Distributed Cognition and Educational Practice

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Distributed Cognition and Educational Practice Jl. of Interactive Learning Research (2002) 13(1/2), 11-29 Distributed Cognition and Educational Practice ILIAS KARASAVVIDIS Department of Primary Teacher Education University of Crete Crete, Greece [email protected] The objective of this article is to present a brief historical over- view of ideas related to the distribution of cognition, offer a criti- cal appraisal, and outline some of the implications for the teach- ing and learning practice. First, the article provides a description of the mind as disembodied and disembedded, an image that has come to dominate western psychological thought. Second, the ar- ticle focuses on a set of ideas that challenge this notion of the mind as the locus of all cognition and intelligence: distributed cognition. The main tenets of distributed cognition in two psy- chological traditions, cognitive science and educational psycholo- gy, are presented. Third, the article considers another influential tradition that has significantly influenced the development of conceptions of distributed cognition: cultural-historical psychol- ogy. Fourth, distributed cognition ideas in cognitive science and educational psychology are critically appraised, so that similari- ties and differences are highlighted. The article concludes with a discussion of some of the implications of distributed cognition ideas for the teaching and learning practice. Socrates: What do you say of him, Meno? Were not all these answers giv- en out of his own head? Meno: Yes, they were all his own. Plato, Meno 12 Karasavvidis In one of the first recorded texts ever to address questions about the mind and the nature of knowledge, the Platonic dialogue Meno, Socrates in- vites Meno to observe his interaction with a young slave to decide on whether the slave is learning something from Socrates or is simply remem- bering known facts. Socrates makes a clear distinction between teaching and telling, considering, asking questions as distinct from teaching (“I am not teaching the boy anything, but only asking him questions”). In the course of the interaction, Socrates elicits certain knowledge of geometry from the slave. Meno is compelled to agree on that all the answers the slave gave were “given out of his own head” and further accepts this “spontaneous re- covery of knowledge” on the part of the slave as “recollection.” Even though Socrates merely aimed to show that recollection is a main source of knowledge, the dialogue is interesting in two main respects. First, it portrays a certain image of knowledge that is basically seen as being prior to exist- ence. Second, it delineates roles for the teacher and the learner, thereby pro- viding a model of cognition that can be utilized for instruction: teaching is presented as a process of eliciting knowledge from rather than presenting knowledge to the leaner. The present article focuses on the notion of cognition as distributed, a notion which is largely incompatible with Socrates’; interpretation that the answers the slave gave were “given out of his own head”, an interpretation that eventually has come to dominate western philosophical and psycholog- ical thought. By presenting and discussing views that support the notion of cognition as distributed, we will cast doubt on Socrates’ account that the slave was unassisted in arriving at the respective understanding of a geo- metrical fact. DISTRIBUTED COGNITION: A BRIEF HISTORICAL OVERVIEW Descartes carried forward this Platonic image of knowledge, thereby separat- ing the mind from the body and treating the mind as a self-standing, inde- pendently operating entity (Haugeland, 1998). While for the first few de- cades of psychology as a scientific discipline the mind was a legitimate ob- ject of study through introspection (cf. Cole’s, 1996, account of the second psychology), ushering in the behaviorist rein shifted the focus from the mind to objective behavior. Finally, the cognitive revolution of the ’50s re- stored the emphasis on the mind (Gardner, 1987). This evolution helps un- derstand why the mind has been treated as disembodied and disembedded, Distributed Cognition and Educational Practice 13 cognition being “in the head” as a property of the individual mind. Most of the current psychological research is either explicitly or implicitly based on this conception of cognition: cognitive processes are thought of as residing inside the head, their study is largely decontextualized, and the individual is used as the unit of analysis. For instance, the study of memory typically in- volves the examination of how individuals memorize a body of knowledge, how they encode it and integrate it into the existing knowledge structures, and how they retrieve it from those structures. The study of memory usually involves abstract tasks that are typically meaningless and likely to have very little connection with the real world. Finally, experiments are carried out in a “white room” where subjects are neither allowed to use any artifacts for re- membering (e.g., take notes as they would usually do in real life if they had to remember long meaningless strings of symbols) nor turn to others present in the environment (family members, partners, colleagues, friends) and use them as memory aids (e.g. asking a colleague in the office to remind them to do something as they would normally do in real life). This approach to the study of psychological processes is indicative of the tendency to think of the individual mind as the locus of all cognition and intelligence. In recent years, however, the mind-body dualism has been challenged both on philosophical (e.g., Winograd & Flores, 1987; Dreyfus & Dreyfus, 1990) and empirical grounds (Lave, 1988; Lave & Wenger, 1991; Hutchins, 1995a; Clark, 1997). Owing to such theoretical and empirical advances, new models of the mind and cognition have surfaced aiming to transcend the lim- itations of the dualistic model: situated cognition and distributed cognition. Our specific focus in this article will be on the latter. The idea that cognition is distributed is not new as Cole and Engestrom (1993) pointed out. The revived interest in the idea of cognition as distribut- ed has been attributed to; (a) the fact that people rely on computer artifacts to handle a wide variety of cognitive tasks, (b) the influence of cultural-his- torical psychology, and (c) the dissatisfaction with the notion of cognition as a property of the individual mind (Salomon, 1993a). In spite of this re- newed interest, it should be stressed that distributed cognition is neither a coherent theory nor a theoretical framework. Rather, it can be roughly de- scribed as a set of ideas about the nature of cognition and how it relates to fellow people and artifacts. We will present an integrated account of distrib- uted views of cognition in two different traditions: cognitive science (Hutch- ins, 1995a; Clark, 1997), and educational psychology (Salomon, 1993; Resnick, Levine, & Teasley, 1991). We will mainly focus on the volume by Salomon even though we refer to both volumes as falling under the category of educational psychology. It should be noted, however, that as opposed to 14 Karasavvidis the volume by Salomon, which is mainly addressing psychologists and edu- cators, the volume by Resnick, Levine and Teasley is much broader in scope covering areas such as psychology, education, conversation, language and communication (Schegloff, 1991; Heath, 1991; Rogoff, 1991; Hutchins, 1991; Resnick, 1991; Lave, 1991). Distributed Cognition in Cognitive Science While in traditional cognitive science cognition was considered to re- side in the head, recent approaches have moved the boundaries of cognition beyond the head (Norman, 1993; Hutchins, 1995a; Clark, 1997; Haugeland, 1998). The limitations of cognition as symbol-based computation are being highlighted by cognitive scientists who acknowledge that, for certain pur- poses, it is more appropriate to consider cognition (and intelligence) as a property of the whole system within which the individual functions rather than as something limited by the skin or skull (Clark, 1997; Greeno & Moore, 1993; Zhang & Norman, 1994; Norman, 1993; Hutchins, 1995a; Hutchins & Klausen, 1998). The image of mind that emerges is that of the leaky mind “es- caping its natural confines and mingling shamelessly with body and with the world” (Clark, 1997, p. 53). The appropriateness of using the individual as a unit of analysis is questioned, as it is maintained that the properties of individual cognition cannot be understood by simply studying individual cognition per se: rath- er, one should look at the whole system within which the person operates using various tools (Hutchins, 1995a; 1995b; Hutchins & Palen, 1998). By way of illustration, Hutchins (1995b) reached two main conclusions in his study of the memory processes in a commercial airline cockpit. First, memory functions are more a matter of interpretation of material symbols by the pi- lots than a matter of recollection of these symbols from their memories. Sec- ond, the memory of the cockpit is not made of individual pilot memory alone; focusing on individual pilot memory is insufficient in understanding the phe- nomenon of memory, because a considerable portion of the mnemonic func- tion takes place outside the individual pilot memory, namely outside of the individual pilot head. Hutchins (1995a) has studied how cognition makes use both of the nat- ural environment to offload some of the computational burden involved in calculations and specially designed artifacts which crystallize knowledge and practice thereby saving mental effort. Regarding the use of the environ- ment as a tool, Hutchins (1995a) provided a colorful example with his de- scription of Micronesian navigation, where navigators are sailing for several Distributed Cognition and Educational Practice 15 days out of the sight of land without using any typical western mechanical, electrical or magnetic resources. While at first sight it appears that they are poorly equipped for such a task, they nevertheless navigate very accurately: they know the bearings of the point of departure, the destination, and can indicate other islands off to the side of the course even though these are out of sight.
Recommended publications
  • Distributed Cognition As the Basis for Adaptation and Homeostasis In
    DISTRIBUTEDCOGNITIONASTHEBASISFORADAPTATION ANDHOMEOSTASISINROBOTS james henry stovold Doctor of Philosophy University of York Computer Science July 2016 ABSTRACT Many researchers approach the problem of building autonomous systems by looking to biology for inspiration. This has given rise to a wide-range of artificial systems mimicking their biological counterparts—artificial neural networks, artificial endocrine systems, and artificial musculoskeletal systems are prime examples. While these systems are succinct and work well in isolation, they can become cumbersome and complicated when combined to perform more complex tasks. Autonomous behaviour is one such complex task. This thesis considers autonomy as the complex behaviour it is, and proposes a bottom-up approach to developing autonomous beha- viour from cognition. This consists of investigating how cognition can provide new approaches to the current limitations of swarm systems, and using this as the basis for one type of autonomous behaviour: artificial homeostasis. Distributed cognition, a form of emergent cognition, is most often described in terms of the immune system and social insects. By taking inspiration from distributed cognition, this thesis details the development of novel algorithms for cognitive decision-making and emergent identity in leaderless, homogenous swarms. Artificial homeostasis is provided to a robot through an architecture that combines the cognitive decision-making algorithm with a simple associative memory. This architecture is used to demonstrate how a simple architecture can endow a robot with the capacity to adapt to an unseen environment, and use that information to proactively seek out what it needs from the environment in order to maintain its internal state. iii CONTENTS Abstract iii Table of Contents v List of Figures viii List of Tables xi List of Code Listings xii Acknowledgements xiii Declaration xv 1 introduction 1 1.1 Motivation .
    [Show full text]
  • GB-Human Computation Handbook
    From Human Computation to the Global Brain: the self-organization of distributed intelligence Francis Heylighen Global Brain Institute Vrije Universiteit Brussel Introduction The present chapter wishes to investigate the wider context of human computation, viewing it as merely one approach within the broad domain of distributed human-computer symbiosis. The multifarious developments in the “social” Internet have shown the great potential of large-scale col- laborative systems that involve both people and the various information and communication technologies (ICT) that process, store and distribute data. Here, I wish to explore this development in the broadest sense, as the self-organization of a distributed intelligence system at the planetary level—a phenomenon that has been called the “global brain”. To get there, I will first define and illustrate the fundamental concept of distributed intelligence. Then I will review how such an intelligent net- work emerges and grows through a combination of self-organization and design. Finally, I will sketch some potential applications of the anticipated global brain. Human-computer complementarity The rationale for human computation is that people have certain intrinsic skills that are difficult to reproduce in computer programs. A computation system that requires those skills must therefore include people as informa- tion-processing agents. Thus, in human computation, people and comput- ers are supposed to work together synergetically, the one complementing the other. The reason for this complementarity lies in the fact that humans and com- puters process information in very different ways. Computers excel at ac- curately storing and retrieving discrete items, such as numbers or strings of characters.
    [Show full text]
  • Supported Collaborative Learning at the Workplace
    Computer-Supported Collaborative Learning Series Sean P. Goggins Isa Jahnke Volker Wulf Editors Computer- Supported Collaborative Learning at the Workplace CSCL@Work Computer-Supported Collaborative Learning at the Workplace COMPUTER-SUPPORTED COLLABORATIVE LEARNING SERIES Series Editors: Christopher Hoadley, New York University, New York, USA Naomi Miyake, Chukyo University, Aichi, Japan Editorial Board: Michael Baker, CNRS & Université Lumière Lyon, France Carl Bereiter, Ontario Institute for Studies in Education, Canada Yrjö Engeström, University of Helsinki, Finland Gerhard Fischer, University of Colorado, U.S.A. H. Ulrich Hoppe, University of Duisburg-Essen, Germany Timothy Koschmann, Southern Illinois University, U.S.A. Claire O’Malley, University of Nottingham, U.K. Roy Pea, SRI International, U.S.A. Clotilde Pontecorovo, University ‘La Sapienza’, Italy Jeremy Roschelle, SRI International, U.S.A. Daniel Suthers, University of Hawaii, U.S.A. The Computer-Supported Collaborative Learning Book Series is for people working in the CSCL fi eld. The scope of the series extends to ‘collaborative learning’ in its broadest sense; the term is used for situations ranging from two individuals performing a task together, during a short period of time, to groups of 200 students following the same course and interacting via electronic mail. This variety also concerns the computational tools used in learning: elaborated graphical whiteboards support peer interaction, while more rudimentary textbased discussion forums are used for large group interaction. The series will integrate issues related to CSCL such as collaborative problem solving, collaborative learning without computers, negotiation patterns outside collaborative tasks, and many other relevant topics. It will also cover computational issues such as models, algorithms or architectures which support innovative functions relevant to CSCL systems.
    [Show full text]
  • Human Enhancement Technologies and Our Merger with Machines
    Human Enhancement and Technologies Our Merger with Machines Human • Woodrow Barfield and Blodgett-Ford Sayoko Enhancement Technologies and Our Merger with Machines Edited by Woodrow Barfield and Sayoko Blodgett-Ford Printed Edition of the Special Issue Published in Philosophies www.mdpi.com/journal/philosophies Human Enhancement Technologies and Our Merger with Machines Human Enhancement Technologies and Our Merger with Machines Editors Woodrow Barfield Sayoko Blodgett-Ford MDPI • Basel • Beijing • Wuhan • Barcelona • Belgrade • Manchester • Tokyo • Cluj • Tianjin Editors Woodrow Barfield Sayoko Blodgett-Ford Visiting Professor, University of Turin Boston College Law School Affiliate, Whitaker Institute, NUI, Galway USA Editorial Office MDPI St. Alban-Anlage 66 4052 Basel, Switzerland This is a reprint of articles from the Special Issue published online in the open access journal Philosophies (ISSN 2409-9287) (available at: https://www.mdpi.com/journal/philosophies/special issues/human enhancement technologies). For citation purposes, cite each article independently as indicated on the article page online and as indicated below: LastName, A.A.; LastName, B.B.; LastName, C.C. Article Title. Journal Name Year, Volume Number, Page Range. ISBN 978-3-0365-0904-4 (Hbk) ISBN 978-3-0365-0905-1 (PDF) Cover image courtesy of N. M. Ford. © 2021 by the authors. Articles in this book are Open Access and distributed under the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license, which allows users to download, copy and build upon published articles, as long as the author and publisher are properly credited, which ensures maximum dissemination and a wider impact of our publications. The book as a whole is distributed by MDPI under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons license CC BY-NC-ND.
    [Show full text]
  • Distributed Cognition in Classical Antiquity Reveals Diverse Notions of Distributed Cognition in the Early Greek and Roman Worlds
    Edited by Miranda Anderson, THE EDINBURGH HISTORY OF DISTRIBUTED COGNITION Douglas Cairns and THE EDINBURGH HISTORY OF DISTRIBUTED COGNITION Mark Sprevak ‘Once we look for it, distributed cognition is ubiquitous in classical antiquity. This book is a fascinating examination of the tools that made thinking easier and of the complex boundaries between the individual mind and the group.’ Ruth Scodel, University of Michigan Distributed Cognition in Classical Antiquity Reveals diverse notions of distributed cognition in the early Greek and Roman worlds This collection brings together eleven essays by international specialists in classical antiquity and provides a general and a period-specific introduction to distributed cognition and the cognitive humanities. The essays look at the ways in which cognition is explicitly or implicitly conceived of as distributed across brain, body and world in Greek and Roman technology, science and medicine, material culture, philosophy and literary studies. This exploratory work will be valuable across the humanities as it reveals the historical foundations of our theoretical and practical attempts to comprehend and optimise the distributed nature of human cognition. Miranda Anderson is a Research Fellow at the University of Edinburgh. Douglas Cairns is Professor of Classics in the University of Edinburgh. Mark Sprevak is Senior Lecturer in Philosophy at the University of Edinburgh. Distributed Cognition in Classical Antiquity Cover image: © János Kass, etching made for the illustration of Madách Imre’s Az ember tragédiája (Tragedy of Man), Egypt Cover design: Bekah Mackenzie and Stuart Dalziel Edited by Miranda Anderson, Douglas Cairns and Mark Sprevak 2 Distributed Cognition in Classical Antiquity Distributed Cognition in Classical Antiquity Edited by Miranda Anderson, Douglas Cairns and Mark Sprevak Edinburgh University Press is one of the leading university presses in the UK.
    [Show full text]
  • Distributed Cognitions GENERAL EDITORS: ROY PEA Psychological and Educational JOHN SEELY BROWN Considerations
    Learning in doing: Social, cognitive, and computational perspectives Distributed cognitions GENERAL EDITORS: ROY PEA Psychological and educational JOHN SEELY BROWN considerations The construction zone: Working for cognitive change in school Denis Newman, Peg Grrfin, and Michael Cole Plans and situated actions: The problem of human-machine Edited by interaction Lucy Suchman GAVRIEL SALOMON Situated learning: Legitimate peripheral participation University of Ha$, Israel Jean Lave and Etienne Wenger Street mathematics and school mathematics Terezinha Nunes, Anahria Dim Schliemann, and David William Carraher Understanding practice: Perspectives on activity and context Seth Chaiklin andJean Lave (editors) I943 CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS Published by the Press Syndicate of the University of Cambridge The Pin Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge CB2 1RI' 40 West 20th Street, New York, NY 10011-4211, USA Contents 10 Stamford Road, Oakleigh, Melbourne 3166, Australia 0 Cambridge Universify Press 1993 First phlished 1993 Printed in the United States of America Library of Conqcsr Catalo@n~-in-PublicdionData Disaibuted cognitions : psychological and educational considerations I / edited by Gavriel Salomon. List of contribufon page vii I p. cm. - (Learning in doing) Includes index. Series foreword ix ISBN 0-521-41406-7 (hard) xi 1. Cognition and culture. 2. Knowledge, Sociology of. 3. Cognition - Social aspects. 4. Learning. Psychology of - Social aswcts. I. Salomon. Gavriel. 11. Series. 1 A cultural-historical approach to distributed 92-41220 cognition CIP MICHAEL COLE AND YRJO ENGESTR~M A catalog record for this book is available from the British Library. 2 Practices of distributed intelligence and designs for education ISBN 0-521-41406-7 hardback ROY D. PEA 3 Person-plus: a distributed view of thinking and learning D.
    [Show full text]
  • The Emergence of Distributed Cognition: a Conceptual Framework
    submitted for Proceedings of Collective Intentionality IV, Siena (Italy), to be published as a special issue of Cognitive Systems Research The Emergence of Distributed Cognition: a conceptual framework Francis HEYLIGHEN, Margeret HEATH and Frank VAN OVERWALLE Vrije Universiteit Brussel, Pleinlaan 2, B-1050 Brussels, Belgium {fheyligh, mheath, fjvoverw}@vub.ac.be ABSTRACT: We propose a first step in the development of an integrated theory of the emergence of distributed cognition/extended mind. Distributed cognition is seen as the confluence of collective intelligence and “situatedness”, or the extension of cognitive processes into the physical environment. The framework is based on five fundamental assumptions: 1) groups of agents self-organize to form a differentiated, coordinated system, adapted to its environment, 2) the system co-opts external media for internal propagation of information, 3) the resulting distributed cognitive system can be modelled as a learning, connectionist network, 4) information in the network is transmitted selectively, 5) novel knowledge emerges through non-linear, recurrent interactions. The implication for collective intentionality is that such a self-organizing agent collective can develop “mental content” that is not reducible to individual cognitions. Extended Mind: collective intelligence and distributed cognition From a cybernetic perspective [Heylighen & Joslyn, 2001], a cognitive system cannot be understood as a discrete collection of beliefs, procedures, and/or modules. Cognition is a continuously evolving process which relates present perceptions via internal states to potential further perceptions and actions. It thus allows an agent to anticipate what may happen, adapt to changes in its environment, and moreover effect changes upon its environment [Kirsch & Maglio, 1994].
    [Show full text]
  • The Extended Mind
    2015 48th Hawaii International Conference on System Sciences New frontiers for Crowdsourcing: the Extended Mind Roger M. Whitaker, Martin Chorley, Stuart M. Allen School of Computer Science and Informatics, Cardiff University 5 The Parade, Roath, Cardiff, CF24 3AA, UK {r.m.whitaker, m.j.chorley, s.m.allen}@cs.cardiff.ac.uk Abstract well-established form of collective intelligence, that has emerged through a number of successful commericial We introduce the concept of extended mind crowd- platforms and become a viable way to conduct survey- sourcing (EMC) which capitalises on the way in which based research [2]. humans naturally extend their cognition into the envi- As technology is developing, new opportunities and ronment, using external objects such as smartphones applications for crowdsourcing are emerging. In par- and applications to augment their mental capacity. ticular discovery of collective human behaviour and This phenomenon means that human computation is inherent culture is becoming possible. Recent exam- embedded in data and devices, representing a new way ples include the characterisation of international eat- through which human cognition can be accessed for col- ing habits [3], the grand vision of the FuturICT initia- lective discoveries. We relate EMC to existing socio- tive [4] and discovery of correlations between personal- logical and psychological concepts and argue that it lies ity and decisions in the places that we visit [5]. These at the intersection of human computation, social com- developments are occurring hand-in-hand with the pro- puting and crowdsourcing. gression of technologies capable of capturing more and EMC is a way in which new problems and discov- more of our individual activity and cognition.
    [Show full text]
  • Fafnir – Nordic Journal of Science Fiction and Fantasy Research Journal.Finfar.Org
    ISSN: 2342-2009 Fafnir vol 1, iss 2, pages 23–40 Fafnir – Nordic Journal of Science Fiction and Fantasy Research journal.finfar.org Intuitive Technologies. Models of Posthuman Subjectivity in Simon Ings' Hot Head and Hotwire Kaisa Kortekallio Abstract: This article analyzes two novels by the British writer Simon Ings, Hot Head (1992) and Hotwire (1995), from perspectives provided by second-order systems theory, philosophy of neuroscience and posthumanist philosophy. In Ings' cyberpunk fiction, the use of a particular novum, a programmable cerebral tissue called “datafat”, enables elaborate experimentation on different theories of mind and matter. Due to this experimentation, Ings’ work is able to convey a conception of cognition as an emergent effect produced in material processes that are both human and non-human. Ings’ work asserts the human subject as a complex system in a complex technological ecology and, consequentially, presents us with a model for subjectivity that might be called “posthuman”. Keywords: Simon Ings, Hot Head, Hotwire, posthuman subjectivity, posthumanism, philosophy of neuroscience in literature, complex systems in literature Biography and contact info: Kaisa Kortekallio is a doctoral student in the Doctoral Programme for Philosophy, Arts and Society at the University of Helsinki. Kortekallio holds a Master’s degree in General Literature. “I know that the molecules in my body are traceable to phenomena in the cosmos. That excites me. That makes me want to grab people on the street and say: ‘Have you HEARD THIS?” – astrophysicist Neil deGrasse Tyson in a talk given at the Beyond Belief Conference, 2006 There is profound reconfiguration going on in scientifically oriented minds – reconfiguration of the models of human existence and practice.
    [Show full text]
  • Cognition, Distributed
    Cognition, Distributed Cognition, Distributed 1. Mind in Society For many people, distributed cognition means cog- Like all other branches of cognitive science, distributed nitive processes that are distributed across the mem- cognition seeks to understand the organization of bers of a social group (Salomon 1993). The fun- cognitive systems. Like most of cognitive science, it damental question here is how the cognitive processes takes cognitive processes to be those that are involved we normally associate with an individual mind can be in memory, decision making, inference, reasoning, implemented in a group of individuals? A wide range learning, and so on. Also following mainstream of disciplines in the social sciences has explored this cognitive science, it characterizes cognitive processes question. in terms of the propagation and transformation of Treating memory as a socially distributed cognitive representations. function has a long history in sociology and anthro- What distinguishes distributed cognition from other pology. Durkheim, and his students, especially approaches is the commitment to two related theo- Halbwachs (1925), maintained that memory could not retical principles. The first concerns the boundaries of even be coherently discussed as a property of an the unit of analysis for cognition. While boundaries isolated individual. Roberts (1964) proposed that are often a matter of tradition in a field, there are some social organization could be read as a sort of archi- general rules one can follow. Bateson (1972) says one tecture of cognition at the community level. He should bound the unit so that things are not left characterized the cognitive properties of a society (its inexplicable.
    [Show full text]
  • Music and the Transhuman Ear: Ultrasonics, Material Bodies, and the Limits of Sensation
    Music and the Transhuman Ear: Ultrasonics, Material Bodies, and the Limits of Sensation “We favor morphological freedom – the right to modify and enhance one’s body, cognition and emotions.” (Transhumanist declaration, 2012)1 “I am apt to think, if we knew what it was to be an angel for one hour, we should return to this world, though it were to sit on the brightest throne in it, with vastly more loathing and reluctance than we would now descend into a loathsome dungeon or sepulchre.” (George Berkeley, 1732)2 PART I The materialist turn When Voyager probes 1 and 2 left the earth’s orbit in 1977, the committee tasked with assembling cultural artifacts followed scientist Lewis Thomas’ advice to include recordings of J. S. Bach among the many musical samples. This, it seems, was the best way to open a conversation with an unknown non-human interlocutor, wherein exchanges may be spaced hundreds of years apart. Many styles and genres were committed to the golden discs, but Thomas worried that by broadcasting Bach, the human race might be guilty of bragging to aliens: “we would be bragging, of course,” he admitted in 1972, “but it is surely excusable to put the best possible face on at the beginning of such an acquaintance.”3 His statement makes telling assumptions. To take one example, the three-voice C-major fugue Glenn Gould recorded (WTC, Book II) matches humans’ ability at auditory streaming, which, as David Huron has shown, tends to max out at around three streams, after which “confusions [over contrapuntal lines] become commonplace.”4 It would seem that part of the effect of Bach’s 1 Various, “Transhumanist Declaration,” The Transhumanist Reader, ed.
    [Show full text]
  • CSCL Proceedings Bleed Front 2
    Social Interaction, Constructivism and their Application within (CS)CL Theories Christian Hartmann, Jennifer Charlotte Angersbach and Nikol Rummel [email protected], [email protected], [email protected] Institute of Educational Research, Ruhr-Universität Bochum Abstract: We argue that the diversity of theories underlying CSCL research and the dispute concerning the distinction between the terms cooperation and collaboration may be explained (at least in part) by the variability of assumptions concerning the role of social interaction for individual learning. In this paper we identify different roles ascribed to social interaction in theories of learning and attempt to link them to different forms of constructivism in order to categorize theoretical conceptualizations of (CS)CL. This categorization may provide a starting point for developing a framework that enables consolidating various theoretical points of view. Keywords: cooperation, collaboration, constructivism, social interaction, learning theories, theoretical framework Introduction The field of Computer-Supported Collaborative Learning (CSCL) is influenced by several scientific disciplines (e.g. psychology, sociology, philosophy, computer science). Therefore CSCL research builds upon a variety of different theoretical points of view (Stahl, 2013). The phenomena that lie at the heart of CSCL research comprise social interaction and learning in the context of information technology (Ludvigsen & Mørch, 2010). To date, no single, overarching theory or paradigm is able to explain the relationship between those terms (or concepts) comprehensively (Goldbeck & El-Moslimany, 2013). We argue that a potential reason for this may be that there is no clear and universally valid definition of the concepts social interaction and learning. Some approaches appear to be compatible, while others seem incommensurable as they diverge concerning central assumptions concerning the nature of human cognition and social interaction.
    [Show full text]