Global Distributive Justice After Rawls: a Modified Poggean Argument for How We Harm the World's Poorest" (2011)

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Global Distributive Justice After Rawls: a Modified Poggean Argument for How We Harm the World's Poorest Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Dissertations Theses and Dissertations 2011 Global Distributive Justice After Rawls: A Modified oggeanP Argument for How We Harm the World's Poorest Mark Chakoian Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss Part of the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Chakoian, Mark, "Global Distributive Justice After Rawls: A Modified Poggean Argument for How We Harm the World's Poorest" (2011). Dissertations. 211. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss/211 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 2011 Mark Chakoian LOYOLA UNIVERSITY CHICAGO GLOBAL DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE AFTER RAWLS: A MODIFIED POGGEAN ARGUMENT FOR HOW WE HARM THE WORLD‘S POOREST A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE GRADUATE SCHOOL IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY PROGRAM IN PHILOSOPHY BY MARK CHAKOIAN CHICAGO, ILLINOIS AUGUST 2011 Copyright by Mark Chakoian, 2011 All rights reserved ACKNOWLEDGMENTS My extreme gratitude goes to my director, David Ingram, for all of his help. I would also like to thank my readers, David Schweickart and Tom Wren, along with the other members of my proposal committee, Tom Carson and Diana Meyers, who helped me to better formulate my project. I would also like to thank Andrew Cutrofello, for helping me to figure out what I really wanted to write about. Finally, I would like to thank my parents for their unconditional support. iii PREFACE In 2004, I entered Loyola‘s doctoral program in philosophy. I had just completed my undergraduate work at Bradley University. Majoring in mathematics at Bradley, I soon discovered philosophy through my choice of electives and added it as a second major. The philosophy program at Bradley was small, with two dedicated professors. The first philosopher I fell in love with was Heidegger, and I decided to pursue graduate work in continental philosophy. Considering myself a continental philosopher and Heideggerian, as a graduate student at Loyola I also pursued another side of philosophy out of personal interest: social and political. Living in Chicago, Race Theory struck me as being particularly interesting and important, and it was on Charles Mills‘ Blackness Visible that I wrote my Master‘s paper. When I finished my coursework, I began discussing a dissertation on Heidegger with one of my professors; when she left the department, I took a step back to reconsider what my doctoral project would be. As a senior at Bradley University, I had taken a philosophy seminar on cosmopolitanism. In it, my professor posed the question of whether it was just to buy a can of cola (such as the one he always had in hand), when that dollar could provide life-saving support to a needy child. Thinking through this at the time, I concluded that justice and morality were relative terms, and that those with the money made the rules. That basic question, however, stuck with me; as I continued into my graduate studies, I couldn‘t shake the feeling that the money I was living on could be better spent saving the lives of others. I iv soon began considering other ways that my actions impacted those around me: the environmental impact of the meat I consumed, the consequences of the runoff from pesticides and fertilizers used to grow the food I ate, the conditions of the factories where my clothes were produced. I did not connect my lifestyle changes to philosophy until I began reconsidering my dissertation topic: could an argument be made that justified, or even demanded, that we live our lives with an eye to our impacts on others? In my pursuit of this question I came across the work of Thomas Pogge. As I considered the ways that this basic argument could take shape—that we have obligations to live our lives differently because of the ways that we harm others—I narrowed the scope of my dissertation to be an analysis and reformulation of Pogge‘s main argument from World Poverty and Human Rights. As my research continues, I turn to the other implications of negative-duty arguments: How do we harm others through actions that we consider to be commonplace? How do the affluent within our own society harm the worst off within it? Is it possible for individuals today to live without harming others, and what are the implications if it is not? v TABLE OF CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGMENTS iii PREFACE iv LIST OF TABLES viii LIST OF FIGURES ix INTRODUCTION 1 Summary of Chapters 2 Final Remarks 8 CHAPTER ONE: RAWLS AND THE LIMITS OF JUSTICE 9 Introduction 9 A Theory of Justice 10 Freeman‘s Defense of Rawls 21 Peoples as Masters of their Own Fates 44 A Fully Veiled Duty 49 Preliminary Conclusions 51 CHAPTER TWO: SINGER AND OUR OBLIGATIONS TO THE WORLD‘S POOREST 60 Introduction 60 Positive Duties 62 Three Kinds of Duty 78 CHAPTER THREE: TWO WAYS WE HARM THE WORST OFF: UPHOLDING THE UNJUST RESULTS OF OUR SHARED HISTORY AND EXCLUSION FROM A COMMON RESOURCE POOL 93 Introduction 93 Defending the Argument from Harm 94 Our Shared Violent History 100 Exclusion from a Shared Resource Pool 126 CHAPTER FOUR: TWO WAYS WE HARM THE WORST OFF: OUR GLOBAL INSTITUTIONS AND ENVIRONMENTAL DAMAGES 138 Shared Global Institutions 138 Convergence Theory 163 Environmental Harm 166 Convergence Theory Revisited 177 CHAPTER FIVE: A MODEST PROPOSAL 181 A Modest Proposal 184 The Connection of the GRD to the Poggean Argument 197 vi Objections to the GRD 205 Toward a New Proposal 218 Conclusion 222 CONCLUSION 224 BIBLIOGRAPHY 226 VITA 232 vii LIST OF TABLES Table 1. Global Resource Consumption 131 viii LIST OF FIGURES Figure 1. The Intersection of the Harms Described by the Three Strands 165 Figure 2. World Maps with Nations Scaled to Reflect Carbon Emissions and Per Capita Mortality from Climate Change 176 Figure 3. The Intersection of the Convergence of the Harms Described by the Three Original Sub-arguments with the Harms Described by the Environmental Argument 179 Figure 4. Changes to the Intersection of the Harms Described by the Three Sub-arguments as Environmental Harms are Included 180 Figure 5. Projected Revenue Streams Resulting from the Implementation of the GRD 210 ix INTRODUCTION In December of 2004, a tsunami struck the coast of Indonesia and other nations, killing 230,000 people. The world responded quickly and generously, donating more than $11 billion.1 In January of 2010, a 7.0 magnitude earthquake struck Haiti, also killing 230,000.2 Less than a week later, the American Red Cross had collected $105 million in individual donations, $22 million of which came via their new ‗text to donate‘ system.3 Eventually the international response to the earthquake totaled $10 billion in pledges and donations from governments and international organizations.4 In each of the weeks following the 2004 tsunami and 2010 earthquake, more people around the world died of (other) poverty-related causes than died as a result of either disaster. In the five years between the 2004 tsunami and the 2010 earthquake, some 90 million people died from poverty related causes. I am by no means suggesting that these events are not tragic, but their scale is miniscule in comparison to the horrors of world poverty, which kills some 50,000 people every day. Those dying in this way are human beings: they are individuals with families and aspirations. Many of them are children, and almost all of them could be saved. 1 Tom Wright, ―UN Failed to Coordinate Tsunami Relief, Red Cross Report Says,‖ New York Times, October 6, 2005, http://www.nytimes.com/2005/10/05/world/asia/05iht-relief.html. 2 Henry Fountain, ―In Studying Haiti, a New Angle on an Earthquake‘s Intensity,‖ New York Times, October 18, 2010, http://www.nytimes.com/2010/10/19/science/19quake.html. 3 Stephanie Strom, ―A Deluge of Donations via Text Messages,‖ New York Times, January 9 2010, http://www.nytimes.com/2010/01/19/us/19charity.html. 4 Neil MacFarquhar, ―Skepticism on Pledges for Haiti,‖ New York Times, March 31, 2010, http://www.nytimes.com/2010/04/01/world/americas/01haiti.html. 1 2 The project that follows is about the nature of our obligations to the world‘s worst off people: more specifically, it is an assessment of Thomas Pogge‘s argument that we have substantial negative duties to the extremely impoverished. Pogge‘s understanding of our duties in this area stands in marked contrast to most mainstream views. Some would say that we have no relationship to these people; their dying may be a tragedy, but it is the unfortunate result of an overpopulated world and is not anything that we can be held accountable for. Others would say that only the leaders of the nations in which the impoverished live might be responsible: they have developed national institutions that benefit themselves instead of their people, and they have forged a path of corruption instead of creating the structures necessary for success. Those who do ascribe us responsibility tend to focus on our positive duties to the worst off: when we hear news of an event of any sort that kills 50,000 people, we have a natural inclination to aid those who have survived. Pogge makes a stronger claim: poverty is something that we contribute to. According to this view, each and every one of us is taking part in causing the deaths of 18 million people every year.
Recommended publications
  • Effective Altruism William Macaskill and Theron Pummer
    1 Effective Altruism William MacAskill and Theron Pummer Climate change is on course to cause millions of deaths and cost the world economy trillions of dollars. Nearly a billion people live in extreme poverty, millions of them dying each year of easily preventable diseases. Just a small fraction of the thousands of nuclear weapons on hair‐trigger alert could easily bring about global catastrophe. New technologies like synthetic biology and artificial intelligence bring unprece­ dented risks. Meanwhile, year after year billions and billions of factory‐farmed ani­ mals live and die in misery. Given the number of severe problems facing the world today, and the resources required to solve them, we may feel at a loss as to where to even begin. The good news is that we can improve things with the right use of money, time, talent, and effort. These resources can bring about a great deal of improvement, or very little, depending on how they are allocated. The effective altruism movement consists of a growing global community of peo­ ple who use reason and evidence to assess how to do as much good as possible, and who take action on this basis. Launched in 2011, the movement now has thousands of members, as well as influence over billions of dollars. The movement has substan­ tially increased awareness of the fact that some altruistic activities are much more cost‐effective than others, in the sense that they do much more good than others per unit of resource expended. According to the nonprofit organization GiveWell, it costs around $3,500 to prevent someone from dying of malaria by distributing bed­ nets.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Academics Should Join to Stand Against Poverty Thomas Pogge and Luis Cabrera*
    ACADEMICS STAND AGAINST POVERTY Outreach, Impact, Collaboration: Why Academics Should Join to Stand Against Poverty Thomas Pogge and Luis Cabrera* t is a typical late afternoon in the Timarpur neighborhood, lying just across the Mahatma Gandhi Marg ring road from the University of Delhi North I Campus. Families gather outside one- and two-room brick living quarters, many of which have only a single draped cloth serving as the front wall. Other homes are made of found materials: cloth or plastic bound over slim wooden poles; a mishmash of blankets, boards, and corrugated metal for walls; metal or blue plastic tarpaulins weighted against the wind with stones and bricks for roofs. A boy of perhaps four fills a bucket at the single communal tap serving a dozen families and wobbles up a set of stairs, sloshing out water with each step. Another child, younger, plays quietly beside a woman sleeping on the pavement under a shelter of plastic and burlap bags. On the street, cycle rickshaw drivers—among the hundreds of thousands of laborers in the city who toil for often less than $ per day—strain as they pedal as many as four passengers or enormous loads of cardboard, rice, build- ing materials, or scrap metal along the margins of the street. They are cut off repeatedly by scooters, motorcycles, cars, buses, and large trucks, all incessantly honking warnings to one another. Across the street from the make- shift housing rise four-story apartment buildings. Air conditioners protrude from the neat plaster exterior of each unit. The complex is enclosed by tall *For helpful feedback, the authors would like to thank Ashok Acharya, Simon Caney, Onora O’Neill, Henry Shue, Gareth Wall, and the editors of this journal.
    [Show full text]
  • On Thomas Pogge’S Theory of Global Justice Why We Are Not Collectively Responsible for the Global Distribution of Benefits and Burdens Between Individuals
    DOI 10.1515/sats-2012-0012 sats 2012; 13(2): 207–222 Søren Flinch Midtgaard On Thomas Pogge’s Theory of Global Justice Why We Are Not Collectively Responsible for the Global Distribution of Benefits and Burdens between Individuals Abstract: Thomas Pogge’s ingenious and influential Rawlsian theory of global justice asserts that principles of justice such as the difference principle or, alter- natively, a universal criterion of human rights consisting of a subset of the prin- ciples of social justice apply to the global basic structure or economic order. Individuals that contribute to upholding the latter and benefit from it are, Pogge emphasizes, jointly responsible for its unjust features, not least for the fact that it, foreseeably and avoidably, affects up to 18 million people per year in such a way that they die. The paper mounts an immanent criticism against Pogge re- volving around his notion of collective responsibility. Especially, it argues that people cannot plausibly be held responsible for the distribution of benefits and burdens between individuals at the global level addressed by the kind of princi- ples Pogge invokes. They, and their governments, can, and should, however, be held responsible for the unjust features of the existing law of peoples or states. Keywords: Thomas Pogge; collective responsibility; principles of justice; princi- ples of the law of peoples Søren Flinch Midtgaard, Department of Political Science and Government, Aarhus University, Denmark, E-mail: [email protected] 1 Introduction1 Thomas Pogge argues
    [Show full text]
  • Liberal Cosmopolitanism and Economic Justice
    LIBERAL COSMOPOLITANISM AND ECONOMIC JUSTICE Katherine Erbeznik A Dissertation Submitted to the Graduate College of Bowling Green State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY December 2008 Committee: Steven Wall, Advisor Rachel A. Vannatta Graduate Faculty Representative Fred D. Miller, Jr. Ellen Frankel Paul Jeffrey Moriarty ii ABSTRACT Steven Wall, Advisor The goal of this dissertation is to answer two questions: Is global poverty unjust, such that coercive remedies may be imposed to alleviate it? And if so, does it justify global redistribution as a remedy? This dissertation takes up the same task initiated by Thomas Pogge in his 2002 book, World Poverty and Human Rights, in that the theory of justice from which these questions are answered assigns priority to negative duties of non-interference, rather than positive duties of assistance. More specifically, the theory of cosmopolitan justice underlying this evaluation is that of natural rights liberalism in the tradition of John Locke and Robert Nozick. According to this theory, global poverty could be unjust only if it was the result of violating individual rights. The first half of the dissertation explores the ways in which Pogge claims poverty is the result of rights violations – that such poverty is the result of a tainted global history and that the current distribution of global resources violates the right to fair shares, – ultimately denying that these ground the injustice of poverty. Instead, I argue that global poverty is unjust because a distribution of resources that contains severe poverty violates the minimal access proviso, a constraint on property rights that takes the deprivation of others to limit the property rights of some.
    [Show full text]
  • Revisiting Thomas Pogge's Dividend and Taxes to Help the Poor
    DOI: 10.34810/rljaev1n12id389303 4 REVISITING THOMAS POGGE’S DIVIDEND AND TAXES TO HELP THE POOR Hussain Ibn Ahmed M. Albahrani Abstract: The objective of this study is to verify the validity of Thomas Pogge’s Global Resources Dividend (henceforth, GRD) to al- leviate poverty in the world. The main question addressed in this paper is whether Pogge’s dividend and tax model has deficiencies, and if so, to identify these. Specifically, this paper discusses the validity of imposing a 1% tax on resources to help the poor, and the reasons for the selection of natural resources and not other sources of wealth. It also investigates whether Pogge’s idea can only be applied to a specific social group or it may be implemented universally. Did Pogge go far enough or did he set limits on his dividend? The central hypothesis in this paper is that Pogge’s dividend and tax may prove to be unfair and based on ethnocentric and unreasonable argu- ments. The study relies mainly on Pogge’s publications and, occasionally, includes economic data to examine Pogge’s dividend and taxes.1 The paper concludes that, even though Pogge recognises the role of colonialism in today’s poverty, his methodology for solving the problem fails to be fair for the following reasons: i. Being selective in terms of the tax percentage, that is, on what is to be taxed (i.e., natural resources, but not technology companies 1 Occasionally, economic data were extracted from papers and reports originally published in French, Spanish or Arabic. All translations are mine unless otherwise stated.
    [Show full text]
  • Freedom from Poverty As a Human Right: Who Owes What to the Very
    OXFORD Freedom from Poverty as a Human Right Who owes what to the very poor? Edited by Thomas Pogge The Philosopher’s Library series UNESCO Publishing FREEDOM FROM POVERTY AS A HUMAN RIGHT Freedom from Poverty as aHumanRight Who Owes What to the Very Poor? Edited by THOMAS POGGE 1 3 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford ox2 6dp Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide in Oxford New York Auckland Cape Town Dar es Salaam Hong Kong Karachi Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Nairobi New Delhi Shanghai Taipei Toronto With offices in Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France Greece Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal Singapore South Korea Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam Oxford is a registered trademark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries Published in the United States by Oxford University Press Inc., New York © UNESCO 2007 All rights reserved Published jointly in 2007 by the United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization (UNESCO), 7, place de Fontenoy, 75007 Paris, France, and Oxford University Press, Great Clarendon Street, Oxford ox2 6dp, United Kingdom The moral rights of the authors have been asserted Database right Oxford University Press (maker) First published 2007 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization.
    [Show full text]
  • Thomas Pogge and the Two Types of Libertarian
    Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy Summer 8-13-2013 Thomas Pogge And The Two Types Of Libertarian Zachary Hopper Georgia State University Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses Recommended Citation Hopper, Zachary, "Thomas Pogge And The Two Types Of Libertarian." Thesis, Georgia State University, 2013. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses/133 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Theses by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THOMAS POGGE AND THE TWO TYPES OF LIBERTARIAN by ZACHARY R. HOPPER Under the Direction of Andrew Altman ABSTRACT Thomas Pogge proposes the Health Impact Fund (HIF) as a realistic, feasible reform to the pharmaceutical patent regime that would incentivize pharmaceutical research and reward innovation for medicines based on their impact on the global burden of disease. Pogge advances a human rights-based argument to show that the HIF is a morally required addition to the current pharmaceutical patent regime. One objection to his human rights argument comes from a libertarian appeal to property rights. Pogge’s response to the libertarian leads to the counterintuitive conclusion that libertarianism is incompatible with any system of intellectual property rights. This paper will show how Pogge fails to distinguish between what I call status quo and revisionist libertarian positions on intellectual property. Making this distinction, I maintain, would strengthen the human rights argument and allow Pogge to avoid the counterintuitive conclusion of his response to the libertarian.
    [Show full text]
  • Whether and Where to Give1 (Forthcoming in Philosophy and Public Affairs)
    1 Whether and Where to Give1 (Forthcoming in Philosophy and Public Affairs) Theron Pummer University of St Andrews 1. The Ethics of Giving and Effective Altruism The ethics of giving has traditionally focused on whether, and how much, to give to charities helping people in extreme poverty.2 In more recent years, the discussion has increasingly focused on where to give, spurred by an appreciation of the substantial differences in cost- effectiveness between charities. According to a commonly cited example, $40,000 can be used either to help 1 blind person by training a seeing-eye dog in the United States or to help 2,000 blind people by providing surgeries reversing the effects of trachoma in Africa.3 Effective altruists recommend that we give large sums to charity, but by far their more central message is that we give effectively, i.e., to whatever charities would do the most good per dollar donated.4 In this paper, I’ll assume that it’s not wrong not to give bigger, but will explore to what extent it may well nonetheless be wrong not to give better. The main claim I’ll argue for here is that in many cases it would be wrong of you to give a sum of money to charities that do less good than others you could have given to instead, even if 1 I am extremely grateful to Derek Parfit, Roger Crisp, Jeff McMahan, and Peter Singer for extremely helpful feedback and encouragement. I am also very grateful to Johann Frick, Ulla Wessels, William MacAskill, Richard Arneson, Brian McElwee, Hilary Greaves, Elizabeth Ashford, Justin Snedegar, Ben Sachs, Sarah Broadie, Andreas Mogensen, Gulzaar Barn, Iason Gabriel, Carissa Véliz, Larry Temkin, Toby Ord, Teru Thomas, Owen Schaefer, Michelle Hutchinson, Caleb Ontiveros, Jesse Tomalty, Tom Ash, Kevin Wong, Caley Anderson, Tim Campbell, Farbod Akhlaghi-Ghaffarokh, Paul Woodruff, Ben Lange, Tina Rulli, Luc Bovens, Thomas Pogge, Francesca Minerva, Alberto Giubilini, Seth Lazar, Christian Barry, Felix Pinkert, Julian Savulescu, and the editors and two anonymous readers at Philosophy and Public Affairs for very helpful comments.
    [Show full text]
  • Bounded and Cosmopolitan Justice
    Review of International Studies (2000), 26, 45–60 Copyright © British International Studies Association Bounded and cosmopolitan justice ONORA O’NEILL1 1. The scope of justice Since antiquity justice has been thought of as a political or civic virtue, more recently as belonging in a ‘bounded society’,2 or as a primary task of states.3 All such views assume that the context of justice has boundaries, which demarcate those who are to render and to receive justice from one another from others who are to be excluded. Yet the view that justice is intrinsically bounded sits ill with the many claims that it is cosmopolitan, owed to all regardless of location or origin, race or gender, class or citizenship. The tension between moral cosmopolitanism and institu- tional anti-cosmopolitanism has been widely discussed over the last twenty years, but there is still a lot of disagreement about its proper resolution.4 Take, for example, the specific version of this thought that views justice as wholly internal to states. If we start with cosmopolitan principles, the justice of states will suffice for justice only if we can show that any system of just states will itself be just. 1 An earlier rather different version of this article appeared under the title ‘Civic and Cosmopolitan Justice’ as the Lindley Lecture for 2000, published by the Philosophy Department of the University of Kansas. 2 John Rawls relies on the idea of a bounded society throughout his work. References to Rawls’s writings cited here may be abbreviated in subsequent footnotes: A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971); ‘Themes in Kant’s Moral Philosophy’ (1989), in Collected Papers, Samuel Freeman (ed.), (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), pp.
    [Show full text]
  • Thomas Pogge's Theory of a Minimally Just Global Institutional
    Thomas Pogge’s Theory of a Minimally Just Global Institutional Order Bachelor Degree Project in Philosophy 15 ECTS Spring Term 2011 Astrid Paulsson Supervisors: Oskar Macgregor and Paavo Pylkkanen Examiner: Stefan Berglund Abstract The immense inequalities between the world’s poor and the world’s rich have compelled philosopher Thomas Pogge to develop a moral framework based on the Universal Declaration of Human Rights that challenges our most commonsense political moral views. Pogge disputes minimally and universally that we all have a negative duty not to harm so long as the harm is foreseeable and avoidable, rather than a positive duty to do well. Furthermore Pogge argues for an institutional view of negative duties flown from the fact that we all shape, uphold and impose institutions. With the help of three philosophers; Polly Vizard, Tim Hayward and Mathias Risse, I debate a number of their raised objections to Thomas Pogge’s theory of institutional global justice which all focus on the controversial causal claim that the present global order causes global poverty. The objections discussed are (a) Vizard’s scrutinizing of Pogge’s notion of responsibility (b) Hayward’s call for a full causal account of how the global order is harming the poor and (c) Risse’s alternative baseline for harm. I argue that although Pogge has some potential problems, he nevertheless is not contradicted by these objections to the extent that they themselves claim. I hold that the debated criticism appeals for further investigation and that in light of the arguments in this thesis we have a negative duty not to harm and a positive obligation to reform global unjust institutions in responding to global poverty.
    [Show full text]
  • JUSTICE: DOMESTIC and GOLBAL PERSPECTIVES – BLHV-275-01 Fall Term, 2014 Thursdays: 5:20 PM – 7:50 PM
    SYLLABUS JUSTICE: DOMESTIC AND GOLBAL PERSPECTIVES – BLHV-275-01 Fall Term, 2014 Thursdays: 5:20 PM – 7:50 PM INSTRUCTOR: Dr. Steven L. Snell OFFICE HOURS: Wednesdays: 2:00 PM -3:30 PM TELEPHONE: (646) 279-3214 E-MAIL: [email protected] COURSE DESCRIPTION: The course is designed to provide students with an overview of political theory relating to both domestic and global justice. First, it will examine various theories of domestic justice – including utilitarianism, possessive and choice-based libertarianism, and John Rawls’s theory of “justice-as-fairness”. The political theories contained in the readings express diverse (and in some cases highly controversial) concepts; these readings will comprise the first two parts of the course. In the third portion of the course, the focus shifts to global justice. Under what circumstances does a sovereign state have duties – negative or positive – to citizens of other nations? The course examines cosmopolitan theories of Charles Beitz and Thomas Pogge, critiques of these cosmopolitan theories by Thomas Nagel and Matthias Risse, and Rawls’s reasons for not extending his “two principles of justice” from the domestic context into the global context. Finally, the course will address practical proposals for holding multinational corporations responsible for complicity in abuses of human rights. TEXTS: The books for the course include: JOHN RAWLS, JUSTICE AS FAIRNESS: A RESTATEMENT (Erin Kelly editor, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2002) [$27.00] JOHN RAWLS, THE LAW OF PEOPLES (Cambridge,
    [Show full text]
  • Rawls' Methodological Blueprint
    Rawls’ Methodological Blueprint This is a pre-proofs, pre-copy-edited version. Please only cite the finished version, which is now published in the European Journal of Political Theory, and available at: http://ept.sagepub.com/content/early/2015/09/23/1474885115605260.abstract?rss=1 Abstract Rawls’ primary legacy is not that he standardised a particular view of justice, but rather that he standardised a particular method of arguing about it: justification via reflective equilibrium. Yet this method, despite such standardisation, is often misunderstood in at least four ways. First, we miss its continuity across his various works. Second, we miss the way in which it unifies other justificatory ideas, such as the ‘original position’ and an ‘overlapping consensus’. Third, we miss its fundamentally empirical character, given that it turns facts about the thoughts in our head into principles for the regulation of our political existence. Fourth, we miss some of the implications of that empiricism, including its tension with moral realism, relativism, and conservatism. Catherine Audard John Rawls, Stocksfield:Acumen, 2007. Samuel Freeman Rawls, London:Routledge, 2007. Paul Graham Rawls, Oxford:Oneworld, 2007. Percy B. Lehning John Rawls:An Introduction, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009. Jon Mandle & David A. Reidy (eds) A Companion to Rawls, Chichester: WileyBlackwell, 2014. Sebastiano Maffetone Rawls:An Introduction, Cambridge: Polity, 2010. Thomas Pogge John Rawls:His Life and Theory of Justice, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007. Introduction Rawls’ primary legacy is not his theory of justice, or even the debate he started about that concept, but rather the way in which that debate is carried out.
    [Show full text]