Duress, Deception and the Validity of a Promise David Owens an Invalid

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Duress, Deception and the Validity of a Promise David Owens an Invalid Duress, Deception and the Validity of a Promise David Owens An invalid promise is one whose breach does not wrong the promisee. I describe two different accounts of why duress and deception invalidate promises. According to the fault account duress and deception invalidate a promise just when it was wrong for the promisee to induce the promisor to promise in that way. According to the injury account, duress and deception invalidate a promise just when by inducing the promise in that way the promisee wrongs the promisor. I demonstrate that the injury account is superior. I then argue that in this respect promising is like any exercise of a normative power. I conclude by distinguishing two theories of promissory obligation, a widely held view which I call the information interest theory and an alternative which I call the authority interest theory. I argue that the points established earlier support the authority interest theory over its rival. A highwayman, finding an inadequate amount of money on his victim, forces them to promise to provide more once they are released. Here the victim does make a promise, that is they express an intention to undertake an obligation to furnish the highwayman with more money. Nevertheless, the law and common opinion would agree that the victim is not bound by their promise. Nor would he be bound if he promised to buy a second hand car from a dealer and subsequently discovered that the dealer had tampered with the mileage clock. In these cases duress and deception invalidate the promise. Promissory obligation has long been a central topic in moral and political philosophy and thus the topic of promissory invalidation has also attracted philosophical attention.1 But many have wondered whether there is anything of philosophical interest to be said about how and why duress and deception invalidate. Hume for one alleged that when thinking about such matters we draw distinctions which reflection cannot justify and he uses this as evidence of the conventional nature of promissory obligation (Hume 1740, Bk. 3, Pt. 2, Sect. 5). Other writers from 1 Legal theorists have written extensively on the topic of contractual validity and though I have found these writings extremely helpful and shall refer to several of them, I shall not discuss them directly. This is because legal theorists are concerned with contracts - reciprocal agreements where both parties expect to get something out of the deal - and treat unilateral or gratuitous promises as at best peripheral cases. Their main interest is in the remedies for breach of contract, in how costs should be allocated once a contract has been breached. I focus on the question ‘when does the breach of a promise wrong the promisee?’ and I shall discuss the remedies for breach of promise only in passing. Grotius through Sidgwick down to the present day have found only confusion in this area, inviting us to infer that one can settle when promise is void for duress or misrepresentation only in the context of a particular legal system.2 It would be indeed foolish to suppose that the details of what constitutes, say, a valid marriage contract can be worked out a priori. But moral reasoning might still provide some insight into promissory validity and, in particular, into why duress and deception tend to invalidate promises. And this might cast some light on the nature of promissory obligation as such. At least that is my hope. I shall proceed as follows. In the first section, I focus on a specific notion of invalidation according to which an invalid promise is one breach of which does not wrong the promisee. In the second section, I introduce two accounts of how force and fraud invalidate promises: the fault account and the injury account. Both share the idea that force and fraud invalidate because they are wrongs but they interpret this idea in quite different ways. I argue that the injury account is superior and in the third section, I apply this account to the exercise of other normative powers like giving and consenting. In the final section, I distinguish two different theories of promissory obligation - the familiar information interest theory and the less familiar authority interest theory - and suggest that the truth of the injury account supports the latter. 1. What is invalidation? What is it for a promise to be invalid? My answer is simple: a promise is invalid when the promisor would not wrong the promisee just by breaking their promise. To explain that simple answer, I must separate wronging someone or injuring them on the one hand from doing something wrong or being at fault on the other. For an invalid promise needs to be distinguished from a promise that the promisor is justified in breaking. Wronging someone by breaking a valid promise can be the right thing to do. 2 After considering exactly when promises are invalidated by ‘force or fraud’, Sidgwick concludes that ‘on all these points Common Sense seems doubtful’ (Sidgwick 1874, p. 306). Sidgwick’s scepticism is endorsed by (Atiyah 1981, p. 25). Grotius notes ‘a great variety of opinions’ on these points (Grotius 1625, Bk 2, Ch. 11, Sect, 7). Several writers have maintained that whether an action wrongs someone and whether that action is justified are two quite different questions.3 One might say this because one thought that we are sometimes justified in doing things for which there is no moral justification. But I am envisioning the rather different possibility that the right thing to do even from the moral point of view is to wrong someone, to injure them, perhaps by violating some right of theirs. For example, we are sometimes entitled to damage the property or harm the persons of others and in so doing we normally wrong them. What is the precise significance of this wronging? If the injury here were a legal wrong, the legal consequence would be compensation of some sort. But it is less clear what reaction fits a moral injury, especially where the injury’s infliction is justified. Compensation is often out of place and even where compensation suits, it is as an expression of other more basic reactions.4 I am inclined to think that, in at least some cases, guilt, remorse, apology, requests for forgiveness are appropriate responses on the part of the perpetrator even though what they have done was justified (Marcus 1996, pp. 31-3). Conversely, blame and resentment, as well as forgiveness and offers of reconciliation on the victim’s part are frequently not out of place. I shall support these claims by describing situations (of justified breach of promise) in which such responses are quite common, a fact which places the burden of proof on anyone who thinks them irrational or at least inappropriate. But these scenarios are not meant to settle the matter. What I need both to elucidate the notion of promissory invalidation and to formulate my own theory of it is the idea that whether one wrongs someone by breaking a promise and whether the breach is justified are two different things. Others can make this distinction in their own way without rejecting the rest of what I say.5 3 (Gardner 2005, pp. 54-7) argues that the law of both tort and contract require the idea of a wrong that is nevertheless justified. See also (Thomson 1990, pp. 100-3). 4 For example, offering compensation for breach of promise would often be rather odd. How do you compensate someone for failing to turn up to their wedding? If you do send them a gift in an effort to make it up to them, the gesture will be well received only in so far as the gift is taken to be an expression of some feeling (not just the discharge of a debt.) (Williams 1982, pp. 27-30). There are also cases in which the promisee very much wants the promise to be kept but actually benefits from its breach. This hardly invalidates the promise but it does make compensation inappropriate. 5 Philosophers who try to make this distinction without supposing that justifiable wronging is blameworthy include Raz (2004, pp. 189-93 and 1986, pp. 359-66) and Thomson (1990, Ch. 3). In my view, both Raz and Thomson make too much of compensation. If you fail to turn up to someone’s wedding, attention will focus on whether the happy couple are entitled to resent your absence and not on, for example, whether you should pay them for the wasted place at the wedding breakfast. One is often justified in breaking a promise, for example when some more weighty duty (e.g. a more important promise) turns out to conflict with it in a way which could not have been anticipated when the promise was made. But the fact that one is justified in breaking the promise is perfectly consistent with the fact that one is wronging the promisee, that one is failing to discharge an obligation to them. We often feel guilty about such a breach of promise, apologise for the breach and seek to make it up to the promisee, even while continuing to believe that breaching this promise was, in the circumstances, the right thing to do. 6 And the guilt the wronger feels here is something more than the regret a decent person feels whenever they must cause harm, or allow someone to be harmed: there is an injury, not just a harm. Suppose I have a limited supply of a life-saving drug and must decide who is to live and who is to die.
Recommended publications
  • North Dakota Century Code T14c02
    CHAPTER 14-02 PERSONAL RIGHTS 14-02-01. General personal rights. Every person, subject to the qualifications and restrictions provided by law, has the right of protection from bodily restraint or harm, from personal insult, from defamation, and from injury to the person's personal relations. 14-02-02. Defamation classified. Defamation is effected by: 1. Libel; or 2. Slander. 14-02-03. Civil libel defined. Libel is a false and unprivileged publication by writing, printing, picture, effigy, or other fixed representation to the eye, which exposes any person to hatred, contempt, ridicule, or obloquy, or which causes the person to be shunned or avoided, or which has a tendency to injure the person in the person's occupation. 14-02-04. Civil slander defined. Slander is a false and unprivileged publication other than libel, which: 1. Charges any person with crime, or with having been indicted, convicted, or punished for crime; 2. Imputes to the person the present existence of an infectious, contagious, or loathsome disease; 3. Tends directly to injure the person in respect to the person's office, profession, trade, or business, either by imputing to the person general disqualifications in those respects which the office or other occupation peculiarly requires, or by imputing something with reference to the person's office, profession, trade, or business that has a natural tendency to lessen its profits; 4. Imputes to the person impotence or want of chastity; or 5. By natural consequence causes actual damage. 14-02-05. Privileged communications. A privileged communication is one made: 1. In the proper discharge of an official duty; 2.
    [Show full text]
  • Survival of Claims for and Against Executors and Administrators Alvin E
    Kentucky Law Journal Volume 19 | Issue 3 Article 1 1931 Survival of Claims For and Against Executors and Administrators Alvin E. Evans University of Kentucky Follow this and additional works at: https://uknowledge.uky.edu/klj Part of the Estates and Trusts Commons Right click to open a feedback form in a new tab to let us know how this document benefits you. Recommended Citation Evans, Alvin E. (1931) "Survival of Claims For and Against Executors and Administrators," Kentucky Law Journal: Vol. 19 : Iss. 3 , Article 1. Available at: https://uknowledge.uky.edu/klj/vol19/iss3/1 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Journals at UKnowledge. It has been accepted for inclusion in Kentucky Law Journal by an authorized editor of UKnowledge. For more information, please contact [email protected]. KENTUCKY LAW JOURNAL Volume XIX MIARCH, 1931 Number 3. SURVIVAL OF CLAIMS FOR AND AGAINST EXECUTORS AN[Y ADMINISTRATORS The unfortunate condition of our law regarding the sur- vival of claims both against and in favor of the personal repre- sentative has been frequently remarked upon.' It is arguable that a policy which would support a general survival of claims in favor of a personal representative would not exist where the situation is reversed, and the wrongdoer has died in the lifetime of the claimant. The action of trespass was related to criminal appeals, and since a man cannot be punished in his grave, this action did not survive under the common law. To the extent then, that a recovery is vindictive, the maxim that personal actions die with the person might be held to support a desirable policy.
    [Show full text]
  • The Purpose of Compensatory Damages in Tort and Fraudulent Misrepresentation
    LENS FINAL 12/1/2010 5:47:02 PM Honest Confusion: The Purpose of Compensatory Damages in Tort and Fraudulent Misrepresentation Jill Wieber Lens∗ I. INTRODUCTION Suppose that a plaintiff is injured in a rear-end collision car accident. Even though the rear-end collision was not a dramatic accident, the plaintiff incurred extensive medical expenses because of a preexisting medical condition. Through a negligence claim, the plaintiff can recover compensatory damages based on his medical expenses. But is it fair that the defendant should be liable for all of the damages? It is not as if he rear-ended the plaintiff on purpose. Maybe the fact that defendant’s conduct was not reprehensible should reduce the amount of damages that the plaintiff recovers. Any first-year torts student knows that the defendant’s argument will not succeed. The defendant’s conduct does not control the amount of the plaintiff’s compensatory damages. The damages are based on the plaintiff’s injury because, in tort law, the purpose of compensatory damages is to make the plaintiff whole by putting him in the same position as if the tort had not occurred.1 But there are tort claims where the amount of compensatory damages is not always based on the plaintiff’s injury. Suppose that a defendant fraudulently misrepresents that a car for sale is brand-new. The plaintiff then offers to purchase the car for $10,000. Had the car actually been new, it would have been worth $15,000, but the car was instead worth only $10,000. As they have for a very long time, the majority of jurisdictions would award the plaintiff $5000 in compensatory damages 2 based on the plaintiff’s expected benefit of the bargain.
    [Show full text]
  • Torts - Interference with Or Injuries in Personal Relations - Malicious Inducement of Breach of Marriage Promise
    North Dakota Law Review Volume 29 Number 3 Article 8 1953 Torts - Interference with or Injuries in Personal Relations - Malicious Inducement of Breach of Marriage Promise Douglas Birdzell Follow this and additional works at: https://commons.und.edu/ndlr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Birdzell, Douglas (1953) "Torts - Interference with or Injuries in Personal Relations - Malicious Inducement of Breach of Marriage Promise," North Dakota Law Review: Vol. 29 : No. 3 , Article 8. Available at: https://commons.und.edu/ndlr/vol29/iss3/8 This Case Comment is brought to you for free and open access by the School of Law at UND Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in North Dakota Law Review by an authorized editor of UND Scholarly Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. NORTH DAKOTA LAW REVIEW the coal as well as in the coal itself, yet recognized as indisputable that upon exhaustion of the coal the space would revert to the grantor. If, as contended, the conveyance of the coal carries with it the containing chamber, why should the ownership of the space terminate as soon as all the coal is mined? The rational view would be that the reverter takes place because the grantee has never at any time had a corporeal estate in the containing walls. The con- veyance carries an estate in the coal only, with an easement in the walls for support and removal. s In the exercise of that easement the grantee has no right to put an additional burden upon the servient estate by using it for mining of coal in adjoining tracts.
    [Show full text]
  • Alienation of Affection Suits in Connecticut a Guide to Resources in the Law Library
    Connecticut Judicial Branch Law Libraries Copyright © 2006-2020, Judicial Branch, State of Connecticut. All rights reserved. 2020 Edition Alienation of Affection Suits in Connecticut A Guide to Resources in the Law Library This guide is no longer being updated on a regular basis. But we make it available for the historical significance in the development of the law. Table of Contents Introduction .................................................................................................... 3 Section 1: Spousal Alienation of Affection ............................................................ 4 Table 1: Spousal Alienation of Affections in Other States ....................................... 8 Table 2: Brown v. Strum ................................................................................... 9 Section 2: Criminal Conversation ..................................................................... 11 Table 3: Criminal Conversation in Other States .................................................. 14 Section 3: Alienation of Affection of Parent or Child ............................................ 15 Table 4: Intentional Infliction of Emotional Distress ............................................ 18 Table 5: Campos v. Coleman ........................................................................... 20 Prepared by Connecticut Judicial Branch, Superior Court Operations, Judge Support Services, Law Library Services Unit [email protected] Alienation-1 These guides are provided with the understanding that they represent
    [Show full text]
  • Breach of Promise to Marry and Return of Engagement Ring and Courtship Gifts a Guide to Resources in the Law Library
    Connecticut Judicial Branch Law Libraries Copyright © 2001-2021, Judicial Branch, State of Connecticut. All rights reserved. 2021 Edition Breach of Promise to Marry and Return of Engagement Ring and Courtship Gifts A Guide to Resources in the Law Library Table of Contents Introduction .................................................................................................... 3 Section 1: Breach of Promise to Marry and Return of Engagement Ring and Courtship Gifts ............................................................................................................... 4 Table 1: No Fault Approach........................................................................... 20 Figure 1: Substituted Complaint .................................................................... 22 Figure 2: Amendment to first count of plaintiff’s complaint ............................... 25 See Also: Alienation of Affection Suits in Connecticut Replevin in Connecticut Prepared by Connecticut Judicial Branch, Superior Court Operations, Judge Support Services, Law Library Services Unit [email protected] Breach of Promise to Marry – 1 These guides are provided with the understanding that they represent only a beginning to research. It is the responsibility of the person doing legal research to come to his or her own conclusions about the authoritativeness, reliability, validity, and currency of any resource cited in this research guide. View our other research guides at https://jud.ct.gov/lawlib/selfguides.htm This guide links to advance
    [Show full text]
  • Domestic Relations: Avoidance of Anti-Heartbalm Legislation by the Action of Fraud Allan B
    Hastings Law Journal Volume 8 | Issue 2 Article 4 1-1957 Domestic Relations: Avoidance of Anti-Heartbalm Legislation by the Action of Fraud Allan B. O'Connor Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.uchastings.edu/hastings_law_journal Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Allan B. O'Connor, Domestic Relations: Avoidance of Anti-Heartbalm Legislation by the Action of Fraud, 8 Hastings L.J. 210 (1957). Available at: https://repository.uchastings.edu/hastings_law_journal/vol8/iss2/4 This Note is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Journals at UC Hastings Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Hastings Law Journal by an authorized editor of UC Hastings Scholarship Repository. NOTES DOMESTIC RELATIONS: AVOIDANCE OF ANTI-HEARTBALM LEGISLATION BY THE ACTION OF FRAUD The heartbalm actions of alienation of affections, criminal conversation, seduc- tion and breach of promise of marriage were highly criticized because of their misuse as a means of extortion. This criticism by both press and law reviews led many states to abolish these actions. The prime target of this criticism was the action of breach of promise. When the first anti-heartbalm statutes were passed, it was predicted that these statutes might be circumvented by actions brought in fraud and/or deceit.' However, until the decision in Langley v. Schumacker,2 all the courts which have construed these statutes have consistently denied relief upon such theories,3 and the rule evolved that: " . .. [W]here an action stems from, or arises out of, a breach of a marriage contract, the consequences of the statute abolishing actions for such a cause may not be avoided ' 4 by bringing an action in tort for fraud or deceit.
    [Show full text]
  • A Promise-Based Defense of Wilfull Breach Doctrine Steve Thel Fordham University School of Law, [email protected]
    Fordham Law School FLASH: The Fordham Law Archive of Scholarship and History Faculty Scholarship 2008 Wilfulness versus Expectation: A Promise-Based Defense of Wilfull Breach Doctrine Steve Thel Fordham University School of Law, [email protected] Peter Siegelman University of Connecticut School of Law Follow this and additional works at: http://ir.lawnet.fordham.edu/faculty_scholarship Part of the Contracts Commons, and the Legal Ethics and Professional Responsibility Commons Recommended Citation Steve Thel and Peter Siegelman, Wilfulness versus Expectation: A Promise-Based Defense of Wilfull Breach Doctrine, 107 Mich. L. Rev. 1517 (2008-2009) Available at: http://ir.lawnet.fordham.edu/faculty_scholarship/469 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by FLASH: The orF dham Law Archive of Scholarship and History. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of FLASH: The orF dham Law Archive of Scholarship and History. For more information, please contact [email protected]. WILLFULNESS VERSUS EXPECTATION: A PROMISOR-BASED DEFENSE OF WILLFUL BREACH DOCTRINE Steve Thel* Peter Siegelman** Willful breach doctrine should be a major embarrassmentto con- tract law. If the default remedy for breach is expectation damages designed to put the injured promisee in the position she would have been in if the contract had been performed, then the promi- sor's behavior-the reasonfor the breach-looks to be irrelevant in assessing damages. And yet the cases are full of references to "willful" breaches, which seem often to be treated more harshly than ordinary ones based on the promisor's bad/willful conduct.
    [Show full text]
  • FILED Court of Appeals Division II State of Washington 713112019 12:20 PM
    FILED Court of Appeals Division II State of Washington 713112019 12:20 PM NO. ----97503-5 Court of Appeals No. 51055-3-II IN THE SUPREME COURT FOR THE STA TE OF WASHINGTON JODI BRUGH, an individual, Respondent, V. PUN-T ASTIC RIDES CO., an Oregon corporation; MIDWAY RIDES LLC, a Washington limited liability company; JOHN DOE MANUFACTURER, an unknown entity, Petitioners. PETITION FOR REVIEW Patricia K. Buchanan, WSBA No. 19892 Tim T. Parker, WSBA No. 43674 Nicholas A. Carlson, WSBA No. 48311 Attorneys for Petitioners PATTERSON BUCHANAN FOBES & LEITCH, INC., P.S. 2112 Third Avenue, Suite 500 Seattle, WA 98121 Tel. 206.462.6700 TABLE OF CONTENTS Page TABLE OF AUTHORITIES .................................................................. iii I. INTRODUCTION .......................................................................... 1 II. IDENTITY OF PETITIONERS ................................................... 2 III. COURT OF APPEALS' DECISION ........................................... 2 IV. ISSUES PRESENTED FOR REVIEW ........................................ 2 V. STATEMENT OF THE CASE ..................................................... 3 A. Procedural History................................................................ 3 B. The Court of Appeals' Reasoning ....................................... 3 C. Relevant Facts Ignored by the Court of Appeals ............... 5 i. Did Brugh have preexisting trauma? ................................ 5 ii. Did Brugh suffer trauma after the roller coaster? ............ 6 D. Injury from Preexisting Conditions
    [Show full text]
  • Engagement Cancellation and Its Legal Implication in Malaysia (Woman‘S Rights Perspective)
    98 Engagement Cancellation and Its Legal Implication In Malaysia (Woman‘s Rights Perspective) Uswatul Fikriyah Sharia Faculty State Islamic University Maulana Malik Ibrahim Malang [email protected] Abstact: This article aims to describe the legal implication of engagement cancellation in Malaysia and to analyze the woman‘s rights protection aspect in Act 303 Islamic Family Law Federal Territory 1984 in Malaysia. This article based on library research focuses on regulation Islamic Family Law Federal Territory Act 303 year 1984 of Malaysia, particularly concerning on about betrothal or Engagement. The result of this study show that the implication of engagement itself could open the opportunities to both of bride and groom to understand and know each other. The implications of engagement cancellation that can be taken from section 15 Act 303 Islamic Family Law Federal Territory. In Islamic family law in Malaysia especially Act 303 Federal Territory Islamic Family Law 1984 women have rights in accordance with their position, namely in the form of rights before marriage, the rights within marriage and the last is the rights after divorce. Women's rights protection aspects contained in the Act 303 Islamic Family Law Federal Territory generally not only in case of engagement cancellation or breach of promise of marriage (bethrothal) but in all the rights of women in marriage. It has the purpose to protect women's rights. Keywords: engagement, family law, Malaysia Introduction Process of marriage in Malaysia is generally undertaken with various accompanying customs. The customs are acceptable in Islam as something good and reasonable. It provides many benefits such as peminangan or engagement ceremony procession.
    [Show full text]
  • 1. This Court Has Diversity Jurisdiction Over Plaintiff's Claim Against Weiderhold Since She Is a Citizen of Pennsylvania and He Is a Citizen of Virginia
    IN THE UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT FOR THE EASTERN DISTRICT OF PENNSYLVANIA SUSAN ELAINE SMITH : CIVIL ACTION : v. : : THE NATIONAL RAILROAD PASSENGER : CORPORATION ("AMTRAK"), et al. : NO. 98-2816 MEMORANDUM Bartle, J. October , 1998 The interesting question presented is whether the claim of plaintiff Susan Elaine Smith ("Smith") against defendant Fred E. Weiderhold ("Weiderhold") is for breach of promise to marry - a cause of action long ago abolished. 1 Weiderhold has moved to dismiss the complaint as to him under Rule 12(b)(6) of the Federal Rules of Civil Procedure on the ground that plaintiff has not stated a claim upon which relief can be granted. In considering a Rule 12(b)(6) motion, the court may rely upon the allegations in the complaint, exhibits attached to the complaint, and matters of public record. Pension Benefit Guar. Corp. v. White Consol. Indus. , 998 F.2d 1192, 1196 (3d Cir. 1993), cert. denied, 510 U.S. 1042 (1994). All well-pleaded factual allegations in the complaint are assumed to be true and 1. This court has diversity jurisdiction over plaintiff's claim against Weiderhold since she is a citizen of Pennsylvania and he is a citizen of Virginia. Plaintiff has sued Amtrak, Weiderhold's employer, for breach of common law duty to warn, breach of fiduciary duty under ERISA, and quid pro quo sexual harassment. are viewed in the light most favorable to the nonmovant. Hishon v. King & Spalding, 467 U.S. 69 (1984); Rocks v. City of Philadelphia, 868 F.2d 644, 645 (3d Cir. 1989). A complaint should be dismissed pursuant to Rule 12(b)(6) only where it is clear that no relief could be granted under any set of facts that could be proved consistent with the allegations.
    [Show full text]
  • Promises of Confidentiality: Do Reporters Really Have to Keep Their Word
    Missouri Law Review Volume 57 Issue 3 Summer 1992 Article 7 Summer 1992 Promises of Confidentiality: Do Reporters Really Have to Keep Their Word Harold B. Oakley Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.missouri.edu/mlr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Harold B. Oakley, Promises of Confidentiality: Do Reporters Really Have to Keep Their Word, 57 MO. L. REV. (1992) Available at: https://scholarship.law.missouri.edu/mlr/vol57/iss3/7 This Note is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Journals at University of Missouri School of Law Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Missouri Law Review by an authorized editor of University of Missouri School of Law Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Oakley: Oakley: Promises of Confidentiality Promises of Confidentiality: Do Reporters Really Have to Keep Their Word? Cohen v. Cowles Media Co.' I. INTRODUCTION In an industry in which information is the ultimate commodity, a new dilemma that confronts the media world is whether the First Amendment protects news gatherers from sources who try to enforce promises of confidentiality. The debate raised in Cohen v. Cowles Media Co.2 pits the First Amendment freedoms of the press and speech against concepts of contracts and torts that are deeply rooted in our legal heritage. By upholding the media's liability to its sources, the United States Supreme Court's opinion in Cohen could have a great impact upon the way reporters gather news and methods of news publication. The decision will propel contract issues such as offer, acceptance and consideration into the ivory tower of editorial journalism.
    [Show full text]