Divine Judgment and the Nature of Time

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Divine Judgment and the Nature of Time View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Asbury Theological Seminary Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 22 Issue 3 Article 5 7-1-2005 Divine Judgment and the Nature of Time Patrick Toner Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Toner, Patrick (2005) "Divine Judgment and the Nature of Time," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 22 : Iss. 3 , Article 5. Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol22/iss3/5 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. DIVINE JUDGMENT AND THE NATURE OF TIME Patrick Toner Many Christians believe that persons who, at the moment of death, are in rebellion from God, are damned, while those in right relationship with God are saved. This is what, for instance, the Catholic teaching regarding the fate of those who die in mortal sin amounts to. In this paper, I argue that this “last moment view” is incompatible with a popular theory of time known as eter- nalism, according to which all times are equally real. If that’s right, then those who accept the last moment view are committed to an alternative theory of time known as presentism. Many Christians accept an account of the afterlife according to which the determining factor in the Divine judgment is the state of the person’s soul at death—I’ll call this account the “last moment view.” As far as I know, the clearest statement of the last moment view is in Catholic teaching, according to which, if a person dies in a state of mortal sin, then he is con- signed to the “eternal death of hell.”1 I will argue that the “eternalist” account of time is incompatible with the last moment view, and that, there- fore, those who accept the last moment view are committed to “presen- tism.” (I’ll sketch out the meaning of this terminology in the paper’s first section.) The main target of my arguments will be eternalism in combina- tion with the ontological view known as “perdurance,” but, as I’ll briefly show towards the close of the paper, “endurantist” eternalists shall fare no better (or no worse, as the case may be) against my arguments than eter- nalists of the perdurantist persuasion. I Eternalism—the claim that all times are ontologically on par; that the present is no more real than the past or the future—stands in contrast to presentism, according to which the past is no more, and the future is not yet; only the present exists.2 Thus, the dispute between eternalists and pre- sentists is a dispute about the ontological status of times other than the pre- sent. Presentists think that only the present exists, while eternalists think all times exist. Another way of putting the presentist thesis is that presen- tists believe that only those things that exist now, exist at all (and further, that objects exemplify only those properties they exemplify now). Dinosaurs did exist once, but they don’t exist now, so they don’t exist at all. FAITH AND PHILOSOPHY Vol. 22 No. 3 July 2005 316 All rights reserved DIVINE JUDGMENT AND THE NATURE OF TIME 317 Eternalists agree, of course, that dinosaurs don’t exist now (or, if they don’t agree, that’s not because they’re eternalists, but because they have some additional peculiarity), but they do believe that dinosaurs exist. They exist in the past, which is just as real as the future, which is just as real as the present. A helpful comparison is often drawn between presentism and actual- ism. Just as the presentist thinks that only those things that exist now exist (or that an object exemplifies only those properties that it exemplifies now), the actualist holds that only those things that exist in the actual world exist. One can, similarly, compare the eternalist with the possibilist. Just as the eternalist believes that objects that don’t exist now nevertheless exist, possi- bilists believe that objects that don’t exist here (i.e. in the actual world) nev- ertheless exist. We turn now to the persistence issue. Endurantists and perdurantists agree that (at least some) objects persist, or last, over time.3 (For example, I existed in 1975, and I exist now: I have persisted.) They disagree about how objects persist. Endurantists hold that persisting objects are wholly present at all times in which they exist. Perdurantists believe that persisting objects are, rather, spread out in time: they have temporal parts, and are not whol- ly present at any given moment of time. So assume that perdurantism is true: what accounts for my existing in both 1975 and 2002 is that I have a temporal part in 1975 and a temporal part in 2002; I am made up of all of my temporal parts. To understand what this means, just consider your spatial parts. What accounts for you being both in water and in air (at the same time) is that you have a part (your foot) in the water, and a part (your head) in the air. The perdurantist claims that temporal parts are just like spatial parts. Just as spatially extended objects have spatial parts in differ- ent places, temporally extended objects have temporal parts in different times. Many philosophers accept perdurantism because of various metaphysi- cal puzzles. One of the best known of these puzzles is the problem of tem- porary intrinsics, which David Lewis calls the “decisive objection against endurance.”4 Persisting things change their intrinsic properties. For instance shape: when I sit, I have a bent shape; when I stand, I have a straight- ened shape. Both shapes are temporary intrinsic properties; I have them only some of the time. How is such change possible? The trouble here, Lewis thinks, is that it is a contradiction for one thing to have both the property of sitting and the property of standing. Lewis believes that the only plausible way to solve the problem is by invoking perdurance, according to which it is not one thing that has these contradic- tory properties, but, rather, it’s different things that have them—one tem- poral part has the property sitting, and another has the property standing. Presentists, as you would expect, do not find this objection decisive. As we’ll see, the problem of temporary intrinsics is importantly relevant to my argument below, so I will briefly outline a good presentist reply to the problem. Look again at the problem: if it is possible for persisting objects 318 Faith and Philosophy to change, then it is possible that a persisting object O is F, and that in the past, O was ~F. Thus, it seems, O is both F and ~F. And that’s not good. Presentists avoid this problem by insisting that an object exemplifies only the properties it has at the present. There is no contradiction, then, because O, if it is now F, is no longer ~F, even though it once was.5 This will be important in what follows. It is, I think, relatively uncontroversial that perdurance entails eternal- ism.6 To see why, imagine that presentism is true. Then, if perdurance is true and I am the sum of all my temporal parts—but only the present part exists—I am not a persisting thing at all, but simply an instantaneous blip. After all, how could I have parts that don’t exist?7 But perdurance is sup- posed to be a theory of persistence, so it isn’t compatible with presentism. Thus, not only do we see that perdurance entails eternalism, we also see that presentism entails endurance. It’s not, however, entirely clear that endurance and eternalism are incom- patible. Indeed, some very good philosophers believe these doctrines are compatible. I’m inclined to think they are mistaken, but we needn’t settle that dispute here.8 We’ll put that combination of views aside, and return to it later. For the time being, I will argue against perdurance—on the under- standing that perdurance entails eternalism.9 Also, until further notice, when I speak of endurance, I shall mean endurance combined with presen- tism. Once I have shown that the last moment view rules out perdurantist eternalism, I shall then briefly take up the question of whether endurantist eternalism can escape my arguments. I don’t think it can. II Those who accept the last moment view believe that a person’s moral state at the time of his death is the determining factor in his fate—God assigns people their place in either heaven or hell on the basis of his judgment of the state of the soul at death. The Catholic Church, again, teaches that one who dies with unconfessed mortal sin on his soul is damned. Now consid- er of a fairly standard complaint about the Catholic teaching on mortal sin and damnation. Imagine that Wendy has been a good and faithful Catholic all her life, but that one day she returns home from work to find her husband in bed with the mailman. Wendy kills her husband with the very heavy mailbag she happens to find handy. Let’s stipulate that this is a mor- tal sin.
Recommended publications
  • Experience and the Passage of Time∗
    Experience and the Passage of Time∗ Bradford Skow 1 Introduction Some philosophers believe that the passage of time is a real phenomenon. And some of them find a reason to believe this when they attend to features of their conscious experience. In fact this “argument from experience” is supposed to be one of the main arguments for passage. What exactly does this argument look like? Is it any good? There are in fact many different arguments from experience. I am not sure I understand them all. In this paper I want to talk about the three most interesting arguments that I do understand.1 I am going to argue that all three of them fail. ∗Published in Philosophical Perspectives 25: Metaphysics (2011), pp.359-387. 1I will not say anything about A. N. Prior’s “Thank Goodness That’s Over” argument (Prior 1959) because it is not an argument from experience (even though it is often said to be). Here is Prior’s argument: I can be glad that my ordeal is over without being glad that my ordeal is earlier than this thought or that my ordeal is earlier than 12 noon. But the latter two propositions are the propositions that some opponents of passage (the ones Prior knew) identified with the proposition that my ordeal is over. Prior concluded that the object of my propositional attitude is a proposition that only proponents of passage believe in. Phenomenal experience does not play an important role in this argument. True, there is some distinctive phenomenal “feel” that (sometimes? usually? always?) occurs when I am glad about something.
    [Show full text]
  • Parts of Persons Identity and Persistence in a Perdurantist World
    UNIVERSITÀ DEGLI STUDI DI MILANO Doctoral School in Philosophy and Human Sciences (XXXI Cycle) Department of Philosophy “Piero Martinetti” Parts of Persons Identity and persistence in a perdurantist world Ph.D. Candidate Valerio BUONOMO Tutors Prof. Giuliano TORRENGO Prof. Paolo VALORE Coordinator of the Doctoral School Prof. Marcello D’AGOSTINO Academic year 2017-2018 1 Content CONTENT ........................................................................................................................... 2 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS ........................................................................................................... 4 INTRODUCTION ................................................................................................................... 5 CHAPTER 1. PERSONAL IDENTITY AND PERSISTENCE...................................................................... 8 1.1. The persistence of persons and the criteria of identity over time .................................. 8 1.2. The accounts of personal persistence: a standard classification ................................... 14 1.2.1. Mentalist accounts of personal persistence ............................................................................ 15 1.2.2. Somatic accounts of personal persistence .............................................................................. 15 1.2.3. Anti-criterialist accounts of personal persistence ................................................................... 16 1.3. The metaphysics of persistence: the mereological account .........................................
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosophy and Physics of Time Travel: the Possibility of Time Travel
    University of Minnesota Morris Digital Well University of Minnesota Morris Digital Well Honors Capstone Projects Student Scholarship 2017 The Philosophy and Physics of Time Travel: The Possibility of Time Travel Ramitha Rupasinghe University of Minnesota, Morris, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.morris.umn.edu/honors Part of the Philosophy Commons, and the Physics Commons Recommended Citation Rupasinghe, Ramitha, "The Philosophy and Physics of Time Travel: The Possibility of Time Travel" (2017). Honors Capstone Projects. 1. https://digitalcommons.morris.umn.edu/honors/1 This Paper is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Scholarship at University of Minnesota Morris Digital Well. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors Capstone Projects by an authorized administrator of University of Minnesota Morris Digital Well. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Philosophy and Physics of Time Travel: The possibility of time travel Ramitha Rupasinghe IS 4994H - Honors Capstone Project Defense Panel – Pieranna Garavaso, Michael Korth, James Togeas University of Minnesota, Morris Spring 2017 1. Introduction Time is mysterious. Philosophers and scientists have pondered the question of what time might be for centuries and yet till this day, we don’t know what it is. Everyone talks about time, in fact, it’s the most common noun per the Oxford Dictionary. It’s in everything from history to music to culture. Despite time’s mysterious nature there are a lot of things that we can discuss in a logical manner. Time travel on the other hand is even more mysterious.
    [Show full text]
  • Bergsoniana, 1
    Bergsoniana 1 | 2021 Reassessing Bergson Bergsonian Answers to Contemporary Persistence Questions Florian Fischer Electronic version URL: https://journals.openedition.org/bergsoniana/448 DOI: 10.4000/bergsoniana.448 ISSN: 2800-874X Publisher Société des amis de Bergson Electronic reference Florian Fischer, “Bergsonian Answers to Contemporary Persistence Questions”, Bergsoniana [Online], 1 | 2021, Online since 01 July 2021, connection on 14 September 2021. URL: http:// journals.openedition.org/bergsoniana/448 ; DOI: https://doi.org/10.4000/bergsoniana.448 Les contenus de la revue sont mis à disposition selon les termes de la Licence Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International. BERGSONIAN ANSWERS TO CONTEMPORARY PERSISTENCE QUESTIONS Florian FISCHER Introduction Time is one of the central topics of contemporary analytic philosophy, and Henri Bergson is one of the most important philosophers of time, but still Bergson plays virtually no role in the contemporary analytic debate about time. In contrast to his poor reception,1 Henri Bergson has a lot to offer analytic philosophy, as I will argue. More precisely, I will illustrate what the debates about persistence and ontology of time might gain from incorporating Bergsonian ideas. To do so, I will first investigate persistence, i.e., existence through time. The focal point of the contemporary analytic debate is how to conceptualise change without letting the involved incompatibilities lead to a logical contradiction. This can be called a horizontal way of posing the question, namely, how to reconcile two incompatible properties had by one entity at two points in time. Bergson famously asserted that objects are ontologically secondary, mind- dependent abstractions from an underlying dynamic reality.
    [Show full text]
  • Four-Dimensionalism, Eternalism, and Deprivationist Accounts of the Evil of Death
    Synthese https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03393-0 ORIGINAL RESEARCH Four-dimensionalism, eternalism, and deprivationist accounts of the evil of death Andrew Brenner1 Received: 22 June 2021 / Accepted: 28 August 2021 © The Author(s), under exclusive licence to Springer Nature B.V. 2021 Abstract Four-dimensionalists think that we persist over time by having different temporal parts at each of the times at which we exist. Eternalists think that all times are equally real. Deprivationists think that death is an evil for the one who dies because it deprives them of something. I argue that four-dimensionalist eternalism, conjoined with a standard deprivationist account of the evil of death, has surprising implications for what we should think about the evil of death. In particular, given these assumptions, we will lack any grounds for thinking that death is an evil for some individuals for whom we would antecedently expect it to be an evil, namely those individuals who cease to exist at death. Alternatively, we will only have some grounds for thinking that death is an evil for certain individuals for whom we might antecedently be more inclined to think death is not an evil, namely those individuals who survive death, in the sense that they continue to exist after death. Keywords Death · Evil of death · Four-dimensionalism · Eternalism · Perdurantism · Stage theory 1 Introduction According to four-dimensionalism, things which persist over time do so by hav- ing temporal parts at each of the times at which they exist. Four-dimensionalism is almost always conjoined with an eternalist temporal ontology, according to which past, present, and future things are equally real.
    [Show full text]
  • Travelling in Time: How to Wholly Exist in Two Places at the Same Time
    Travelling in Time: How to Wholly Exist in Two Places at the Same Time 1 Introduction It is possible to wholly exist at multiple spatial locations at the same time. At least, if time travel is possible and objects endure, then such must be the case. To accommodate this possibility requires the introduction of a spatial analog of either relativising properties to times—relativising properties to spatial locations—or of relativising the manner of instantiation to times—relativising the manner of instantiation to spatial locations. It has been suggested, however, that introducing irreducibly spatially relativised or spatially adverbialised properties presents some difficulties for the endurantist. I will consider an objection according to which embracing such spatially relativised properties could lead us to reject mereology altogether in favour of a metaphysics according to which objects are wholly present at every space-time point at which they exist. I argue that although such a view is coherent, there are some good reasons to reject it. Moreover, I argue that the endurantist can introduce spatially relativised or adverbialised properties without conceding that objects lack spatial parts. Such a strategy has the additional advantage that it allows the endurantist not only to explain time travel, but also to reconcile our competing intuitions about cases of fission. The possibility of travelling back in time to a period in which one’s earlier self or one’s ancestors exist, raises a number of well-worn problems (Grey, 1999; Chambers, 1999; Horwich, 1975 and Sider, 2002). In this paper I am concerned with only one of these: how is it that an object can travel back in time to meet its earlier self, thus existing at two different spatial locations at one and the same time? Four-dimensionalists have an easy answer to this question.
    [Show full text]
  • Presentism/Eternalism and Endurantism/Perdurantism: Why the Unsubstantiality of the First Debate Implies That of the Second1
    1 Presentism/Eternalism and Endurantism/Perdurantism: why the 1 unsubstantiality of the first debate implies that of the second Forthcoming in Philosophia Naturalis Mauro Dorato (Ph.D) Department of Philosophy University of Rome Three [email protected] tel. +393396070133 http://host.uniroma3.it/dipartimenti/filosofia/personale/doratoweb.htm Abstract The main claim that I want to defend in this paper is that the there are logical equivalences between eternalism and perdurantism on the one hand and presentism and endurantism on the other. By “logical equivalence” I mean that one position is entailed and entails the other. As a consequence of this equivalence, it becomes important to inquire into the question whether the dispute between endurantists and perdurantists is authentic, given that Savitt (2006) Dolev (2006) and Dorato (2006) have cast doubts on the fact that the debate between presentism and eternalism is about “what there is”. In this respect, I will conclude that also the debate about persistence in time has no ontological consequences, in the sense that there is no real ontological disagreement between the two allegedly opposite positions: as in the case of the presentism/eternalism debate, one can be both a perdurantist and an endurantist, depending on which linguistic framework is preferred. The main claim that I want to defend in this paper is that the there are logical equivalences between eternalism and perdurantism on the one hand and presentism and endurantism on the other. By “logical equivalence” I mean that one position is entailed and entails the other. As a consequence of this equivalence, it becomes important to inquire into the question whether the dispute between endurantists and perdurantists is authentic, given that Savitt (2006) Dolev (2006) and Dorato (2006) have cast doubts on the fact that the debate between presentism and eternalism is about “what there is”.
    [Show full text]
  • Taking Tense Seriously’ Dean W
    W. Zimmerman dialectica Vol. 59, N° 4 (2005), pp. 401–457 The A-Theory of Time, The B-Theory of Time, and ‘Taking Tense Seriously’ Dean W. Zimmerman† ABSTRACT The paper has two parts: First, I describe a relatively popular thesis in the philosophy of propositional attitudes, worthy of the name ‘taking tense seriously’; and I distinguish it from a family of views in the metaphysics of time, namely, the A-theories (or what are sometimes called ‘tensed theories of time’). Once the distinction is in focus, a skeptical worry arises. Some A- theorists maintain that the difference between past, present, and future, is to be drawn in terms of what exists: growing-block theorists eschew ontological commitment to future entities; pre- sentists, to future and past entities. Others think of themselves as A-theorists but exclude no past or future things from their ontology. The metaphysical skeptic suspects that their attempt to articulate an ‘eternalist’ version of the A-theory collapses into merely ‘taking tense seriously’ – a thesis that does not imply the A-theory. The second half of the paper is the search for a stable eternalist A-theory. It includes discussion of temporary intrinsics, temporal parts, and truth. 1. Introduction Sadly, the great metaphysician J. McT. E. McTaggart is now remembered mainly for what must be his worst argument: the infamous argument for ‘the unreality of time’. But even this ‘philosophical “howler” ’ (as C. D. Broad rightly called it1) includes enough insightful analysis to have made it a natural starting point for most subsequent work on the metaphysics of time.
    [Show full text]
  • Endurantism Vs. Perdurantism
    International Journal of Database Management Systems ( IJDMS ) Vol.4, No.3, June 2012 CONCEPTUAL MODELLING AND THE QUALITY OF ONTOLOGIES : ENDURANTISM VS. PERDURANTISM Mutaz M. Al-Debei 1, Mohammad Mourhaf Al Asswad 2, Sergio de Cesar 3 and Mark Lycett 4 1Department of Management Information Systems, The University of Jordan, Amman, Jordan [email protected] 2Department of Information Systems and Computing, Brunel University – West London, London, UK {mohammad.alasswad,Sergio.deCesare,mark.lycett}@brunel.ac.uk ABSTRACT Ontologies are key enablers for sharing precise and machine-understandable semantics among different applications and parties. Yet, for ontologies to meet these expectations, their quality must be of a good standard. The quality of an ontology is strongly based on the design method employed. This paper addresses the design problems related to the modelling of ontologies, with specific concentration on the issues related to the quality of the conceptualisations produced. The paper aims to demonstrate the impact of the modelling paradigm adopted on the quality of ontological models and, consequently, the potential impact that such a decision can have in relation to the development of software applications. To this aim, an ontology that is conceptualised based on the Object-Role Modelling (ORM) approach (a representative of endurantism) is re-engineered into a one modelled on the basis of the Object Paradigm (OP) (a representative of perdurantism). Next, the two ontologies are analytically compared using the specified criteria. The conducted comparison highlights that using the OP for ontology conceptualisation can provide more expressive, reusable, objective and temporal ontologies than those conceptualised on the basis of the ORM approach.
    [Show full text]
  • Endurantism Or Perdurantism?
    The embodied self: Endurantism or perdurantism? Saskia Heijnen Contents Contents ...................................................................................................................................... 1 Abstract ...................................................................................................................................... 2 Introduction ................................................................................................................................ 2 1. Endurantism versus perdurantism in metaphysics .............................................................. 5 1.1 Particulars ......................................................................................................................... 5 1.2 Persisting particulars ......................................................................................................... 7 1.3 Temporal parts: a closer look ......................................................................................... 10 1.4 Wholly present: a closer look ......................................................................................... 14 1.5 Perdurantism and endurantism in action ........................................................................ 17 1.5.1 Fusion ....................................................................................................................... 17 1.5.2 Fission ...................................................................................................................... 19 2. Endurantism versus
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Time: a Slightly Opinionated Introduction
    Philosophy of time: A slightly opinionated introduction Florian Fischer There are several intertwined debates in the area of contemporary philos- ophy of time. One field of inquiry is the nature of time itself. Presentists think that only the present moment exists whereas eternalists believe that all of (space-)time exists on a par. The second main field of inquiry is the question of how objects persist through time. The endurantist claims that objects are three-dimensional wholes, which persist by being wholly1 present, whereas the perdurantist thinks that objects are four- dimensional and that their temporal parts are the bearers of properties. The third debate in the field of contemporary philosophy of time is about tense- versus tenseless theory. Tensers are at odds with detensers about the status of the linguistic reference to the present moment. These are only very crude characterizations and it is even disputed by some ad- vocates of the corresponding positions that they are accurate. However this very sketchy picture already reveals a fundamental difference: The eternalism/presentism and endurance/perdurance discussions belong to the field of metaphysics, whereas tense is in the first instance a linguistic phenomenon. Among the many fields of philosophy, there are two that are more intimately interconnected than most but whose practi- tioners have too long pursued relatively independent paths. On the one hand, there are philosophers of language, who have devoted much attention to indexicals (`now', etc.), tem- poral operators (`it has been the case that', etc.), and tensed sentences. On the other hand, there are the philosophers of tensed and tenseless time (also called A-time or B-time, dynamic time or static time, etc.).
    [Show full text]
  • Nihilist Perdurantism: a New Ontology of Material Objects
    University of Kentucky UKnowledge Theses and Dissertations--Philosophy Philosophy 2017 NIHILIST PERDURANTISM: A NEW ONTOLOGY OF MATERIAL OBJECTS Brian Matthew Carlson University of Kentucky, [email protected] Author ORCID Identifier: https://orcid.org/0000-0002-9625-2266 Digital Object Identifier: https://doi.org/10.13023/ETD.2017.268 Right click to open a feedback form in a new tab to let us know how this document benefits ou.y Recommended Citation Carlson, Brian Matthew, "NIHILIST PERDURANTISM: A NEW ONTOLOGY OF MATERIAL OBJECTS" (2017). Theses and Dissertations--Philosophy. 17. https://uknowledge.uky.edu/philosophy_etds/17 This Doctoral Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy at UKnowledge. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses and Dissertations--Philosophy by an authorized administrator of UKnowledge. For more information, please contact [email protected]. STUDENT AGREEMENT: I represent that my thesis or dissertation and abstract are my original work. Proper attribution has been given to all outside sources. I understand that I am solely responsible for obtaining any needed copyright permissions. I have obtained needed written permission statement(s) from the owner(s) of each third-party copyrighted matter to be included in my work, allowing electronic distribution (if such use is not permitted by the fair use doctrine) which will be submitted to UKnowledge as Additional File. I hereby grant to The University of Kentucky and its agents the irrevocable, non-exclusive, and royalty-free license to archive and make accessible my work in whole or in part in all forms of media, now or hereafter known.
    [Show full text]