PROBLEMS in LOGICAL FORM Robert C

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

PROBLEMS in LOGICAL FORM Robert C PROBLEMS IN LOGICAL FORM Robert C. Moore SRI International, Menlo Park, CA 94025 pieces of the logical form of the utterance that I INTRODUCTION constitute referring expressions. Having logical forms be semantically compositional is the ultimate expression of this kind of decomposability, as it renders ev,ery Decomposition of the problem of "language well-formed subexpression a locus of meanlng--and understanding" into manageable subproblems has always therefore a potential locus of meanlng-dependent posed a major challenge to the development theories of, processing. This is probably a more telling argument and systems for, natural-language processing. More or for semantic composltlonality in designing language- less distinct components are conventionally proposed for processing systems than in analyzing human language, but handling syntax, semantics, pragmatics, and inference. it can be reasonably argued that such design principles While disagreement exists as to what phenomena properly must be followed by any system, whether natural or belong in each area, and how much or what kinds of artificial, that has to adapt to a complex environment interaction there are among these components, there is (see [Simon, 1969], especially Chapter 4). I fairly widespread concurrence as to the overall Logical form, therefore, is proposed as a level of organization of linguistic processing. representation distinct from surface-syntactlc form, because there is apparently no direct way to Central to this approach is the idea that the semantically interpret natural language sentences in a processing of an utterance involves producing an compositional fashion. Some linguists and philosophers expression or structure that is in some sense a have challenged this assumption [Montague, 1974a] representation of the literal meaning of the utterance. [Barwlse and Cooper, 1981], but the complexity of their It is often maintained that understanding what an proposed systems and the limited range of syntactic utterance literally means consists in being able to forms they consider leave serlous doubt that the recover this representation. In philosophy and logical-form level can be completely bypassed. 2 linguistics this sort of representation is usually said to display the~ form of an utterance, so we will Beyond being co~positiouel, it is desirable--though refer (somewhat loosely-~-- to the representations perhaps not essential--that the meaning of a logical themselves as "logical forms," form also be independent of the context in which the associated utterance occurs. (The meaning of an This paper surveys what we at SRI view as some of expression in natural language, of course, is often the key problems encountered in defining a system of context-dependent.) A language-processing system must representation for the logical forms of English eventually produce a context-independent representation sentences, and suggests possible approaches to their of what the speaker means by an utterance because the solution. We will first look at some general issues content of the utterance will normally be subjected to related to the notion of logical form, and then discuss further processlnE after the original context has been a number of problems associated with the way information lost. In the many cases in which the speaker's intended involving certain key concepts is expressed in English. meaning is simply the literal meaning, a context- Although our main concern here is with theoretical independent logical form would give us the issues rather than with system performance, this paper representation we need. There is little doubt that some is not merely speculative. The DIALOGIC system representation of this sort is required. For example, currently under development in the SKI Artificial much of our general knowledge of the world is derived Intelligence Center parses English sentences and from simple assertions of fact in natural language, but translates them into logical forms embodying many of the our situation would be hopeless if, for every fact we ideas presented here. knew, we had to remember the context in which it was obtained before we could use it appropriately. Imagine trying to decide what to do with a tax refund by having to recall whether the topic of conversation was rivers or financial institutions the first time one heard that II THE NATURE OF LOGICAL FORM banks were good places in which to keep money. As this example suggests, context independence is The first question to ask is, why even have a level closely related to the resolution of ambiguity. For any of logical form? After all, sentences of natural given ambiguity, it is possible to find a case in which languages are themselves conveyers of meaning; that is the information needed tO resolve it is derived from the what natural languages are for. The reason for having context of an utterance. Therefore, if the meanlnEs of logical foznns is to present the literal meanings of logical forms are to be context-lndependent, the system sentences more perspicuously than do the sentences of logical forms must provide distinct, unambiguous themselves. It is sometimes said that natural-language representations for all possible readings of an sentences do not '~ear their meanings on their sleeves"; ambiguous utterance. The question remains whether logical forms are intended to do exactly that. logical form should also provide ambiguous representations to handle cases in which the From this perspective, the main desideratum for a dlsamblguatlng information is obtained later or is system of logical form is that its semantics be simply general world knowledge. The pros and cons of compositional. That is, the meaning of a complex such an approach are far from clear, so we will expression should depend only on the meaning of its generally assume only unembIEuous logical forms. subexpresslons. This is needed for meanlnE-dependent cou~utational processes to cope with logical forms of Although it is sometimes assumed that a context- arbitrary complexity. If there is to be any hope of independent representation of the literal meaning of a maintaining an intellectual grasp of what these sentence can be derived by using syntactic and semantic processes are doing, they must be decomposable into knowledge only, some pragmatic factors must also be smaller and smaller meanlng-dependent subprocesses taken into account. To take a concrete example, suppose operating on smaller and smaller meaningful pieces of a the request "Please llst the Nobel Prize winners in logical form. For instance, if identifying the entities physics," is followed by the question '~dho are the referred to by an utterance is a subprocess of inferring Americans?" The phrase "the Americans" in the second the speaker's intentions, there must be identifiable utterance should almost certainly be interpreted as 117 referring to American winners of the Nobel Prize in In summary, the notion of logical form we wish to physics, rather than all inhabitants or citizens of the capture is essentially that of a representation of the United States, as It might be understood in isolation. "literal meaning in context" of an utterance. To If the logical form of the utterance is to reflect the facilitate further processing, it is virtually essential intended interpretation, processes that are normally that the meaning of Ioglcal-form expressions be assigned to praSmatlcs must be used to derive it. compositional and, at the same time, it is highly desirable that they be conCext-lndependenc. The latter One could attempt to avoid thls consequence by condition requires that a system of logical form furnish representing "the Americans" at the level of logical distinct representations for the dlfferenc readings of form as literally meaning all Americans, and have later ambiguous natural-language expressions. It also pragmatic processing restrict the interpretation co requires chat some limited amount of prag~atlc American winners of the Nobel Prize in physics. There processing be involved in producing those are other cases, however, for which thls sort of move is representations. Finally, we note that not all not available. Consider more carefully the adjective pragmatic factors in the use of language can be "American." American people could be either inhabitants reflected in the logical form of an utterance, because or citizens of the United States; American cars could be some of those factors are dependent on information that either manufactured or driven in the United States; the logical form itself provides. American food could be food produced or consumed in or prepared in a style indigenous Co the United States. In short, the meaning of "American" seems to be no more than "bearing some contextually determined relation to the United States." Thus, there is n~o deflnlte context- III FORM AND CONTENT IN KNOWLEDGE P.EP&ESENTJtTION independent mesnlng for sentences containing modifiers llke "American." The same is true for many uses of "have," "of," possessives, locative prepositions Developing a theory of the loglcal form of English [Herskovits, 1980] and compound nominals. The only way sentences is as much an exercise in knowledge to hold fast to the position that the construction of representation as in linguistics, but ic differs from loglcal-form precedes all pragmatic processing seems to most work in arclficlal intelligence on knowledge be to put in "dummy'* symbols for the unknown relations: representation in one key respect. Knowledge This m@y in fact be very useful in building an actual representation schemes are usually intended by their system, ~ but It is hard to imagine that such a level of designers to be as general as possible and to avoid representation would bear much theoretical weight. com~aitment to any particular concepts. The essential problem for a theory of logical form, however, is co We will chum assume that a theoretically represent specific concepts chat natural languages have interesting level of logical form will have resolved special features for expressing information about. contextually dependent definite references, as well as Concepts that fall in chls category include: the ocher "local" pragmatic lndeterminacies mentioned.
Recommended publications
  • Against Logical Form
    Against logical form Zolta´n Gendler Szabo´ Conceptions of logical form are stranded between extremes. On one side are those who think the logical form of a sentence has little to do with logic; on the other, those who think it has little to do with the sentence. Most of us would prefer a conception that strikes a balance: logical form that is an objective feature of a sentence and captures its logical character. I will argue that we cannot get what we want. What are these extreme conceptions? In linguistics, logical form is typically con- ceived of as a level of representation where ambiguities have been resolved. According to one highly developed view—Chomsky’s minimalism—logical form is one of the outputs of the derivation of a sentence. The derivation begins with a set of lexical items and after initial mergers it splits into two: on one branch phonological operations are applied without semantic effect; on the other are semantic operations without phono- logical realization. At the end of the first branch is phonological form, the input to the articulatory–perceptual system; and at the end of the second is logical form, the input to the conceptual–intentional system.1 Thus conceived, logical form encompasses all and only information required for interpretation. But semantic and logical information do not fully overlap. The connectives “and” and “but” are surely not synonyms, but the difference in meaning probably does not concern logic. On the other hand, it is of utmost logical importance whether “finitely many” or “equinumerous” are logical constants even though it is hard to see how this information could be essential for their interpretation.
    [Show full text]
  • Bearers of Truth and the Unsaid
    1 Bearers of Truth and the Unsaid Stephen Barker (University of Nottingham) Draft (Forthcoming in Making Semantics Pragmatic (ed) K. Turner. (CUP). The standard view about the bearers of truth–the entities that are the ultimate objects of predication of truth or falsity–is that they are propositions or sentences semantically correlated with propositions. Propositions are meant to be the contents of assertions, objects of thought or judgement, and so are ontologically distinct from assertions or acts of thought or judgement. So understood propositions are meant to be things like possible states of affairs or sets of possible worlds–entities that are clearly not acts of judgement. Let us say that a sentence S encodes a proposition «P» when linguistic rules (plus context) correlate «P» with S in a manner that does not depend upon whether S is asserted or appears embedded in a logical compound. The orthodox conception of truth-bearers then can be expressed in two forms: TB1 : The primary truth-bearers are propositions. TB2 : The primary truth-bearers are sentences that encode a proposition «P». I use the term primary truth-bearers , since orthodoxy allows that assertions or judgements, etc, can be truth-bearers, it is just that they are derivatively so; they being truth-apt depends on other things being truth-apt. Some orthodox theorists prefer TB1 –Stalnaker (1972)– some prefer TB2 –Richard (1990). We need not concern ourselves with the reasons for their preferences here. Rather, our concern shall be this: why accept orthodoxy at all in either form: TB1 or TB2 ? There is without doubt a strong general reason to accept the propositional view.
    [Show full text]
  • Stoicism a School of Thought That Flourished in Greek and Roman
    Stoicism A school of thought that flourished in Greek and Roman antiquity. It was one of the loftiest and most sublime philosophies in the record of Western civilization. In urging participation in the affairs of man, Stoics have always believed that the goal of all inquiry is to provide man with a mode of conduct characterized by tranquillity of mind and certainty of moral worth. Nature and scope of Stoicism For the early Stoic philosopher, as for all the post-Aristotelian schools, knowledge and its pursuit are no longer held to be ends in themselves. The Hellenistic Age was a time of transition, and the Stoic philosopher was perhaps its most influential spokesman. A new culture was in the making. The heritage of an earlier period, with Athens as its intellectual leader, was to continue, but to undergo many changes. If, as with Socrates, to know is to know oneself, rationality as the sole means by which something outside of the self might be achieved may be said to be the hallmark of Stoic belief. As a Hellenistic philosophy, Stoicism presented an ars vitae, a way of accommodation for people to whom the human condition no longer appeared as the mirror of a universal, calm, and ordered existence. Reason alone could reveal the constancy of cosmic order and the originative source of unyielding value; thus, reason became the true model for human existence. To the Stoic, virtue is an inherent feature of the world, no less inexorable in relation to man than are the laws of nature. The Stoics believed that perception is the basis of true knowledge.
    [Show full text]
  • Pagebreaks in the Original Publication Are Indicated in Margine by a Slash and Page Number
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by PhilPapers Pagebreaks in the original publication are indicated in margine by a slash and page number Theodor Ebert (Erlangen) Dialecticians and Stoics on the Classification of Propositions In his discussion and refutation of the logical theories of dogmatist philosophers in Adversus Mathematicos (M. ) 8, Sextus Empiricus treats us, among other things, to an account of a classification of propositions (M. 8.93–129). The doctrine reported on here is usually taken to form part of Stoic logic. 1 Together with its apparent counterpart in Diogenes Laertius (D.L.) 7.68–76, this Sextian report is used to reconstruct a theory supposedly held by Stoic philosophers. In what follows I shall try to refute this view and I shall argue that Sextus’ report encapsulates a doctrine worked out not by the Stoic, but by the Dialectical school whose most prominent members seem to have been Diodorus Cronus and Philo. 2 First I shall try to show that the two reports by Sextus and by Diogenes resp. are quite different indeed as to their systematic content and that, therefore, both reports must be drawn from different sources. In a second step it is then argued that Sextus’ account is based on Dialectical material. Finally, I shall compare the Dialectical classification to be found in Sextus to the Stoic one in Diogenes with an eye to exploring these two divisions as different phases within the development of propositional logic. I. As to its systematic intentions, but also with regard to its terminology, the doctrine reported on by Sextus differs in important respects from the one we find in Diogenes Laertius.
    [Show full text]
  • Logical Positivism, Operationalism, and Behaviorism
    This dissertation has been microfilmed exactly as received 70-6878 SHANAB, Robert E lias Abu, 1939- LOGICAL POSITIVISM, OPERATIONALISM, AND BEHAVIORISM. The Ohio State University, Ph.D., 1969 Philosophy University Microfilms, Inc., Ann Arbor, Michigan LOGICAL POSITIVISM, OPERATIONALISM, AND BEHAVIORISM DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Robert Elias Abu Shanab, B.A., A.M. ******** The Ohio State University 1969 Approved by / Adviser Department of Philosophy Dedicated to Professor Virgil Hinshaw, ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I am especially indebted to my adviser, Professor Virgil Hinshaw, Jr. Several of his suggestions have been incorporated in the final manuscript. I wish also to express my thanks to Professor Charles F. Kielkopf. Finally I wish to extend affection and gratitude to my wife for encouragement, patience and for the hours spent typing and retyping manuscripts. ii VITA September 29, 1939 B o m - Jerusalem, Palestine 1962 ........ ........... B.A. , San Jose State College, San Jose, California 1964 ................... M.A., San Jose State College, San Jose, California 1965-1966 ............. Instructor, College of San Mateo, San Mateo, California 1967-1968 ....... Teaching Assistant, Department of Philosophy, The Ohio State University, Columbus, Ohio 1969 ................... Lecturer, The Ohio State University, Newark, Ohio iii CONTENTS. Page ACKNOWLEDGMENTS ..... ....................... ii V I T A ..............................................iii
    [Show full text]
  • LOGICAL FORM Kirk Ludwig
    1.3 LOGICAL FORM Kirk Ludwig Interest in logical form has been driven historically by interest in valid argument forms, that is, semantic entailment relations between the premises and conclusion of an argu- ment underwritten by their semantic forms. The pressure to provide an ever deeper and more general account of valid argument forms has led to a generalization of the notion of logical form to semantic structure relevant to the evaluation generally of the truth or falsity of a sentence. It is a staple of the tradition since Frege that logical form differs, sometimes dra- matically, from the surface or superficial grammatical form of a sentence. (We return below to whether logical form may be associated with some further level of syntactical analysis.) For example, some sentences, like 2 and 3, have multiple readings (“someone is loved by everyone” and “everyone is such that there is someone he loves”; “relatives who are visiting can be boring” and “it can be boring visiting relatives”) which should be assigned different logical forms because the same words contribute differently to truth conditions on each. Some sentences with the same superficial form, such as 1 and 2, 4–6, 9 and 10, 11 and 12, and 13 and 14, are assigned different logical forms because they enter into different systematic entailment relations. And some sentences with superficially different forms, such as 6–8, are assigned the same logical form because they appear to enter into the same systematic entailments. 1. Mary loves John 2. Everyone loves someone 3. Visiting relatives can be boring 4.
    [Show full text]
  • Scepticism About Gods in Hellenistic Philosophy*
    SCEPTICISM ABOUT GODS IN HELLENISTIC PHILOSOPHY* Anthony A. Long University of California, Berkeley Philosophical theology offered the ancient sceptic, Academic or Pyrrhonist, a target which was tailor-made to his methods of argumentative counter-attack in the interests of “suspension of judgement” (epochê). His principal opponents, the Stoics, had marshalled a battery of formal proofs concerning the existence and nature of the gods; and formal proof, or the detection of weaknesses in it, was grist to the sceptic’s mill.1 Moreover, the Stoics were in fundamental disagreement with the Epicureans over theology, disagreement of a kind that the sceptic relished. Without exerting himself, he could begin a refutative routine, as Sextus Empiricus does in Pyrrhôneioi Hupotupôseis [hereafter PH] 3.2-4, by first invoking disagreements on god’s nature: is god corporeal or incorporeal, anthropomorphic or some other form, in spatial location or not, within the world or outside it? If such foundational questions cannot be settled, how, asks Sextus, can we even get a conception (ennoia) of god? People say [e.g., Epicureans] that god should be considered that which is imperishable and blessed.2 But consider what different schools understand by divine blessedness, and basic disagreement surfaces again: is divine blessedness displayed in the rational order pervading the entire world, as Stoics maintain? Or should one opt for the Epicurean conception of gods who are quite detached from the world and who provide no occupation for themselves or for anything else? These Pyrrhonian manoeuvres are scarcely food for deep philosophical thought. Their simplicity, none the less, is beguiling and effective.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 31 Logical Positivism and the Scientific Conception of Philosophy
    Aspects of Western Philosophy: Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly, IIT Madras Chapter 31 Logical Positivism and the Scientific Conception of Philosophy Key Words: Vienna circle, verification principle, positivism, tautologies, factual propositions, language analysis, rejection of metaphysics, practical verifiability, verifiable in principle, strong verifiability, weak verifiability, unified science This chapter discusses one of the very significant developments the 20th century European philosophy has witnessed; logical positivism, which is also known as neo empiricism. Again, like many other such initiatives in philosophy like existentialism, logical positivism is not a school of philosophy, with certain central doctrine, a definite conception of reality or a theory of knowledge. It is rather a movement that reflects the dominant scientific outlook of 20th century European civilization and its extension to all spheres of life. The logical positivists thus advocated a unique conception of knowledge which considered the scientific model as paradigm. They thus opposed metaphysics which aims at going beyond the sensible world and contemplating about transcendental realities. According to them metaphysics is a bad science. They were tremendously influenced by many philosophical approaches, notably, the positivism of Augustine Comte, the logical atomism of Bertrand Russell, and most significantly, by the peculiar conception of language and meaning developed by Ludwig Wittgenstein in his early work, the Tractatus Logico Philosophicus. The fact that almost all major advancements in knowledge have been in the field of natural sciences have prompted the logical positivists to consider scientific conception of knowledge as paradigmatic. They found that the theories of speculative philosophy advocated by different thinkers were merely personal interpretations about reality. Most importantly, these theories were not empirically verifiable and hence it is impossible to establish their truth or falsity.
    [Show full text]
  • Logical Empiricism
    Logical Empiricism HISTORICAL CONTEMPORARY PERSPECTIVES Edited by Paolo Parrini, University ofFlorence Wesley C. Salmon, University ofPittsburgh Merrilee H. Salmon, University of Pittsburgh UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH PRESS This book is dedicated to the memory of Wesley C . Salmon 1925-2001 Published by the University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh, P&, 15260 Copyright ® 2003, University of Pittsburgh Press All rights reserved Manufactured in the United States of America Printed on add-free paper 10987654321 ISBN 0 - 8n9- 4194-5 Contents Preface Introduction r Paolo Parrini and Wesley Salmon I. Turning Points and Fundamental Controversies rt A Turning Point in Philosophy : Carnap-Cassirer-Heidegger 13 Michael Friedman Carnap's "Elimination of Metaphysics through Logical Analysis of Language" : A Retrospective Consideration of the Relationship between Continental and Analytic Philosophy 30 Gottfried Gabriel Schlick and Husserl on the Essence of Knowledge 43 Roberta Lanfredini Carnap versus Gbdel on Syntax and Tolerance 57 S. Awodey and A. W Carus II. On the Origins and Development of the Vienna Circle 65 On the Austrian Roots of Logical Empiricism: The Case of the First Vienna Circle 67 Thomas Uebel On the International Encyclopedia, the Neurath-Carnap Disputes, and the Second World War 94 George Reisch Carl Gustav Hempel : Pragmatic Empiricist log Gereon Wolters III. The Riddle of Wittgenstein 123 The Methods of the Tractatus: Beyond Positivism and Metaphysics? 125 David G. Stern IV Philosophy of Physics 157 Two Roads from Kant : Cassirer, Reichenbach, and General Relativity ' 159 T A. Ryckman Vienna Indeterminism II : From Exner to Frank and von Mises 194 'Michael Stoltzner V. The Mind-Body Problem 231 The Mind-Body Problem in the Origin of Logical Empiricism : Herbert Feigl and Psychophysical Parallelism 233 Michael Heidelberger Logical Positivism and the Mind-Body Problem 263 Jaegwon Kim VI.
    [Show full text]
  • CONTEXT and LOGICAL FORM My Purpose in This Paper Is to Defend
    JASON STANLEY CONTEXT AND LOGICAL FORM ABSTRACT. In this paper, I defend the thesis that all effects of extra-linguistic context on the truth-conditions of an assertion are traceable to elements in the actual syntactic structure of the sentence uttered. In the first section, I develop the thesis in detail, and discuss its implications for the relation between semantics and pragmatics. The next two sections are devoted to apparent counterexamples. In the second section, I argue that there are no convincing examples of true non-sentential assertions. In the third section, I ar- gue that there are no convincing examples of what John Perry has called ‘unarticulated constituents’. I conclude by drawing some consequences of my arguments for appeals to context-dependence in the resolution of problems in epistemology and philosophical logic. My purpose in this paper is to defend the thesis that all truth-conditional effects of extra-linguistic context can be traced to logical form.1 But before the import of this thesis can be understood, a few distinctions must be clarified, and its opponents introduced. By “logical form”, I mean a special sort of linguistic representation, rather than the form of a non-linguistic entity such as a proposition or a fact. However, even in its linguistic sense, there is certainly no one uniform use of the expression “logical form”. But there are two distinguishable senses underlying its many differing usages. It is only in the second of these two senses that the thesis I will defend is interesting and controver- sial. Perhaps the most prevalent tradition of usage of the expression “logical form” in philosophy is to express what one might call the revisionary conception of logical form.
    [Show full text]
  • Formal Logic and Logical Form
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by UNL | Libraries University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Mid-West Quarterly, The (1913-1918) Mid-West Quarterly, The (1913-1918) 1914 Formal Logic and Logical Form Edwin Ray Guthrie Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/midwestqtrly Part of the Arts and Humanities Commons Guthrie, Edwin Ray, "Formal Logic and Logical Form" (1914). Mid-West Quarterly, The (1913-1918). 20. https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/midwestqtrly/20 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Mid-West Quarterly, The (1913-1918) at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in Mid-West Quarterly, The (1913-1918) by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. Published in THE MID-WEST QUARTERLY Vol. 1, No. 2 (January 1914) FORMAL LOGIC AND LOGICAL FORM Last year Dr. F. C. S. Schiller published Formal Logic, a Scientific and Social Problem,-a critical text-book, he calls it in the preface, that will teach logic" in a critical spirit and with a minimum of pedantry and reverence for forms." This object is so thoroughly fulfilled-at the end of the four hundred pages the criticism has been so searching and insistent and the reverence for forms so truly a minimum that formal logic seems to be a complete ruin, and the only scientific problem left at the end is how men ever came to build it, and the only social problem what logicians will now do for a living.
    [Show full text]
  • Anderson, John M. 2005. the Non-Autonomy of Syntax
    The non-autonomy of syntax John M. Anderson In: Folia Linguistica 39 (2005), 223-250. 223 The Non-autonomy of Syntax John M. Anderson Abstract Structuralism sought to introduce various kinds of autonomy into the study of language, in- cluding the autonomy of that study itself.* The basis for this was the insistence on categorial autonomy, whereby categories are identifi ed language-internally (whether in a particular lan- guage or in language). In relation to phonology, categorial autonomy is tempered by grounding: the categories correlate (at least prototypically) with substance, phonetic properties. This is manifested in the idea of ‘natural classes’ in generative phonology. Usually, however, in more modern grammars, despite some dissent, no such grounding (in meaning) has been attributed to syntax. This attitude culminates in the thesis of the ‘autonomy of syntax’ which was put forward in transformational-generative grammar. In what follows here it is argued that the consequences of this are very unfortunate. Distribution alone is insuffi cient to determine the identity of cat- egories; what is relevant is the distribution of the prototypical members of the category, where prototypicality is notionally defi ned. Prototypical nouns, for instance, denote concrete, discrete, stable entities. Syntax, as well as phonology, is grounded. Groundedness ensures that only the prototypical behaviour of semantically prototypical members of a category determines its basic syntax; and this syntax refl ects the semantic properties. Groundedness fi lters out potential syntac- tic analyses that are incompatible with this. For instance, given the diverse semantic characters of prototypical nouns and verbs, groundedness predicts that the X-bar theory of syntactic structure, which attributes parallel projections to lexical categories, is false.
    [Show full text]