Ordinal Utility Utility Theory Conditions Construction

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Ordinal Utility Utility Theory Conditions Construction Utility Theory • For consumer theory do not need to assign precise numerical values to different indifference curves Ordinal Utility • Often convenient to do so especially if dealing with more than 2 goods • To do this, it is convenient to represent the ECON 370: Microeconomic Theory preference relation by a utility function U(x1,x2,…) Summer 2004 – Rice University Stanley Gilbert Lecture 2 Econ 370 - Ordinal Utility 2 Conditions Construction • U(x) is a utility function representing the • Construction of a utility function: preference relation ‘≿’: – Draw the indifference curves – U(x) ≥ U(y) if and only if x y ≿ – Drawing the diagonal (i.e. the line x1 = x2) – For preferences that satisfy A1 – A4 – Labeling each indifference curve with how far from the origin the intersection of that indifference curve and the diagonal it is. Econ 370 - Ordinal Utility 3 Econ 370 - Ordinal Utility 4 1 Identical Representations Equivalence • Many different utility functions can describe same • Our model of consumer behavior would be exactly set of preferences the same whichever of these utility functions were assumed. • Any monotonic transformation of a utility function is still a utility function • See that: U a (x) = [U(x)]2 + 42 • For Example: U ()x = x1x2 a 2 2 b 1 2 U ()x = 4x1 x2 + 42 U (x) = [U(x)] U b ()x = (x x )1 2 1 2 U c (x) = ln[U(x)] c U ()x = ln x1 + ln x2 All three are monotonic transformations of U(x). Econ 370 - Ordinal Utility 5 Econ 370 - Ordinal Utility 6 Characteristics Interpersonal Comparisons • Consumer theory depends only on the shapes of • An associated issue is that of interpersonal indifference curves and the direction in which comparability: utility is increasing (normally northeast). Most – If Jack consumes cans of soda and pizzas and prefers more of each good to less, we can conclude that he economists argue that precise numerical values would prefer 3 cans of soda and 2 pizzas per day to 1 attached to individual indifference curves have no can of soda and 1 pizza per day economic meaning – Suppose, however, that we have two consumers Jack and Jill and Jack consumes 3 cans of soda and 2 pizzas • Because the ordering of indifference curves is all per day while Jill consumes 1 can of soda and 1 pizza that is important, this is described as an ordinal per day. Can we say Jack is happier? theory of utility • There is no objective (i.e. value-free) way to • That is, it can only be used to rank choices for a compare the happiness of the two people single individual • In our analysis we treat utility functions as ordinal Econ 370 - Ordinal Utility 7 Econ 370 - Ordinal Utility 8 2 Common Utility Functions Indifference Curves • Perfect Substitutes: • If we have a utility function u = f(x1, x2): – U(x) = ax + bx a, b > 0 1 2 • Indifference curves are represented by • Perfect Complements: – c = f(x1, x2) – U(x) = min{ ax1, bx2} a, b > 0 – Where ‘c’ is some constant • Cobb-Douglas Preferences α 1 - α – U(x) = x1 x2 0 ≤ α≤ 1 – U(x) = αln(x1) + (1 – α)ln(x2) 0 ≤ α≤ 1 – (Why are these equivalent?) • Quasilinear Preferences – U(x) = x1 + f(x2) Econ 370 - Ordinal Utility 9 Econ 370 - Ordinal Utility 10 Marginal Utility Marginal Utilities and the MRS • Marginal means “incremental”. • The equation of an indifference curve is U(x1,x2) ≡ k, a constant. • MUi = change in U with small change in xi (holding constant consumption of all other goods) • Totally differentiating this identity gives ∂ U MU i = ∂ xi ∂U ∂U dx1 + dx2 = 0 or ∂x1 ∂x2 • For example, if U(x , x ) = x 1/2x 2 1 2 1 2 dx ∂U / ∂x MU (x ) MRS = 2 = − 1 = − 1 • Then, MU(x ) = (½)x -1/2x 2 1 1 2 dx1 ∂U /∂x2 MU (x2 ) 1/2 • And, MU(x2) = 2x1 x2 Econ 370 - Ordinal Utility 11 Econ 370 - Ordinal Utility 12 3 Example of Marginal Utilities and MRS Monotonic Transformations and MRS • Suppose U(x1,x2) = x1x2. Then • Monotonic transformation of U does not change underlying preference structure • Example: U(x1, x2) = x1x2 with MRS = - x2/x1. ∂ U = (1)(x ) = x 2, 2 2 2 2 • Consider V = U or V(x1, x2) = x1 x2 : ∂ x1 2 ∂ V /∂ x1 2x1x2 x2 ∂ U MRS = − = − 2 = − = (x1)(1) = x1 ∂ V /∂ x2 2x1 x2 x1 ∂ x2 d x ∂ U /∂ x x • This is the same as the MRS for U. so MRS = 2 = − 1 = − 2 d x1 ∂ U /∂ x2 x1 • Monotonic transformation does not change MRS. Econ 370 - Ordinal Utility 13 Econ 370 - Ordinal Utility 14 4.
Recommended publications
  • Download?Doi=10.1.1.467.8745&Rep=Rep1&Type=Pdf (Accessed on 7 April 2021)
    Journal of Risk and Financial Management Article The Standard Model of Rational Risky Decision-Making Kazem Falahati Glasgow School for Business and Society, Glasgow Caledonian University, 70 Cowcaddens Road, Glasgow G4 0BA, UK; [email protected]; Tel.: +44-141-331-3708 Abstract: Expected utility theory (EUT) is currently the standard framework which formally defines rational decision-making under risky conditions. EUT uses a theoretical device called von Neumann– Morgenstern utility function, where concepts of function and random variable are employed in their pre-set-theoretic senses. Any von Neumann–Morgenstern utility function thus derived is claimed to transform a non-degenerate random variable into its certainty equivalent. However, there can be no certainty equivalent for a non-degenerate random variable by the set-theoretic definition of a random variable, whilst the continuity axiom of EUT implies the existence of such a certainty equivalent. This paper also demonstrates that rational behaviour under utility theory is incompatible with scarcity of resources, making behaviour consistent with EUT irrational and justifying persistent external inconsistencies of EUT. A brief description of a new paradigm which can resolve the problems of the standard paradigm is presented. These include resolutions of such anomalies as instant endowment effect, asymmetric valuation of gains and losses, intransitivity of preferences, profit puzzle as well as the St. Petersburg paradox. Keywords: decision-making; rationality; risk; expected utility; behavioural puzzles MSC Codes: 62Cxx; 90B50; 91A26; 91B02; 91B06; 91B16; 91B30 Citation: Falahati, Kazem. 2021. The JEL Codes: C00; D01; D81 Standard Model of Rational Risky Decision-Making. Journal of Risk and Financial Management 14: 158.
    [Show full text]
  • Updating Rules for Non-Bayesian Preferences
    Updating Rules for Non-Bayesian Preferences. Tan Wang∗ December, 1999 Abstract We axiomatize updating rules for preferences that are not necessarily in the expected utility class. Two sets of results are presented. The first is the axiomatization and representation of conditional preferences. The second consists of the axiomatization of three updating rules: the traditional Bayesian rule, the Dempster-Shafer rule, and the generalized Bayesian rule. The last rule can be regarded as the updating rule for the multi-prior expected utility (Gilboa and Schmeidler (1989)). The operational merit of it is that it is equivalent to updating each prior by the traditional Bayesian rule. ∗Tan Wang is with the Faculty of Commerce and Business Administration, University of British Columbia, Van- couver, British Columbia, Canada, V6T 1Z2. [email protected]. The author is grateful to the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada for financial support. 1 Introduction The traditional approach to updating is the Bayesian rule. This approach is justified by the ax- iomatic treatment of Savage (1954), where it is shown that, in situations of uncertainty, if a decision maker’s preference satisfies a certain set of axioms, his preference can be represented by an expected utility with respect to a subjective probability measure and that probability measure represents the decision maker’s belief about the likelihood of events. Moreover, in light of new information, the decision maker updates his belief according the Bayesian rule. This Savage paradigm has been the foundation of much of the economic theories under uncertainty. At the same time, however, the Savage paradigm has been challenged by behavior exhibited in Ellsberg paradox (Ellsberg (1961)), which seems to question the very notion of representing a decision maker’s belief by a probability measure and hence by implication the validity of the Bayesian rule.
    [Show full text]
  • Economics 142: Choice Under Uncertainty (Or Certainty) Winter 2008 Vincent Crawford (With Very Large Debts to Matthew Rabin and Especially Botond Koszegi)
    Economics 142: Choice under Uncertainty (or Certainty) Winter 2008 Vincent Crawford (with very large debts to Matthew Rabin and especially Botond Koszegi) Background: Classical theory of choice under certainty Rational choice (complete, transitive, and continuous preferences) over certain outcomes and representation of preferences via maximization of an ordinal utility function of outcomes. The individual makes choices “as if” to maximize the utility function; utility maximization is just a compact, tractable way for us to describe the individual’s choices in various settings. We can view the utility function as a compact way of storing intuition about behavior from simple experiments or though-experiments and transporting it to new situations. The preferences represented can be anything—self-interested or not, increasing in intuitive directions (more income or consumption) or not—although there are strong conventions in mainstream economics about what they are normally defined over—own income or consumption rather than both own and others’, levels of final outcomes rather than changes. Thus if you think the mainstream approach is narrow or wrong-headed, it may make as much or more sense to complain about those conventions than about the idea of rationality per se. Background: Classical “expected utility” theory of choice under uncertainty This is the standard way to describe people’s preferences over uncertain outcomes. The Marschak reading on the reading list, linked on the course page, is a readable introduction. The basic idea is that
    [Show full text]
  • Welfare Goal in Antitrust Journals.Sagepub.Com/Home/Abx
    The Antitrust Bulletin 1-39 ª The Author(s) 2018 The Unsound Theory Behind Article reuse guidelines: sagepub.com/journals-permissions the Consumer (and Total) DOI: 10.1177/0003603X18807802 Welfare Goal in Antitrust journals.sagepub.com/home/abx Mark Glick* Abstract This is the first installment of a two-part commentary on the New Brandeis School (the “New Brandeisians”) in Antitrust. In this first part, I examine why the New Brandeisians are correct to reject the consumer welfare standard. Instead of arguing, as the New Brandeisians do, that the consumer welfare standard leads to unacceptable outcomes, I argue that the consumer or total welfare standard was theoretically flawed and unrigorous from the start. My basic argument is that antitrust law addresses the impact of business strategies in markets where there are winners and losers. For example, in the classical exclusionary monopolist case, the monopolist’s conduct is enjoined to increase competition in the affected market or markets. As a result of the intervention, consumers benefit, but the monopolist is worse off. One hundred years of analysis by the welfare economists themselves shows that in such situations “welfare” or “consumer welfare” cannot be used as a reliable guide to assess the results of antitrust policy. Pareto Optimality does not apply in these situations because there are losers. Absent an ability to divine “cardinal utility” from obser- vations of market behavior, other approaches such as consumer surplus, and compensating and equivalent variation cannot be coherently extended from the individual level to markets. The Kaldor-Hicks compensation principle that is in standard use in law and economics was created to address problems of interpersonal comparisons of utility and the existence of winners and losers.
    [Show full text]
  • Economic Theory, Ideal Types, and Rationality
    Lansana Keita Economic Theory, Ideal Types, and Rationality Abstract: Contemporary economic theory is generally regarded as a scien­ tific or at least potentially so. The replacing of the cardinal theory of utility measurement by the ordinal theory was supposed to prepare the groundwork for economics as a genuine science. But in adopting the ordinal approach, theorists saw fit to anchor ordinal theory to axioms of choice founded on principles of rational behavior. Behavior according to these axioms was embodied in the ideal type model of rational economic man. This model served the basis for scientific explanation of the choices made by actual economic agents. I argue though that the postulate of rationality is a normative principle and that this compromises the scientific pre­ tensions of economic theory. Yet the theorist must rely on this principle to formulate predictive and explanatory theories. This raises questions as to whether it is possible that economic theory satisfy the same kind of scientific criteria set down for research in the natural sciences. I. It is generally assumed that of all the social sciences, econom­ ics is the most promising candidate for acceptance as a science. Theories in economics conform to the formal requirements de­ manded of theories in natural science in the sense that they possess basic postulates, axioms and laws whose function is to describe at a fundamental level some segment of the empir­ ical world particular to the discipline itself. Predictive and explanatory theories are then constructed from these posited axioms and postulates. For example, microeconomic theory which is founded on a set of axioms of choice purports to predict and explain the behavior of the consumer and that of the entre­ preneur.
    [Show full text]
  • Ordinal Utility and the Traditional Theory of Consumer Demand1 Donald W
    real-world economics review, issue no. 67 subscribe for free Ordinal utility and the traditional theory of consumer demand1 Donald W. Katzner [University of Massachusetts/Amherst, USA] Copyright: Donald W. Katzner, 2014 You may post comments on this paper at http://rwer.wordpress.com/comments-on-rwer-issue-no-67/ In an earlier issue of this Journal, Jonathan Barzilai, in a paper entitled, “Inapplicable Operations on Ordinal, Cardinal, and Expected Utility” [see reference 2], has raised important issues regarding ordinal utility, and correctly clarified the meaning of the general notion of ordinality in terms of the mathematical theory of measurement. In that process, he has also subjected the traditional theory of consumer demand to serious attack. Barzilai's assault on traditional consumer theory, which is based on the mathematical theory of measurement, is useful because it brings to the fore the fact that, for economists, there is a second notion of ordinal utility, older than and independent of the mathematical-theory-of-measurement concept, and which is the relevant one for the traditional theory of consumer demand. That older approach seems to have had widespread acceptance among economists before the newer mathematical approach was known to them. The essence of Barzilai's attack consists of the claims that: 1. The function values of the utility function in that theory are ordinal and cannot, according to the mathematical theory of measurement, be subjected to arithmetic operations. This means that, since the reckoning of derivatives requires subtraction and division of function values, the derivatives of the ordinal utility function cannot be calculated.
    [Show full text]
  • On Ordinal Utility, Cardinal Utility, and Random Utility
    This is a repository copy of On ordinal utility, cardinal utility, and random utility . White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/2544/ Article: Batley, R. (2007) On ordinal utility, cardinal utility, and random utility. Theory and Decision, Online. ISSN 1573-7187 https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-007-9046-2 Reuse See Attached Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ White Rose Research Online http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ Institute of Transport Studies University of Leeds This is an author produced version of a paper published in Theory and Decision Journal. It has been peer reviewed but does not include the final publishers formatting and pagination. White Rose Repository URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/2544/ Published paper Batley, Richard (2007) On ordinal utility, cardinal utility, and random utility. Theory and Decision, Online First, May 2007 White Rose Consortium ePrints Repository [email protected] Onordinalutility,cardinalutility,andrandomutility RichardBatley InstituteforTransportStudies,UniversityofLeeds,UK [email protected] ABSTRACT ThoughtheRandomUtilityModel(RUM)wasconceivedentirelyintermsof ordinal utility, the apparatus through which it is widely practised exhibits properties of cardinal utility.The adoption of cardinal utility as a working operation of ordinal is perfectly valid, provided interpretations drawnfrom thatoperationremainfaithfultoordinalutility.Thepaperconsiderswhether the latter requirement holds true for several measurements commonly derivedfromRUM.Inparticularitisfoundthatmeasurementsofconsumer surplus change may depart from ordinal utility, and exploit the cardinality inherentinthepracticalapparatus.
    [Show full text]
  • Were the Ordinalists Wrong About Welfare Economics?
    journal of Economic Literature Vol. XXII (June 1984), pp. 507-530 Were the Ordinalists Wrong About Welfare Economics? By ROBERT COOTER University of California, Berkeley and PETER RAPPOPORT New York University Useful comments on earlier drafts were provided by Sean Flaherty, Marcia Marley, Tim Scanlon, Andrew Schotter, Mark Schankerman, Lloyd Ulman and two anonymous referees. We are grateful to the National Science Foundation and the C. V. Starr Center at New York University for financial support. Responsibility for accuracy rests with the authors. pE DEVELOPMENT of utility theory has economics.1 The intuitive idea of scientific experienced two definitive episodes: progress is that new theories are discov­ the "marginalist revolution" of the 1870s ered that explain more than old theories. and the "Hicksian" or "ordinalist revolu­ We shall contend that the ordinalist revo­ tion" of the 1930s. While the first event lution was not scientific progress in this established a central place for utility the­ sense. For example, the older school was ory in economics, the second restricted concerned with economic policies to the concept of utility acceptable to eco­ bring about income redistribution and al­ nomics. The term "ordinalist revolution" leviate poverty, and the ordinalists did not refers to the rejection of cardinal notions offer a more general theory for solving of utility and to the general acceptance these problems. Instead, the trick that car­ of the position that utility was not compa­ ried the day for the ordinalists was to ar­ rable across individuals. The purpose gue that the questions asked by the older of this paper is to analyze the events school, and the answers which they gave, comprising the ordinalist revolution with 1 For example, Kenneth Arrow, referring to the a view to determining whether they earlier school, wrote: achieved the advances in economic sci­ .
    [Show full text]
  • Ordinal Space, Utility, and Consumer Demand: a Clarifying Note
    Munich Personal RePEc Archive Ordinal Space, Utility, and Consumer Demand: A Clarifying Note Dominique, C-Rene Laval University (ret.) 11 November 2016 Online at https://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/75030/ MPRA Paper No. 75030, posted 12 Nov 2016 07:06 UTC ORDINAL SPACE, UTILITY, AND CONSUMER DEMAND: A CLARIFYING NOTE C-René Dominique Laval University (ret.), Cité Universitaire, Québec, Canada G1K SUMMARY: Concepts such as marginal utility, expected-utility, etc. are severely criticized in some quarters where economists are accused of performing mathematical operations in ordinal spaces. Haplessly, economists’ counter- claims are far from being substantive. This note shows that there exists an order-isomorphism relating preference ordering to a substantive set of real numbers and thus obviates the need for a utility index. KEYWORDS: Ordinal Spaces, Binary Relation, Poset, Total Pre-ordering, Isomorphisms. JEL Classification: D10, D11. INTRODUCTION: In a few recent papers, Barzilai (2010, 2011, 2013) reminds us that on ordinal spaces (non Euclidean) only relations are defined and, therefore, all elementary mathematical operations are inapplicable, including concepts of algebra and calculus. Thus, if norms, metrics, derivatives, convexity concepts, etc. are undefined in ordinal spaces, then ordinal utility functions are not differentiable. Consequently, works on decision theory by von Neumann and Morgenstern (1944), Pareto (1971), Hicks (1946), Samuelson (1948), and Debreu (1954) are based on fundamental errors. So stated, Barzilai then accuses these economists and their followers of misidentifying mathematical spaces, and of drawing erroneous conclusions such as the derivation of individual demand functions and their properties from constrained utility maximization. Katzner (2014) took issue with these claims, arguing in return that Barzilai’s criticism is founded on the general notion of ordinality arising out of the mathematical theory of measurement.
    [Show full text]
  • Economics, Psychology, and the History of Demand Theory
    Economics, Psychology, and the History of Consumer Choice Theory Paper for Conference on The History of Recent Economics (HISRECO) University of Paris X June 22-24, 2007 D. Wade Hands Department of Economics University of Puget Sound Tacoma, WA 98416 USA [email protected] May 2007 Version 2.0 13,693 Words Draft for discussion purposes only. Please do not quote. Earlier versions of this paper were presented at the European Association for Evolutionary Political Economy Conference in Istanbul, Turkey, in November 2006 and at the Whittemore School of Business and Economics, University of New Hampshire, in February 2007. I would like to thank John Davis, Harro Maas, and a number of people in the audience at Istanbul and UNH for helpful comments. 0. Introduction The relationship between psychology and consumer choice theory has been long and tumultuous: a veritable seesaw of estrangement and warm reconciliation. Starting with the British neoclassicism of Jevons and Edgeworth, and moving to contemporary economic theory, it appears that psychology was quite in, then clearly out, and now (possibly) coming back in. If one moves farther back in time and takes the view that the classical tradition was grounded in a natural – and thus non-social, non-mental, and non– psychological – order (Schabas 2005), then the scorecard becomes out, in, out, and (possibly) back in. A tumultuous relationship indeed. The purpose of this paper is to provide a critical examination of this turbulent relationship. The argument is presented in three parts. The first section provides a summary of the standard story about the relationship between psychology and consumer choice theory from the early neoclassicals to the present time.
    [Show full text]
  • BA 513: Ph.D. Seminar on Choice Theory Professor Robert Nau Fall Semester 2008
    BA 513: Ph.D. Seminar on Choice Theory Professor Robert Nau Fall Semester 2008 Notes and readings for class #2: axioms of subjective probability, expected utility, and subjective expected utility (revised January 11, 2008) In the last class we saw how ordinal utility functions, introduced by the marginalist economists in the 1870’s, could be used to model choice problems involving purchase and exchange under conditions of certainty. In this class, we will consider the main elements of the theory of choice under risk and uncertainty that were developed in the mid-1900’s: the theories of subjective probability, expected utility, and subjective expected utility. The primary readings are historical perspectives on these developments and are worth reading somewhat carefully. The secondary readings are excerpts from the original masterworks: they are worth skimming through (or at least reading the introductory parts) to get an appreciation for how the authors framed the problems for themselves. Primary readings 1a. Excerpt on von Neumann’s “sturm und drang” period from Prisoner’s Dilemma by William Poundstone 1b. “Classic and current notions of measurable utility” by Daniel Ellsberg (1954) 1c. “Retrospective on the utility theory of von Neumann and Morgenstern” by Peter Fishburn, 1989 1d. “The Invention of the Independence Condition for Preferences” by Peter Wakker and Peter Fishburn, 1995 Supplementary reading 2a. “Foresight: its logical laws, its subjective sources” by Bruno de Finetti, 1937 (mainly chapter I) 2b. Excerpt from Theory of Games and Economic Behavior by von Neumann and Morgenstern, 1947 2c. Excerpts from The Foundations of Statistics by Leonard J. Savage, 1954 2.1 Historical background We have seen that some elements of rational choice theory had already been developed by the end of the 19th Century (and even much earlier).
    [Show full text]
  • Mathematical Economics - Marginal Analysis in the Consumer Behavior Theory
    Munich Personal RePEc Archive Mathematical Economics - Marginal analysis in the consumer behavior theory Marques, Jorge and Pascoal, Rui CeBER, University of Coimbra, CeBER, University of Coimbra 2018 Online at https://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/96442/ MPRA Paper No. 96442, posted 10 Oct 2019 07:15 UTC Mathematical Economics - Marginal analysis in the consumer behavior theory Jorge Marques CeBER and FEUC, University of Coimbra, Portugal Rui Pascoal CeBER and FEUC, University of Coimbra, Portugal Abstract In the neoclassical theory, the economic value of a good is determined by the benefit that an individual consumer attributes to the last ("marginal") unit consumed. Marginal analysis was introduced to the theory of value by William Jevons, Carl Menger and Léon Walras, the founders of marginalism. Since the so-called “marginalist revolution” of the 1870s, differential (or infinitesimal) calculus has been applied to the mathematical modelling of economic theories. Our goal is to present some consumer behavior models, their advantages and limitations, using the methodology of economic science. It should be emphasized that each (re)formulation is based on different economic principles: diminishing marginal utility, diminishing marginal rate of substitution and weak axiom of revealed preference. 1. Introduction Economics is the social science that has incorporated the most mathematics into its theories and models. The formulation and application of mathematical methods to represent economic principles gave rise to a new area of study called Mathematical Economics. The theory of value was one of the first theories to be analyzed using a mathematical framework. The so-called “marginalist revolution” in Economics, at the beginning of the 1870s, is intimately related to the use of differential (or infinitesimal) calculus.
    [Show full text]