Anderson, John M. 2005. the Non-Autonomy of Syntax

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Anderson, John M. 2005. the Non-Autonomy of Syntax The non-autonomy of syntax John M. Anderson In: Folia Linguistica 39 (2005), 223-250. 223 The Non-autonomy of Syntax John M. Anderson Abstract Structuralism sought to introduce various kinds of autonomy into the study of language, in- cluding the autonomy of that study itself.* The basis for this was the insistence on categorial autonomy, whereby categories are identifi ed language-internally (whether in a particular lan- guage or in language). In relation to phonology, categorial autonomy is tempered by grounding: the categories correlate (at least prototypically) with substance, phonetic properties. This is manifested in the idea of ‘natural classes’ in generative phonology. Usually, however, in more modern grammars, despite some dissent, no such grounding (in meaning) has been attributed to syntax. This attitude culminates in the thesis of the ‘autonomy of syntax’ which was put forward in transformational-generative grammar. In what follows here it is argued that the consequences of this are very unfortunate. Distribution alone is insuffi cient to determine the identity of cat- egories; what is relevant is the distribution of the prototypical members of the category, where prototypicality is notionally defi ned. Prototypical nouns, for instance, denote concrete, discrete, stable entities. Syntax, as well as phonology, is grounded. Groundedness ensures that only the prototypical behaviour of semantically prototypical members of a category determines its basic syntax; and this syntax refl ects the semantic properties. Groundedness fi lters out potential syntac- tic analyses that are incompatible with this. For instance, given the diverse semantic characters of prototypical nouns and verbs, groundedness predicts that the X-bar theory of syntactic structure, which attributes parallel projections to lexical categories, is false. Consideration of the syntax of nouns and verbs confi rms that this is indeed the case. The attribution to syntax of categorial autonomy without grounding should be abandoned. Introduction 0XFKUHFHQWZRUNLQV\QWD[DVVXPHVWKH‘DXWRQRP\RIV\QWD[’V\QWDFWLFJHQ HUDOLVDWLRQVDUHEHVWUHJDUGHGDVLQGHSHQGHQWRIZKDWDUHUHJDUGHGDVH[WUDV\Q WDFWLFFRQVLGHUDWLRQV–VHPDQWLFSUDJPDWLFSKRQRORJLFDOVRFLDO…$OOHJHG HQKDQFHPHQWVRI‘DXWRQRP\’DUHYDOXHGVRWKDWWKHDYRLGDQFHRIDSSHDOVWRZKDW PLJKWEHFRQFHLYHGRIDV‘JURXQGHG’HOHPHQWVZKLFKDUH DWOHDVWSDUWLDOO\EXW QHFHVVDULO\ VHPDQWLFDOO\GHWHUPLQHGLVSUHVHQWHGDVDGHVLUDEOHSXUVXLWVHHHJ :LONLQV ZKRYLQGLFDWHVLQWKHVHWHUPVKHUDVVLJQPHQWRIUHflH[LYLVDWLRQ ZLWKLWVDSSDUHQWGHSHQGHQFHRQ‘WKHPDWLFUROHV’DQGFRUHIHUHQFHWRWKHVHPDQ WLFVUDWKHUWKDQWRWKHV\QWD[,VKDOOVXJJHVWKHUHWKDWWKHFXOWRI‘DXWRQRP\’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‘IXQFWLRQDO’ DSSURDFKHVWRJUDPPDU%XWWKHUHDUHDWOHDVWWZRFRQVLGHUDWLRQVWKDWPDNHWKH IROORZLQJZRUWKSXUVXLQJKHUH ,QWKHfiUVWSODFHWKHUHLVWKHJHQHUDOODFNRIDFNQRZOHGJPHQWWKDWWKHDV VXPSWLRQ RI ‘DXWRQRP\’ LV LWVHOI UHFHQW LV D GHSDUWXUH IURP D FHQWXULHVROG JUDPPDWLFDO WUDGLWLRQ SUHVHQWGD\ ‘IXQFWLRQDOLVWV’ DQG ‘QRWLRQDOLVWV’ LQKHULW D ORQJWUDGLWLRQZKRVHGLVWLQFWLYHYLHZVDUHVWLOOUHOHYDQW,KDYHLQPLQGZRUNLQ ‘WUDGLWLRQDO’ SUHVWUXFWXUDOLVW JUDPPDUDQGLQHDUO\(XURSHDQVWUXFWXUDOLVP,W LVWKH‘DXWRQRP\RIV\QWD[’DVVXPSWLRQWKDWLVDKLVWRULFDODEHUUDWLRQQRWMXVWD GHYLDWLRQIURPRWKHUUHFHQWDSSURDFKHV6HFWLRQRIWKLVSDSHUWKXVVSHOOVRXW VRPHRIWKHEDFNJURXQGWRWKHGHYHORSPHQWRIWKHQRWLRQRIWKH‘DXWRQRP\RI V\QWD[’DQGVSHFLfiHVZKDW,WKLQNLVLQYROYHGLQVXFKDQDVVXPSWLRQ WKRXJKVHH $QGHUVRQEIRUPRUHH[WHQVLYHGLVFXVVLRQRIWKLVKLVWRU\ 6HFRQGO\,VXJJHVWKHUHWKDWWKHDGRSWLRQRIDQRWLRQDODQGIXQFWLRQDOED VLVIRUV\QWD[LVQRWWREHRSSRVHGWR‘IRUPDOJUDPPDU’WKHRSWLPDO‘IRUPDO’ GLVWULEXWLRQDOO\VXSSRUWHG JUDPPDUKDVDQRWLRQDOEDVLV6HFWLRQGLVFXVVHV DIHZV\QWDFWLFSKHQRPHQDWRZKRVHH[SUHVVLRQUHIHUHQFHWRVHPDQWLFVVHHPV WREHDSSURSULDWHDQGVXJJHVWVWKHVHDUHQRWXQW\SLFDO–WKRXJKDVSHFWVRIV\Q WD[PD\EHFRPH‘URXWLQLVHG’OHVVVHQVLWLYHWRQRWLRQDOFRQVLGHUDWLRQV7KLVLV DWRSLFZKLFKLVWDNHQXSLQWKHFRQFOXVLRQ6HFWLRQVKRZVIXUWKHUWKDWLWLV PLVOHDGLQJWREDVH‘IRUPDO’DFFRXQWVRIWKHV\QWD[RIFDWHJRULHVRQDQ\WKLQJEXW WKHEHKDYLRXURIQRWLRQDOO\SURWRW\SLFDOPHPEHUVRIWKHFDWHJRU\7KHRSWLPDO IRUPDO DQDO\VLV FDQQRW EH VHOHFWHG RQ SXUHO\ GLVWULEXWLRQDO VHPDQWLFIUHH JURXQGVZKHWKHURUQRWWKHVHDUHSRVLWHGDVSDUWRI‘XQLYHUVDOJUDPPDU’ 1. The autonomy of syntax ,WLVQRWFRQWURYHUVLDOWRVD\WKDWVWUXFWXUDOLVWVVWURYHWRHVWDEOLVKWKH‘DXWRQRP\ RIOLQJXLVWLFV’ IURPRWKHUGLVFLSOLQHV WKRXJKWKLVJRDOLVLQLWVHOIFRQWURYHUVLDO VHHHJ1HZPH\HU %XWWKLV‘JOREDO’DSSOLFDWLRQRIDXWRQRP\LVQRWWKH PDMRUIRFXVKHUH5DWKHUP\FRQFHUQZLOOEHZLWKUHFHQWSURSRVDOVFRQFHUQLQJ WKHDXWRQRP\RIYDULRXVDVSHFWVRIOLQJXLVWLFVWUXFWXUHVSHFLfiFDOO\RIV\QWD[ 7KHDWWLWXGHLQYROYHGLVUHflHFWHGLQIRUPXODWLRQVVXFKDV5DGIRUG’V‘DXWRQRPRXV V\QWD[SULQFLSOH’ $8721202866<17$;35,1&,3/( 1RV\QWDFWLFUXOHFDQPDNHUHIHUHQFHWRSUDJPDWLFSKRQRORJLFDORUVHPDQWLFLQIRU PDWLRQ 7KLVLVGHULYHGPRUHLPPHGLDWHO\IURP&KRPVN\ %XW&KRPVN\ DOUHDG\LQVLVWVRQ‘V\QWDFWLFDXWRQRP\’‘,WKLQNWKDWZHDUHIRUFHGWRFRQ FOXGHWKDWJUDPPDULVDXWRQRPRXVDQGLQGHSHQGHQWRIPHDQLQJ…’ (OVHZKHUH &KRPVN\ DFNQRZOHGJHV WKH ‘VWUXFWXUDOLVW’ EDFNJURXQG WR VXFK LGHDVDVSDUWRIDFRQFOXGLQJDXWRQRPLVW‘FUHGR’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fiFDQWH[WHQWRIFRQGLWLRQV RIPHDQLQJDQGXVH +RZHYHUHOVHZKHUHDJDLQ&KRPVN\LQVLVWVRQWKHOLPLWVRIWKHFRQWULEXWLRQRI ZKDWKHUHIHUVWRDV‘PRGHUQGHVFULSWLYHOLQJXLVWLFV’ 2QWKHRWKHUKDQGLWVHHPVWRPHWKDWWKHVXEVWDQWLYHFRQWULEXWLRQV>RI‘PRGHUQGH VFULSWLYHOLQJXLVWLFV’@WRWKHWKHRU\RIODQJXDJHVWUXFWXUHDUHIHZDQGWKDWWRDODUJH H[WHQWWKHFRQFHSWVRIPRGHUQOLQJXLVWLFVFRQVWLWXWHDUHWURJUHVVLRQDVFRPSDUHGZLWK XQLYHUVDOJUDPPDU %XWLQVRIDUDVWUDQVIRUPDWLRQDOJHQHUDWLYHJUDPPDUPDLQWDLQHGDQGH[WHQGHG WKH DXWRQRPLVW SRVLWLRQ DGRSWHG E\ WKH LPPHGLDWH IROORZHUV RI %ORRPfiHOG UHSUHVHQWHG E\ WKH FRQWULEXWLRQV WR -RRV – WKRXJK WKLV LV DGPLWWHGO\ VFDUFHO\KRPRJHQHRXV ZKRDUHSUHVXPDEO\WREHLQFOXGHGLQWKHUHIHUHQWVRI KLV‘VWUXFWXUDOOLQJXLVWLFV’DQG‘PRGHUQGHVFULSWLYHOLQJXLVWLFV’LWFDQEHVDLGWR UHSUHVHQWDIXUWKHUVWHSEDFNIURPHQJDJLQJZLWKWKH‘SKLORVRSKLFDO’JUDPPDU WUDGLWLRQZKRVHLGHDVRQ‘XQLYHUVDOJUDPPDU’&KRPVN\DSSDUHQWO\KDVLQPLQG 7KHGHEWRIWUDQVIRUPDWLRQDOJUDPPDUWRWKH$PHULFDQVWUXFWXUDOLVWVZKRSUH FHGHGWKHPKDVEHHQXQGHUHVWLPDWHGWKHGHEWWR‘XQLYHUVDO’RU‘SKLORVRSKLFDO’ JUDPPDUKDVEHHQPXFKH[DJJHUDWHG%HIRUH,WDNHXSWKHH[WHQWRIWKHGHEW WRWKH‘%ORRPfiHOGLDQV’OHWXVFRQVLGHUWKHODFNRIWKHFODLPHGGHEWWR‘SKLOR VRSKLFDO’JUDPPDUV &KRPVN\ GHFODUHVWKDW‘,WKLQNWKDWZHKDYHPXFKWROHDUQIURP DFDUHIXOVWXG\RIZKDWZDVDFKLHYHGE\WKHXQLYHUVDOJUDPPDULDQVRIWKHVHY HQWHHQWKDQGHLJKWHHQWKFHQWXULHV’%XWKLVHTXDWLRQ LELG RI‘GHHSVWUXFWXUH’ ZLWKWKH‘XQGHUO\LQJ’FRQVWUXFWVRIWKHVHJUDPPDULDQVFDQQRWEHVDLGWRFRPH IURPVXFKD‘FDUHIXOVWXG\’$QGWKLVLPSUHVVLRQLVQRWGLVDEXVHGE\DUHDGLQJ RI&KRPVN\ D ,QGHHGSDVVDJHVOLNHWKHIROORZLQJFRQFHUQLQJWKH3RUW 5R\DO*UDPPDU /DQFHORW $UQDXOG PDNHTXLWHWUDQVSDUHQWWKHLQDS SURSULDWHQHVVRIVXFKDQHTXDWLRQ 7KHLGHQWLW\RIGHHSVWUXFWXUHXQGHUO\LQJDYDULHW\RIVXUIDFHIRUPVLQGLIIHUHQWODQ JXDJHVLVIUHTXHQWO\VWUHVVHGWKURXJKRXWWKLVSHULRGLQFRQQHFWLRQZLWKWKHSUREOHPRI KRZWKHVLJQLfiFDQWVHPDQWLFFRQQHFWLRQVDPRQJWKHHOHPHQWVRIVSHHFKDUHH[SUHVVHG &KDSWHU9, RI WKH 3RUW5R\DO *UDPPDU FRQVLGHUV WKH H[SUHVVLRQ RI WKHVH UHODWLRQV LQFDVHV\VWHPVDVLQWKHFODVVLFDOODQJXDJHVRUE\LQWHUQDOPRGLfiFDWLRQDVLQWKH FRQVWUXFWVWDWHLQ+HEUHZRUE\SDUWLFOHVDVLQWKHYHUQDFXODUODQJXDJHVRUVLPSO\ E\ fi[HG ZRUG RUGHU DV LQ WKH FDVH RI WKH VXEMHFWYHUE DQG YHUEREMHFW UHODWLRQV LQ )UHQFK…1RWLFHWKDWZKDWLVDVVXPHGLVWKHH[LVWHQFHRIDXQLIRUPVHWRIUHODWLRQV LQWRZKLFKZRUGVFDQHQWHULQDQ\ODQJXDJHWKHVHFRUUHVSRQGLQJWRWKHH[LJHQFLHVRI WKRXJKW7KHSKLORVRSKLFDOJUDPPDULDQVGRQRWWU\WRVKRZWKDWDOOODQJXDJHVOLWHUDOO\ KDYHFDVHV\VWHPVWKDWWKH\XVHLQflHFWLRQDOGHYLFHVWRH[SUHVVWKHVHUHODWLRQV2QWKH FRQWUDU\WKH\UHSHDWHGO\VWUHVVWKDWDFDVHV\VWHPLVRQO\RQHGHYLFHIRUH[SUHVVLQJ WKHVHUHODWLRQV D 7KH ‘UHODWLRQV’ H[SUHVVHG LQ WKLV YDULHW\ RI ZD\V DUH FOHDUO\ LQ &KRPVN\’V RZQ ZRUGV LW VHHPV ‘VHPDQWLF FRQQH[LRQV’ QRW HOHPHQWV LQ DQ DXWRQRPRXV ‘GHHS VWUXFWXUH’ WKH V\QWD[ RI VXFK ‘SKLORVRSKLFDO’ JUDPPDUV DUH JURXQGHG LQVHPDQWLFV&K9,RIWKH3RUW5R\DO*UDPPDURIIHUVQRWLRQDOGHfiQLWLRQVRI PRUSKRORJLFDOFDVHVDQGSUHSRVLWLRQVWKDWH[SUHVVWKHVH‘FRQQH[LRQV’MXVWDV WKHLPPHGLDWHO\SUHFHGLQJFKDSWHUVDUHFRQFHUQHGZLWKWKHVHPDQWLFGHfiQLWLRQ RIQRXQVDQGQXPEHUDQGJHQGHU%XW‘GHHSVWUXFWXUH’GRHVQRWfiJXUHDPRQJ WKH‘H[LJHQFLHVRIWKRXJKW’ ,WLVUDWKHUWKHDVVXPSWLRQWKDWJUDPPDULVVHPDQWLFDOO\JURXQGHGWKDWKDV PXFKLQFRPPRQZLWKYLHZVH[SUHVVHGLQWKHWUDGLWLRQRI‘SKLORVRSKLFDO’JUDP PDUVZKLFKflRZHUHGSDUWLFXODUO\LQWKHVHYHQWHHQWKDQGHLJKWHHQWKFHQWXULHV $ODWHUH[DPSOHRIWKHVHWKDWLVW\SLFDOLQWKLVUHVSHFWLV-DPHV+DUULV’+HUPHV ZKHUHKHDWWULEXWHVVHPDQWLFSURSHUWLHVWRWKHZRUGFODVVHV‘VXEVWDQFH’ IRU QRXQV ‘HQHUJ\’ IRU YHUEV FRPELQHG ZLWK ‘DVVHUWLRQ’ LQ WKH FDVH RI fiQLWH YHUEV HWF 6XFK LGHDV FDQ EH WUDFHG EDFN SDUWLFXODUO\ WKURXJK UHQDLVVDQFH ‘SKLORVRSKLFDO’JUDPPDULDQVWRWKHSKLORVRSKHUVRIFODVVLFDO*UHHFH
Recommended publications
  • Reference and Sense
    REFERENCE AND SENSE y two distinct ways of talking about the meaning of words y tlkitalking of SENSE=deali ng with relationshippggs inside language y talking of REFERENCE=dealing with reltilations hips bbtetween l. and the world y by means of reference a speaker indicates which things (including persons) are being talked about ege.g. My son is in the beech tree. II identifies persons identifies things y REFERENCE-relationship between the Enggplish expression ‘this p pgage’ and the thing you can hold between your finger and thumb (part of the world) y your left ear is the REFERENT of the phrase ‘your left ear’ while REFERENCE is the relationship between parts of a l. and things outside the l. y The same expression can be used to refer to different things- there are as many potential referents for the phrase ‘your left ear’ as there are pppeople in the world with left ears Many expressions can have VARIABLE REFERENCE y There are cases of expressions which in normal everyday conversation never refer to different things, i.e. which in most everyday situations that one can envisage have CONSTANT REFERENCE. y However, there is very little constancy of reference in l. Almost all of the fixing of reference comes from the context in which expressions are used. y Two different expressions can have the same referent class ica l example: ‘the MiMorning St’Star’ and ‘the Evening Star’ to refer to the planet Venus y SENSE of an expression is its place in a system of semantic relati onshi ps wit h other expressions in the l.
    [Show full text]
  • Two-Dimensionalism: Semantics and Metasemantics
    Two-Dimensionalism: Semantics and Metasemantics YEUNG, \y,ang -C-hun ...:' . '",~ ... ~ .. A Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfilment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Philosophy In Philosophy The Chinese University of Hong Kong January 2010 Abstract of thesis entitled: Two-Dimensionalism: Semantics and Metasemantics Submitted by YEUNG, Wang Chun for the degree of Master of Philosophy at the Chinese University of Hong Kong in July 2009 This ,thesis investigates problems surrounding the lively debate about how Kripke's examples of necessary a posteriori truths and contingent a priori truths should be explained. Two-dimensionalism is a recent development that offers a non-reductive analysis of such truths. The semantic interpretation of two-dimensionalism, proposed by Jackson and Chalmers, has certain 'descriptive' elements, which can be articulated in terms of the following three claims: (a) names and natural kind terms are reference-fixed by some associated properties, (b) these properties are known a priori by every competent speaker, and (c) these properties reflect the cognitive significance of sentences containing such terms. In this thesis, I argue against two arguments directed at such 'descriptive' elements, namely, The Argument from Ignorance and Error ('AlE'), and The Argument from Variability ('AV'). I thereby suggest that reference-fixing properties belong to the semantics of names and natural kind terms, and not to their metasemantics. Chapter 1 is a survey of some central notions related to the debate between descriptivism and direct reference theory, e.g. sense, reference, and rigidity. Chapter 2 outlines the two-dimensional approach and introduces the va~ieties of interpretations 11 of the two-dimensional framework.
    [Show full text]
  • Against Logical Form
    Against logical form Zolta´n Gendler Szabo´ Conceptions of logical form are stranded between extremes. On one side are those who think the logical form of a sentence has little to do with logic; on the other, those who think it has little to do with the sentence. Most of us would prefer a conception that strikes a balance: logical form that is an objective feature of a sentence and captures its logical character. I will argue that we cannot get what we want. What are these extreme conceptions? In linguistics, logical form is typically con- ceived of as a level of representation where ambiguities have been resolved. According to one highly developed view—Chomsky’s minimalism—logical form is one of the outputs of the derivation of a sentence. The derivation begins with a set of lexical items and after initial mergers it splits into two: on one branch phonological operations are applied without semantic effect; on the other are semantic operations without phono- logical realization. At the end of the first branch is phonological form, the input to the articulatory–perceptual system; and at the end of the second is logical form, the input to the conceptual–intentional system.1 Thus conceived, logical form encompasses all and only information required for interpretation. But semantic and logical information do not fully overlap. The connectives “and” and “but” are surely not synonyms, but the difference in meaning probably does not concern logic. On the other hand, it is of utmost logical importance whether “finitely many” or “equinumerous” are logical constants even though it is hard to see how this information could be essential for their interpretation.
    [Show full text]
  • Scope Ambiguity in Syntax and Semantics
    Scope Ambiguity in Syntax and Semantics Ling324 Reading: Meaning and Grammar, pg. 142-157 Is Scope Ambiguity Semantically Real? (1) Everyone loves someone. a. Wide scope reading of universal quantifier: ∀x[person(x) →∃y[person(y) ∧ love(x,y)]] b. Wide scope reading of existential quantifier: ∃y[person(y) ∧∀x[person(x) → love(x,y)]] 1 Could one semantic representation handle both the readings? • ∃y∀x reading entails ∀x∃y reading. ∀x∃y describes a more general situation where everyone has someone who s/he loves, and ∃y∀x describes a more specific situation where everyone loves the same person. • Then, couldn’t we say that Everyone loves someone is associated with the semantic representation that describes the more general reading, and the more specific reading obtains under an appropriate context? That is, couldn’t we say that Everyone loves someone is not semantically ambiguous, and its only semantic representation is the following? ∀x[person(x) →∃y[person(y) ∧ love(x,y)]] • After all, this semantic representation reflects the syntax: In syntax, everyone c-commands someone. In semantics, everyone scopes over someone. 2 Arguments for Real Scope Ambiguity • The semantic representation with the scope of quantifiers reflecting the order in which quantifiers occur in a sentence does not always represent the most general reading. (2) a. There was a name tag near every plate. b. A guard is standing in front of every gate. c. A student guide took every visitor to two museums. • Could we stipulate that when interpreting a sentence, no matter which order the quantifiers occur, always assign wide scope to every and narrow scope to some, two, etc.? 3 Arguments for Real Scope Ambiguity (cont.) • But in a negative sentence, ¬∀x∃y reading entails ¬∃y∀x reading.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Linguistics
    Philosophy of Linguistics Brian Rabern Philosophy DSB 4.04c 0131 651 5178 [email protected] Geoff Pullum Linguistics DSB 2.23 0131 650 3603 [email protected] Meetings The class meetings are from 11:00 to 13:00 each Wednesday from 19th September to 28th November in Old Library 2.19, Geography building, Old Infirmary complex (weeks 1–3 and 6–11) and in 01M.469 Teaching Room 12 (Doorway 3), Medical School building. Class meetings are mandatory. Readings Required reading is to be done before the class meets; background reading to be studied as time and specific interests permit. Assessment (i) short paper (1000-1500 words) to be turned in by 5 p.m. on Monday 15th October (topics will be provided); (ii) final essay examination with choice of questions from the whole of the course. Week 1 (19th September; Old Library 2.19): Introduction What linguistics is. Linguistics as a special science. Syntax and semantics as conceived in logic. Charles Morris’s trichotomy of syntax, semantics, and pragmatics. Philosophy of science applied to linguistics. Required reading • Hunter, Geoffrey (1971) Metalogic: An Introduction to the Metatheory of Standard First Order Logic (Berkeley: University of California Press), pp. 4–13. Background reading • Stainton, Robert (2014) ‘Philosophy of linguistics’, Oxford Handbooks Online. Online at https://works.bepress.com/robertstainton/126/ Week 2 (26th September; Old Library 2.19): Language and languages The metaphysics of linguistics. The vexed question of whether language should be regarded as psychological, social, or purely abstract. The descriptive linguistics of the American structuralists and the mentalist/cognitive backlash; ‘God’s truth’ (realism) vs.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Logic of Two-Dimensional Semantics
    Matrices and Modalities: On the Logic of Two-Dimensional Semantics MSc Thesis (Afstudeerscriptie) written by Peter Fritz (born March 4, 1984 in Ludwigsburg, Germany) under the supervision of Dr Paul Dekker and Prof Dr Yde Venema, and submitted to the Board of Examiners in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MSc in Logic at the Universiteit van Amsterdam. Date of the public defense: Members of the Thesis Committee: June 29, 2011 Dr Paul Dekker Dr Emar Maier Dr Alessandra Palmigiano Prof Dr Frank Veltman Prof Dr Yde Venema Abstract Two-dimensional semantics is a theory in the philosophy of language that pro- vides an account of meaning which is sensitive to the distinction between ne- cessity and apriority. Usually, this theory is presented in an informal manner. In this thesis, I take first steps in formalizing it, and use the formalization to present some considerations in favor of two-dimensional semantics. To do so, I define a semantics for a propositional modal logic with operators for the modalities of necessity, actuality, and apriority that captures the relevant ideas of two-dimensional semantics. I use this to show that some criticisms of two- dimensional semantics that claim that the theory is incoherent are not justified. I also axiomatize the logic, and compare it to the most important proposals in the literature that define similar logics. To indicate that two-dimensional semantics is a plausible semantic theory, I give an argument that shows that all theorems of the logic can be philosophically justified independently of two-dimensional semantics. Acknowledgements I thank my supervisors Paul Dekker and Yde Venema for their help and encour- agement in preparing this thesis.
    [Show full text]
  • The End of Wittgenstein's Tractatus Logico
    Living in Silence: the End of Wittgenstein’s Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus and Lecture on Ethics Johanna Schakenraad Ludwig Wittgenstein’s Tractatus logico-philosophicus starts as a book on logic and (the limits of) language. In the first years after publication (in 1921) it was primarily read as a work aiming to put an end to nonsensical language and all kinds of metaphysical speculation. For this reason it had a great influence on the logical positivists of the Vienna Circle. But for Wittgenstein himself it had another and more important purpose. In 1919 he had sent his manuscript to Ludwig von Ficker, the publisher of the literary journal der Brenner, hoping that Ficker would consider publishing the Tractatus. In the accompanying letter he explains how he wishes his book to be understood. He thinks it is necessary to give an explanation of his book because the content might seem strange to Ficker, but, he writes: In reality, it isn’t strange to you, for the point of the book is ethical. I once wanted to give a few words in the foreword which now actually are not in it, which, however, I’ll write to you now because they might be a key to you: I wanted to write that my work consists of two parts: of the one which is here, and of everything which I have not written. And precisely this second part is the important one. For the Ethical is delimited from within, as it were, by my book; and I’m convinced that, strictly speaking, it can ONLY be delimited in this way.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Reference 1. the Phenomenon Of
    1 Reference 1. The phenomenon of reference In a paper evaluating animal communication systems, Hockett and Altmann (1968) presented a list of what they found to be the distinctive characteristics which, collectively, define what it is to be a human language. Among the characteristics is the phenomenon of "aboutness", that is, in using a human language we talk about things that are external to ourselves. This not only includes things that we find in our immediate environment, but also things that are displaced in time and space. For example, at this moment I can just as easily talk about Tahiti or the planet Pluto, neither of which are in my immediate environment nor ever have been, as I can about this telephone before me or the computer I am using at this moment. Temporal displacement is similar: it would seem I can as easily talk about Abraham Lincoln or Julius Caesar, neither a contemporary of mine, as I can of former president Bill Clinton, or my good friend John, who are contemporaries of mine. This notion of aboutness is, intuitively, lacking in some contrasting instances. For example, it is easy to think that animal communication systems lack this characteristic—that the mating call of the male cardinal may be caused by a certain biological urge, and may serve as a signal that attracts mates, but the call itself is (putatively) not about either of those things. Or, consider an example from human behavior. I hit my thumb with a hammer while attempting to drive in a nail. I say, "Ouch!" In so doing I am saying this because of the pain, and I am communicating to anyone within earshot that I am in pain, but the word ouch itself is not about the pain I feel.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 7 Linguistics As a Science of Structure Ryan M
    Chapter 7 Linguistics as a science of structure Ryan M. Nefdt University of the Western Cape Generative linguistics has rapidly changed during the course of a relatively short period. This has caused many to question its scientific status as a realist scientific theory (Stokhof & van Lambalgen 2011; Lappin et al. 2000). In this chapter, I argue against this conclusion. Specifically, I claim that the mathematical foundations of the science present a different story below the surface. I agree with critics that due to the major shifts in theory over the past 80 years, linguistics is indeed opened up to the problem of pessimistic meta-induction or radical theory change. However, I further argue that a structural realist approach (Ladyman 1998; French 2006) can save the field from this problem and at the same time capture its structural nature. I discuss particular historical instances of theory change in generative grammar as evidence for this interpretation and finally attempt to extend it beyond the gener- ative tradition to encompass previous frameworks in linguistics. 1 Introduction The generativist revolution in linguistics started in the mid-1950s, inspired in large part by insights from mathematical logic and in particular proof theory. Since then, generative linguistics has become a dominant paradigm, with many connections to both the formal and natural sciences. At the centre of the newly established discipline was the syntactic or formal engine, the structures of which were revealed through modelling grammatical form. The generativist paradigm in linguistics initially relied heavily upon the proof-theoretic techniques intro- duced by Emil Post and other formal logicians to model the form language takes (Tomalin 2006; Pullum 2011; 2013).1 Yet despite these aforementioned formal be- ginnings, the generative theory of linguistics has changed its commitments quite 1Here my focus will largely be on the formal history of generative syntax but I will make some comments on other aspects of linguistics along the way.
    [Show full text]
  • The Ambiguous Nature of Language
    International J. Soc. Sci. & Education 2017 Vol.7 Issue 4, ISSN: 2223-4934 E and 2227-393X Print The Ambiguous Nature of Language By Mohammad Awwad Applied Linguistics, English Department, Lebanese University, Beirut, LEBANON. [email protected] Abstract Linguistic ambiguity is rendered as a problematic issue since it hinders precise language processing. Ambiguity leads to a confusion of ideas in the reader’s mind when he struggles to decide on the precise meaning intended behind an utterance. In the literature relevant to the topic, no clear classification of linguistic ambiguity can be traced, for what is considered syntactic ambiguity, for some linguists, falls under pragmatic ambiguity for others; what is rendered as lexical ambiguity for some linguists is perceived as semantic ambiguity for others and still as unambiguous to few. The problematic issue, hence, can be recapitulated in the abstruseness hovering around what is linguistic ambiguity, what is not, and what comprises each type of ambiguity in language. The present study aimed at propounding lucid classification of ambiguity types according to their function in context by delving into ambiguity types which are displayed in English words, phrases, clauses, and sentences. converges in an attempt to disambiguate English language structures, and thus provide learners with a better language processing outcome and enhance teachers with a more facile and lucid teaching task. Keywords: linguistic ambiguity, language processing. 1. Introduction Ambiguity is derived from ‘ambiagotatem’ in Latin which combined ‘ambi’ and ‘ago’ each word meaning ‘around’ or ‘by’ (Atlas,1989) , and thus the concept of ambiguity is hesitation, doubt, or uncertainty and that concept associated the term ‘ambiguous’ from the first usage until the most recent linguistic definition.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle on Verbal Communication: the First Chapters of De Interpretatione
    EJPC 7 (2) pp. 239–253 Intellect Limited 2016 Empedocles: European Journal for the Philosophy of Communication Volume 7 Number 2 © 2016 Intellect Ltd Critical Review. English language. doi: 10.1386/ejpc.7.2.239_3 CRITICAL REVIEW ANITA KASABOVA Sofia University VLADIMIR MARINOV New Bulgarian University Aristotle on verbal communication: The first chapters of De Interpretatione ABSTRACT KEYWORDS This article deals with the communicational aspects of Aristotle’s theory of significa- Aristotle tion as laid out in the initial chapters of the De Interpretatione (Int.).1 We begin De Interpretatione by outlining the reception and main interpretations of the chapters under discussion, verbal communication rather siding with the linguistic strand. We then argue that the first four chap- signification ters present an account of verbal communication, in which words signify things via linguistic expressions thoughts. We show how Aristotle determines voice as a conventional and hence acci- convention dental medium of signification: words as ‘spoken sounds’ are tokens of thoughts, language use which in turn are signs or natural likenesses of things. We argue that, in this way, 1. We follow the standard linguistic expressions may both signify thoughts and refer to things. This double edition of the Greek account of signification also explains the variety of ontological, logical and psycho- text of Int. by Minio- logical interpretations of the initial chapters of Int. Paluello (1949: 47–72), unless otherwise stated. All references to Aristotle’s works 239 11_EJPC 7.2_Critical review article_239-253.indd 239 11/22/16 1:55 PM Anita Kasabova and Vladimir Marinov follow the citation 1.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is a Speech Act? 1 2
    WHAT IS A SPEECH ACT? 1 2 What is a Speech Act? John Searle I. Introduction n a typical speech situation involving a speaker, a hearer, and an utterance by the speaker, there are many kinds of acts associated with Ithe speaker’s utterance. The speaker will characteristically have moved his jaw and tongue and made noises. In addition, he will characteristically have performed some acts within the class which includes informing or irritating or boring his hearers; he will further characteristically have performed acts within the class which includes referring to Kennedy or Khrushchev or the North Pole; and he will also have performed acts within the class which includes making statements, asking questions, issuing commands, giving reports, greeting, and warning. The members of this last class are what Austin1 called illocutionary acts and it is with this class that I shall be concerned in this paper, so the paper might have been called ‘What is an Illocutionary Act?’ I do not attempt to defi ne the expression ‘illocutionary act’, although if my analysis of a particular illocutionary act succeeds it may provide the basis for a defi nition. Some of the English verbs and verb phrases associated with illocutionary acts are: state, assert, describe, warn, remark, comment, command, order, request, criticize, apologize, censure, approve, welcome, promise, express approval, and express regret. Austin claimed that there were over a thousand such expressions in English. By way of introduction, perhaps I can say why I think it is of interest and importance in the philosophy of language to study speech acts, or, as they are sometimes called, language acts or linguistic acts.
    [Show full text]