbright Award to Lecture in India, July 1980 through January 1981. American Council of Learned Societies Fellowship, February 1981 through July 1981. Wayland Collegium Incentive Grant (to develop the course "Science, Perception, and Reality"), 1984. 2 National Humanities Center Fellowship, 1990-91. National Endowment for the Humanities grant to teach a Summer Seminar for College Teachers during July and August of 2000.
    [Show full text]
  • Dialectical Idealism and the Work of Lorenz Von Stein
    JOHN WEISS DIALECTICAL IDEALISM AND THE WORK OF LORENZ VON STEIN Dialectical idealism as applied to social theory may be provisionally defined as an attempt to explain the evolution of Western society through the use of dialectical forms which rely upon the presumed motive power of spiritual, mental, or ideal forces. These forces are presumed to "realize themselves" in the historical process. Hegel and Fichte, of course, first made such concepts familiar. The mighty influence of Marx and dialectical materialism, which kept the form but not the idealism of the Hegelian dialectic, has accounted for a lasting eclipse of interest in this earlier form of dialectical social thought. It is at least partly a symptom of this general decline of interest in dialectical idealism that the work of Lorenz von Stein has become, until quite recently, all but forgotten to modern scholarship.1 German idealism was, after all, the great seminal force in nineteenth century social and historical thought. And Lorenz von Stein was one of the first and (barring Marx and Engels) perhaps the most able of those who applied Hegelian categories to the study of society and the social process. Furthermore, Stein's work is interesting to the student of German intellectual history, because it sheds much light on the themes and assumptions which were held by those young German intellectuals of the Vormdr^ who created, out of German idealism and their own revolutionary hopes, the tradition of modern German social theory and social radicalism. However ineffectual they appear to us now, the German Wars of Liberation and the Prussion Reform Era along with the Revolutions 1 It is encouraging to note that Kaethe Mengelberg, one of the most astute students of Stein's work, will soon publish a translation of his major work: Geschichte der Sozialen Bewegung in Frankreich.
    [Show full text]
  • Cvnov2011.Pdf
    1 Barbara M. Sattler University of St. Andrews, Department of Philosophy Edgecliffe, The Scores St. Andrews, Fife KY16 9AR KY16 E-mail: [email protected] Phone: 01334 462474 Positions held: Summer 2013 – present Permanent position at the University of St. Andrews, Department of Philosophy Summer Semester 2016 Gastprofessur für das Fachgebiet “Philosophie der Antike und Ge- genwart” at the Humboldt Universität (HU) Berlin Summer 2007 – 2013 Assistant Professor of Philosophy and the Humanities Program at Yale University; Secondary Appointment in Classics Summer 2005 – 2007 Tenure-track position at the University of Illinois at Urbana-Cham- paign, Department of Philosophy and Department of the Classics Candlemas semester 2002 Tutor in the Department of Philosophy at St. Andrews 1997 – 2000 Teaching and research assistantship with Prof. Theunissen, FU-Berlin, in metaphysics and ontology 1992 – 1995 Private Tutor in mathematics Education and Qualifications: Fall 2001 – June 2006: Freie Universität (FU) Berlin: PhD (summa cum laude) October 2004 - June 2005 Diplomatische Akademie Wien, certificate in history, international relations, law and modern languages June – July 2004 Wolfson College, Oxford: Academic Visitor Fall 2002 – summer 2003 University of Oxford: visiting graduate student February – June 2002 St. Andrews University: visiting graduate student February 2001 FU-Berlin: M.A. (with distinction) 1995 – 2000 FU-Berlin: Studies in Philosophy and German literature 1993 – 1995 University of Vienna: Studies in German Philology, Philosophy
    [Show full text]
  • Augustinian Christian Philosophy
    AUGUSTINIAN CHRISTIAN PHILOSOPHY How does Christianity bear on philosophy? Is there such a thing as Christian philosophy, or are there only Christians who are also philoso­ phers? How should Christianity and philosophy be related? Should they be related? In "Advice to Christian Philosophers" I said that Christian philosophers should display more autonomy: they have their own fish to fry, their own projects to pursue, (or their own axes to grind, as some might prefer to put it). Here I want to say more about what these projects (or fish, or axes) are like. And the right way to think about these matters, so it seems to me, is broadly Augustinian. Accordingly, I want to propose a program­ matic sketch (a very programmatic sketch) of a conception of Christian philosophy that grows out of some central Augustinian emphases. I don't claim, however, that Augustine in fact thought of Christian philosophy the way I shall suggest. The primary focus of my paper is not historical (that would in any event be beyond my competence); what I want to do is make a suggestion as to how we should think about Christian philosophy now; but this way of thinking of the matter grows out of Augustinian roots.! It's worth noting, furthermore, that what is at issue is not just a way of thinking about Christianity and philosophy, but about Christianity and scholarship more generally. There are at least four elements in Augustinian Christian philosophy. The first two of these are widely recognized and relatively uncontroversial: I shall therefore be brief about them.
    [Show full text]
  • Hegel and Marx on Alienation a Thesis Submitted to the Graduate School of Social Sciences of Middle East Technical University By
    HEGEL AND MARX ON ALIENATION A THESIS SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF SOCIAL SCIENCES OF MIDDLE EAST TECHNICAL UNIVERSITY BY SEVGİ DOĞAN IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS IN THE DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY FEBRUARY 2008 Approval of the Graduate School of (Name of the Graduate School) Prof. Dr. Sencer Ayata Director I certify that this thesis satisfies all the requirements as a thesis for the degree of Master of Arts. Prof. Dr. Ahmet İnam Head of Department This is to certify that we have read this thesis and that in our opinion it is fully adequate, in scope and quality, as a thesis for the degree of Master of Arts of Philosophy. Assist. Prof. Dr. Barış Parkan Supervisor Examining Committee Members Assist. Prof. Dr. Barış Parkan (METU, PHIL) Assist. Prof. Dr. Elif Çırakman (METU, PHIL) Assist. Prof. Dr. Çetin Türkyılmaz (Hacettepe U., PHIL) I hereby declare that all information in this document has been obtained and presented in accordance with academic rules and ethical conduct. I also declare that, as required by these rules and conduct, I have fully cited and referenced all material and results that are not original to this work. Name, Last name: Sevgi Doğan Signature : iii ABSTRACT HEGEL AND MARX ON ALIENATION Doğan, Sevgi M.A., Department of Philosophy Supervisor: Assist. Prof. Barış Parkan February 2008, 139 pages Is alienation a process of self-discovery or is it a loss of reality? The subject of this thesis is how alienation is discussed in Hegel and Marx’s philosophies in terms of this question.
    [Show full text]
  • Religion and Representation in Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit
    DePaul University Via Sapientiae College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences 11-2017 The perversion of the absolute: religion and representation in Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit Thomas Floyd Wright DePaul University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd Recommended Citation Wright, Thomas Floyd, "The perversion of the absolute: religion and representation in Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit" (2017). College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations. 240. https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd/240 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences at Via Sapientiae. It has been accepted for inclusion in College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Via Sapientiae. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE PERVERSION OF THE ABSOLUTE Religion and Representation in Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit A Dissertation Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy December 2017 BY Thomas Floyd Wright Department of Philosophy College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences DePaul University Chicago, Illinois Contents 1 Introduction 1 1.1 Hegel contra Theology . 1 1.2 Marx, Ante-Hegel . 5 1.3 Hegel, post Hegel mortum . 11 1.4 Speculation and perversion . 16 2 The perversion of identity 22 2.1 The evil of ontotheology . 22 2.2 The perversion of desire: Augustine . 26 2.3 The perversion of speech: Hobbes . 30 2.4 The perversion of reason: Kant .
    [Show full text]
  • On Hegel on Buddhism Mario D'amato Rollins College, [email protected]
    Rollins College Rollins Scholarship Online Student-Faculty Collaborative Research 1-1-2011 The pS ecter of Nihilism: On Hegel on Buddhism Mario D'Amato Rollins College, [email protected] Robert T. Moore Rollins College Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.rollins.edu/stud_fac Part of the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Published In D'Amato, Mario and Moore, Robert T., "The peS cter of Nihilism: On Hegel on Buddhism" (2011). Student-Faculty Collaborative Research. Paper 28. http://scholarship.rollins.edu/stud_fac/28 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Rollins Scholarship Online. It has been accepted for inclusion in Student-Faculty Collaborative Research by an authorized administrator of Rollins Scholarship Online. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Specter of Nihilism: On Hegel on Buddhism ∗ Mario D’Amato and Robert T. Moore Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (1770-1831) is renowned as one of the most complex and comprehensive modern philosophers. The goal of his philosophical system is nothing less than to explain the interrelationships among all the multifarious aspects of the whole of reality, including the entire array of historical religions. But Hegel’s dialectical method has been criticized as being speculative and idealistic, and his interpretation of religion has been written off by some as an overly ambitious attempt to force the historical religions into the confines of a predetermined hierarchical scheme. As for his perspective on Buddhism, Hegel interprets it as a form of nihilism, stating that for Buddhism, “the ultimate or highest [reality] is…nothing or not- being” and the “state of negation is the highest state: one must immerse oneself in this nothing, in the eternal tranquillity of the nothing generally” (LPR 253).1 Hegel’s interpretation of Buddhism has of course been appropriately criticized in recent scholarship, most ably by Roger-Pol Droit in his work The Cult of Nothingness: The Philosophers and the Buddha (2003).
    [Show full text]
  • PHILOSOPHICAL (PRE)OCCUPATIONS and the PROBLEM of IDEALISM: from Ideology to Marx’S Critique of Mental Labor
    PHILOSOPHICAL (PRE)OCCUPATIONS AND THE PROBLEM OF IDEALISM: From Ideology to Marx’s Critique of Mental Labor by Ariane Fischer Magister, 1999, Freie Universität Berlin M.A., 2001, The Ohio State University M.Phil., 2005, The George Washington University A Dissertation submitted to The Faculty of Columbian College of Arts and Sciences of The George Washington University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy January 31, 2010 Dissertation directed by Andrew Zimmerman Associate Professor of History The Columbian College of The George Washington University certifies that Ariane Fischer has passed the Final Examination for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy as of August 25, 2009. This is the final and approved form of the dissertation. PHILOSOPHICAL (PRE)OCCUPATIONS AND THE PROBLEM OF IDEALISM: From Ideology to Marx’s Critique of Mental Labor Ariane Fischer Dissertation Research Committee: Andrew Zimmerman, Associate Professor of History, Dissertation Director Peter Caws, University Professor of Philosophy, Committee Member Gail Weiss, Professor of Philosophy, Committee Member ii © Copyright 2010 by Ariane Fischer All rights reserved iii Acknowledgments The author wishes to thank her dissertation advisor Andrew Zimmerman, who has been a continuous source of support and encouragement. His enthusiastic yet demanding guidance has been invaluable. Both his superior knowledge of history and theory as well as his diligence in reviewing drafts have been crucial in the successful completion of the research and writing process. Further, many thanks are extended to Gail Weiss and Peter Caws for joining the dissertation committee, and to Dan Moschenberg and Paul Smith for agreeing to be readers.
    [Show full text]
  • 18062020130129-Hegel 2.Pdf
    GEORGE WILHELM FRIEDRICH HEGEL (1770-1831) George Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel and all the other important German thinkers, Kant, Fichte etc were the children of the French Revolution. Compared to both England and France, Germany was much more backward and feudal, consisting of more than 300 states linked to the Holly Roman Empire, with leadership provided by Francis I of Austria. It came to an end when Napoleon defeated this 1000 years old empire and subsequently in 1806 defeated another powerful German state, Prussia. Hegel was a resident of Prussia at the time of the defeat. Hegel is the most methodologically self-conscious of all philosophers in the western tradition His system encompasses philosophy, metaphysics, religion art, ethics, history and politics- In its range alone his work is impressive and of a truly encyclopaedic character. His position in Germany was so powerful that even the most ferocious attack against orthodox German philosophy that of Karl Marx, sprang largely form Hegelian assumptions. Hegel was born in Stuttgart on 27 August 1770, the eldest son of a middle class family. His father was a civil servant, and most of his relatives were either teachers or Lutheran ministers. As a student, Hegel’s major interest was theology. But he soon gravitated towards philosophy. After completing his studies he accepted the position of a family tutor with a wealthy family in Switzerland from 1793-1796. This was followed by a similar position at Bern and Frankfurt from 1797 to 1800. In 1806 the French armies defeated Prussia at the decisive battle of Jena and Hegel saw Napoleon ride through Jena.
    [Show full text]
  • I HEGEL's LOGIC of ABSOLUTE IDEALISM and HIS POLITICAL
    HEGEL’S LOGIC OF ABSOLUTE IDEALISM AND HIS POLITICAL ARGUMENT: THE CONCEPTUALITY OF ACTUALITY A Dissertation Submitted to the Temple University Graduate Board in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY by Matthew J. Smetona May, 2010 Examining Committee Members: Aryeh Botwinick, Advisory Chair, Political Science Joseph M. Schwartz, Political Science Carol C. Gould, Philosophy and Political Science Joseph Margolis, External Member, Philosophy i © by Matthew J. Smetona 2010 All Rights Reserved ii ABSTRACT Title: Hegel’s Logic of Absolute Idealism and his Political Argument: The Conceptuality of Actuality Candidate’s Name: Matthew J. Smetona Degree: Doctor of Philosophy Temple University, 2010 Doctoral Advisory Committee Chair: Aryeh Botwinick This dissertation is about the theoretical foundation of Hegel’s political argument. Its goal is to comprehend the basic structure of that argument by articulating the conceptual framework Hegel employs when he asserts that the particular set of political institutions he is arguing for is rational. Its argument is that the criterion Hegel employs in his conception of rationality is that an object is rational if and only if it is comprehended by thought in and through the holistic inferential system of concepts he refers to as the Concept ( der Begriff ). Hegel’s final argument in the Science of Logic is that there can be no actual object that is not “rational,” i.e., that is not constituted, in all of its determinations, by the unified activity of thinking that is the Concept. Consequently, it is argued that the rationality, and therewith the actuality, of Hegel’s rational state depicted in the Philosophy of Right derives from the fact that it is comprehended by thought in and through the totality as thought that is the Concept.
    [Show full text]
  • Shared Experience and Sensibility I: Introduction One of the Most
    Shared Experience and Sensibility I: Introduction One of the most well­known and influential theses of Immanuel Kant’s critical philosophical period is his doctrine of Transcendental Idealism. This doctrine, when reduced to its essentials, makes a single bold and influential claim: we can know appearances but not things­in­themselves. However, the details of Transcendental Idealism often result in more division among scholars than agreement. At the heart of Kant’s theoretical philosophy are two important claims about how humans beings structure experience, and one about how they do not. First, humans have two forms of sensibility in which all sense data must be presented: space and time. Thus, all intuitions1 are intuitions of objects in space and time. Second, ​ ​ humans structure and think about their perceptions (i.e. make objective judgements of ​ ​ experience) by making use of the a priori Pure Concepts of the Understanding, or the categories. The categories provide rules for experience; for example: Every alteration has a ​ ​ ​ cause (CPR, B4­5)2. Together, the forms of intuition and the categories provide conditions on ​ the possibility of experience. Put another way, all experience is experience of objects in space ​ and time which are in accord with the categories. Experience is not experience of ​ ​ things­in­themselves. This essay deals with shared human experience—that is, experience of the same object(s) or event(s) shared by two different individuals. In particular, it seeks to investigate what is required for a numerically­identical experience of the world. Throughout Kant’s early ​ ​ and critical writings, the topic is seemingly important, though seldom, if ever, brought to the foreground of discussion.
    [Show full text]
  • Hegel After Augustine, an Essay on Political Theology Geoffrey J.D
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Dissertations (2009 -) Dissertations, Theses, and Professional Projects Transcending Subjects: Hegel After Augustine, an Essay on Political Theology Geoffrey J.D. Holsclaw Marquette University Recommended Citation Holsclaw, Geoffrey J.D., "Transcending Subjects: Hegel After Augustine, an Essay on Political Theology" (2013). Dissertations (2009 -). Paper 303. http://epublications.marquette.edu/dissertations_mu/303 TRANSCENDING SUBJECTS: HEGEL AFTER AUGUSTINE, AN ESSAY ON POLITICAL THEOLOGY by Geoffrey J. D. Holsclaw, B.A., M.Div. A Dissertation submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School, Marquette University, in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Milwaukee, Wisconsin December 2013 ABSTRACT TRANSCENDING SUBJECTS: HEGEL AFTER AUGUSTINE, AN ESSAY ON POLITICAL THEOLOGY Geoffrey J. D. Holsclaw, B.A., M.Div. Marquette University, 2013 From where do political reformers and radicals come who are willing and prepared to challenge the status quo? Where are people formed who are capable of initiating change within a political system? Some worry belief in transcendence closes off authentic political engagement and processes of transformation. Others think that a transcendent orientation is the only means to protect and promote a more free and just society. Some see a positive commitment to transcendence as inimical to democratic practices, while others see such a commitment as indispensible for such a project. These general issues concern transcendence, immanence, and subjectivity as they bear on the question of political transformation. Explaining the differences between these fundamental orientations prompts an investigation of the philosophical and theological systems of Hegel and Augustine. Examining Hegel and Augustine around the issues of transcendence and freedom offers a way to understand these more localized disagreements between political philosophers and theologians, and even between theologians.
    [Show full text]