Syd Barrington 27 November 2018 Demosthenes

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Syd Barrington 27 November 2018 Demosthenes Barrington 1 Syd Barrington 27 November 2018 Demosthenes: Orator and Politician Demosthenes was born in 384 BC to Demosthenes, a wealthy Greek factory owner, and Cleobule, a supposed Scythian. He would eventually be called a “Greek speaking barbarian” (Jaeger, 23) by Aeschines, because he was not of full Greek blood. After Demosthenes father died when he was 7, he left Demosthenes to three legal guardians, so that he, and his inheritance, were well taken care of. However, when Demosthenes came of age he was only given a small percentage of his father's money. His three guardians, Aphobus, Demophon, nephews of Demosthenes father, and Therippides, a close friend of his father, had taken property of the estate for themselves and mishandle the rest, and the value of his inheritance decreased. He decided then to learn rhetoric so he could bring his guardians to court, and because he could not do as most healthy, young Greeks boys did; he also was weak and his mother would not let him go out to the gymnasia for fear of him getting harmed. When Callistratus the orator went to trial against Oropus, Demosthenes convinced his rhetoric teacher to let him go with him and it was here that Demosthenes witnessed Callistratus win his case and he decided that he too wanted a well-known reputation as a great orator. He then became a pupil of Isaeus, a logographer. He did not study under Isocrates because their view points in politics were different and he would have much rather studied directly under someone and learn ever bit possible than a generic education of rhetoric school declamations. At Barrington 2 the age of 18, he filed his court cases against each of his guardians; however, he shortly thereafter had to serve his military term, as “Attic law forbade his carrying on any lawsuits during these years” (Jaeger, 26). Finally, Demosthenes took each of his guardians to court in order to prove his father's estate was worth much more than his guardians had given him. His first speeches were for each separate court trials in which he attacked his guardians and successfully won, yet he did not receive what was due to him. He took a liking to public speaking and continued to do so. Yet when he was first starting, “he was interrupted by their clamours and laughed at for his inexperience, since his discourse seemed to them confused by long periods and too harshly and immoderately tortured by formal arguments” (Plutarch, 849). Demosthenes also had a weak voice and shortness of breath, which embarrassed him greatly, so greatly that he received advice from Satyrus, and actor, who gave him certain phrases to repeat. This lead Demosthenes on the journey of bettering not only his voice, but also his public speaking, as he would conceal himself in an underground study to practice his diction and delivery of sentences. He cured himself from his lisp by speaking with rocks in his mouth, he would speak phrases in one breath, and he would speak in front of a mirror to see the delivery of his own words. He would “[shave] one side of his head in order that shame might keep him from going abroad even though he greatly wished to do so” (Plutarch, 849). Demosthenes became very thoughtful throughout this process as well. He would rarely answer someone when called upon, unless he had had time to think and process all aspects. Nevertheless, Plutarch recalls in his biography of Demosthenes, that “those orations which were spoken off-hand by him had more courage and boldness than those which he wrote out” (Plutarch, 850), which shows his utter passion in what he is doing. Barrington 3 Demosthenes went from being an orator to the world of politics around the age of 32. He had began court career after handling his cases successfully, and he then studied speech-writing until he felt he could go into politics. Demosthenes taught a private group rhetoric, as he was extremely well versed in it from all of his studying. As Jaeger states, “He knew how to find in everything something from which he could learn” (Jaeger, 31). Demosthenes would not appear in court for private cases because he didn not want to influence judges; writers of speeches were never named, so he could write for many people, but he would never show up to the trial. The turn to politics was a conscious turning point in Demosthenes life. He became a speaker and proposed new things to the Assembly, for the Assembly asked him, and his other associates, to come up with a new political program. Demosthenes believed in the opposition to how things were running in Athens, and he made that opinion heard; he pointed out the financial issues, struggles with the Assembly's rejections of fixes that could potentially better the system, and the foreign policies. He wanted to recover from the Greek’s failed financial system, rebuild confidence in politics and business, and conserve the resources of the state. Demosthenes four greatest speeches in politics were of/relating to foreign policy,and it was at this time that he went head to head with Aeschines. Aeschines brought Demosthenes to trial multiple times because of disputes he and Demosthenes had created amongst themselves. (In 330 Aeschines was exiled after trying to veto a crown that was being given to Demosthenes on behalf of his devotion to Athens). Demosthenes speeches were passionate and thought out, and it was clear to see that Demosthenes was very invested in politics at this point despite his nontraditional start. Plutarch did however call Demosthenes, “unstable in his character and unable to remain true for any Barrington 4 length of time to the same policies or the same men”. Demosthenes wrote many speeches having to do with tax laws (Against Androtion and Against Leptines) and government corruption ​ ​ ​ ​ (Against Timocrates and Against Aristocrates). Demosthenes also went head to head with ​ ​ ​ ​ Eubulus, an extremely well known politician, for he wanted to form an alliance with Megalopolis against Thebes. Demosthenes was interested in a foreign policies for the good of Athen’s, which was a new perspective for Athenians. He could be very compelling in spreading his opinion which lead many persons to point out that “we cannot often be sure what the facts were or make up our mind how we should vote, even when we have the speeches on both sides of a case, as sometimes happens” (Luce, 419). He continuously wrote many other persuading speeches and became extremely relied upon for his input. Demosthenes died in 322 after he escaped from being prosecuted as a Macedonian agitator, and fled to an island. There, he was surrounded by assassins and committed suicide by poison. One significant event that shaped Demosthenes life was when he locked himself in an underground room and practiced his speaking. In Plutarch’s biography he talked of how Demosthenes was criticised by the public when he first began speaking. He was embarrassed because of this and his speech impediment. I found it very surprising that he would lock himself in a room for months on end to fix this. I realize that there were not speech therapists in Athens, but for him to decide to constantly practice, for days on end, was very astounding. He was considered weak and fragile by his mother, and that he would sit inside and read and study rather than go to the gymnasia with the other young boys. Therefore he was very intelligent, though his body was weak. He clearly had wanted to go into being a logographer from early adulthood, and if he could not deliver a speech in such a manner, then it was also clear to see that he would stop Barrington 5 at nothing. It was noted that he got rid of his lisp by speaking phrases over and over again with pebbles in his mouth. His determination really sticks out as an important characteristic of his life. This experience led him to be patient and thoughtful as he repeated phrases over and over. Many ancient historians reflected on this and said that he had to think about the subject matter long before he would give his input. Another significant turning point in his life was when he went from being an orator to being a statesman. This switched was not only because he had gained lots of trust and fame, but because his hardwork in studying and practicing speeches brought him there. He no longer had to be anonymous, for his work could now help influence the state and people would know who came up with said ideas. Demosthenes was not always one sided, but he was good at making his point clear no matter whose side he was on. He was very persuasive and tried to help Athens in multiple wars with his input. He enjoyed the idea of building up Athens foreign policy, so wars with other city-states and empires was something he was very passionate about. He tried to help Athens in their economic terms, but he had to go head to head with one of Athens most intelligent persons, Eubulus. He and Eubulus fought back and forth with reforms and policies. I believe these two were extremely intelligent, and very much alike in the sense that they were both passionate about their jobs/duties. Though they were on opposing sides, I think that they had Athens on their minds, for they were patriotic and cared for their city. I believe the main goal of Demosthenes was to have Athens always be the powerhouse, and to gain back the city’s freedom when it was conquered by the Macedonians, for he never wanted to be under the Macedonian rule.
Recommended publications
  • Introduction: Oratory and Law at Athens
    Introduction: Oratory and Law at Athens One of the many intriguing (and unique) aspects of Athenian law is that our information about it comes very largely from speeches composed for delivery in court. These date to the period 420-320,1 and reflect in part the high value the Greeks in all periods placed on effective speaking. Even Achilles, whose fame rested primarily on his martial superiority, was brought up to be “a speaker of words and a doer of deeds” (Iliad 9.443). Great Athenian leaders like Themistocles and Pericles were accomplished public speakers; and epic poetry, tragedy, comedy, and history all made frequent use of set speeches. The formal pleadings of the envoys to Achilles in Iliad Book Nine, the messenger speeches in tragedy reporting events like the battle of Salamis in Aeschylus’ Persians, and Pericles’ funeral oration in Thucydides’ History are but a few indications of the Greeks’ never-ending fascination with the spoken word, and with formal public speaking in particular, which reached its height in the public oratory of the fifth and fourth centuries. I. Oratory2 Originally, oratory was not a specialized subject of study but was learned by practice and example. The formal study of rhetoric as an “art” (technē) began, we are told, in the middle of the fifth century in Sicily with Corax and his pupil Tisias.3 These two are scarcely more than names to us, but another Sicilian, Gorgias of Leontini (c. 490-390), developed a dazzling new style of speech and argument. Gorgias initiated the practice, which continued into the early fourth century, of composing speeches for mythical or imaginary occasions.
    [Show full text]
  • Goneis in Athenian Law (And Perception)
    GONEIS IN ATHENIAN LAW (AND PERCEPTION) David Whitehead Queen’s University Belfast [email protected] Abstract: This paper aims to establish what the laws of classical Athens meant when they used the term goneis. A longstanding and widespread orthodoxy holds that, despite the simple and largely unproblematic “dictionary” definition of the noun goneus/goneis as parent/parents, Athenian law extended it beyond an individual’s father and mother, so as to include – if they were still alive – protection and respect for his or her grandparents, and even great-grandparents. While this is not a notion of self-evident absurdity, I challenge it on two associated counts, one broad and one narrow. On a general, contextual level, genre-by genre survey and analysis of the evidence for what goneus means (and implies) in everyday life and usage shows, in respect of the word itself, an irresistible thrust in favour of the literal ‘parent’ sense. Why then think otherwise? Because of confusion, in modern minds, engendered by Plato and by Isaeus. In Plato’s case, his legislation for Magnesia contemplates (I argue) legal protection for grandparents but does not, by that mere fact, extend the denotation of goneis to them. And crucially for a proper understanding of the law(s) of Athens itself, two much-cited passages in the lawcourt speeches of Isaeus, 1.39 and 8.32, turn out to be the sole foundation for the modern misunderstanding about the legal scope of goneis. They should be recognised for what they are: passages where law is secondary and rhetorical persuasion paramount.
    [Show full text]
  • Isocrates and the Rhetorical Creation of Europe: the Medium As
    Isocrates & Europe - 1 Isocrates and the Rhetorical Creation of Europe: The Medium as Message I. Introduction: Overview The idea that Isocrates helped create the concept of transnationalism that fostered Europe both as an idea and as an eventual political union is common fare in rhetorical studies. De Romilly (1992) writes that “Isocrates was perhaps the first in antiquity to focus his political theories on the idea of Europe” (p. 2). Isocrates anticipated “the idea of Europe” (Hariman, 2004, p. 231) and used the words Europen and Europes 13 times in his essays. But, to date, critical exploration of Isocrates’ role in developing the idea of Europe has primarily dealt with the content of his works – with his eloquent and relentless focus on panhellenism and the related conflict between Europe and Asia. This paper, however, will focus on medium rather than message. It will focus on Isocrates’ pioneering use of a new medium – written documents/syggrammata – and the role that the new rhetorical medium played in forming Europe. The most famous passage in the Isocratean canon, the so-called Hymn to Logos (Jaeger, 1944/1971), which first appeared in Nicocles (5-9) and was repeated in Antidosis (253-257), holds that speech/logos is a civic and political unifier, by means of which “we have come together and founded cities and made laws and invented arts” (Nicocles 6). Yet before Isocrates, who was “the first individual who could be termed a ‘writer’ in the modern sense of the term” (Lentz, 1989), logos and its community-building powers Isocrates & Europe - 2 traveled primarily orally: Cities, alliances, arts, and laws were built through face-to-face communication.
    [Show full text]
  • "Bringing-Before-The-Eyes": Visuality and Audience in Greek Rhetoric By
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by ASU Digital Repository "Bringing-before-the-eyes": Visuality and Audience in Greek Rhetoric by Brent D. Chappelow A Dissertation Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy Approved April 2016 by the Graduate Supervisory Committee: Shirley K Rose, Co-Chair Kathleen S. Lamp, Co-Chair Maureen Daly Goggin ARIZONA STATE UNIVERSITY May 2016 ABSTRACT "Bringing-before-the-eyes": Visuality and Audience in Greek Rhetoric examines how Greek rhetorical theories are understood through the lens of visuality and the ways in which orators accounted for audience knowledges and expectations in the creation of rhetorical texts and performances. Through a close reading of Greek rhetorical texts from the classical period, I develop three heuristics for analyzing the ways in which rhetoricians invite and encourage visualized images through rhetorical practice. By exploring (1) language cues that orators use to signal visualization, (2) the ways in which shared cultural memories and ideas allow orators to call upon standardized images, and (3) the influence of stylistic choices and audience emotions related to the vividness of rhetorical images, I argue that it is possible to analyze the ways in which classical Greek orators understood and employed visual elements in their rhetorical performances. I then conduct an analysis of the visual aspects of Demosthenes' On the Embassy using these heuristics to demonstrate the ways in which these three aspects of visuality are intertwined and contribute to a greater understanding of the relationship between the verbal and the visual in rhetorical theory.
    [Show full text]
  • Medical Language in the Speeches of Demosthenes Allison Das a Dissertation Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirement
    Medical Language in the Speeches of Demosthenes Allison Das A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Washington 2015 Reading Committee: Ruby Blondell, Chair Deborah Kamen Alexander Hollmann Program Authorized to Offer Degree: Classics Department Allison Das ii ©Copyright 2015 Allison E. Das Allison Das iii University of Washington Abstract Medical Language in the Speeches of Demosthenes Allison E. Das Chair of Supervisory Committee Dr. Ruby Blondell Classics Department Introduction This project is intended as an examination of medical language and imagery in the speeches of Demosthenes, with special attention given to his speeches against his political opponent Aeschines, Against the False Embassy (19) and On the Crown (18). In Chapter 1, I contextualize his use of such language and imagery by exploring the influence of Hippocratic medicine on fourth- and fifth-century non-medical literature. I argue that the shared anxieties of medicine and politics, namely that both arts demand quick action and foresight on the part of the good practitioner, and the rich new vocabulary of suffering and disease, made Hippocratic medicine an enticing model for the political writer, that is, the historian, philosopher, and orator. Demosthenes' medical language and imagery should thus be seen as part of a tradition of analogizing the two arts, which began during the circulation of the first Hippocratic treatises and continued well into and past his own day. Allison Das iv In Chapter 2, I look at medical language and imagery in Demosthenes' prosecution of Aeschines for political misconduct during the Second Embassy to Philip II of Macedon, On the False Embassy.
    [Show full text]
  • Athenian Homicide Rhetoric in Context
    ATHENIAN HOMICIDE RHETORIC IN CONTEXT BY CHRISTINE C. PLASTOW Thesis submitted to University College London for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy DEPARTMENT OF GREEK AND LATIN UNIVERSITY COLLEGE LONDON 1 DECLARATION I, Christine C. Plastow, confirm that the work presented in this thesis is my own. Where information has been derived from other sources, I confirm that this has been indicated in the thesis. Signed: --------------------------------------------------------------------------- 2 ABSTRACT Homicide is a potent crime in any society, and classical Athens was no exception. The Athenians implemented legal methods for dealing with homicide that were set apart from the rest of their legal system, including separate courts, long-established laws, and rigorous procedures. We have, however, limited extant sources on these issues, including only five speeches from trials for homicide. This has fomented debate regarding aspects of law and procedure, and rhetoric as it relates specifically to homicide has not been examined in detail. Here, I intend to examine how the nature of homicide and its prosecution at Athens may have affected rhetoric when discussing homicide in forensic oratory. First, I will establish what I will call the ideology of homicide at Athens: the set of beliefs and perceptions that are most commonly attached to homicide and its prosecution. Then, I will examine homicide rhetoric from three angles: religious pollution, which was believed to adhere to those who committed homicide; relevance, as speakers in the homicide courts were subject to particular restrictions in this regard; and motive and intent, related issues that appear frequently in rhetoric and, in some cases, define the nature of a homicide charge.
    [Show full text]
  • Interstate Alliances of the Fourth-Century BCE Greek World: a Socio-Cultural Perspective
    City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works All Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects 9-2016 Interstate Alliances of the Fourth-Century BCE Greek World: A Socio-Cultural Perspective Nicholas D. Cross The Graduate Center, City University of New York How does access to this work benefit ou?y Let us know! More information about this work at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu/gc_etds/1479 Discover additional works at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu This work is made publicly available by the City University of New York (CUNY). Contact: [email protected] INTERSTATE ALLIANCES IN THE FOURTH-CENTURY BCE GREEK WORLD: A SOCIO-CULTURAL PERSPECTIVE by Nicholas D. Cross A dissertation submitted to the Graduate Faculty in History in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, The City University of New York 2016 © 2016 Nicholas D. Cross All Rights Reserved ii Interstate Alliances in the Fourth-Century BCE Greek World: A Socio-Cultural Perspective by Nicholas D. Cross This manuscript has been read and accepted for the Graduate Faculty in History in satisfaction of the dissertation requirement for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. ______________ __________________________________________ Date Jennifer Roberts Chair of Examining Committee ______________ __________________________________________ Date Helena Rosenblatt Executive Officer Supervisory Committee Joel Allen Liv Yarrow THE CITY UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK iii ABSTRACT Interstate Alliances of the Fourth-Century BCE Greek World: A Socio-Cultural Perspective by Nicholas D. Cross Adviser: Professor Jennifer Roberts This dissertation offers a reassessment of interstate alliances (συµµαχία) in the fourth-century BCE Greek world from a socio-cultural perspective.
    [Show full text]
  • Antiphon the Sophist the Fragments
    ANTIPHON THE SOPHIST THE FRAGMENTS EDITED WITH INTRODUCTION, TRANSLATION, AND COMMENTARY BY GERARD J. PENDRICK published by the press syndicate of the university of cambridge The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge, United Kingdom cambridge university press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge cb22ru,UK 40 West 20th Street, New York ny 10011-4211, USA 477 Williamstown Road, Port Melbourne, vic 3207, Australia Ruiz de AlarcoÂn 13, 28014 Madrid, Spain Dock House, The Waterfront, Cape Town 8001, South Africa http://www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 2002 This book is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published 2002 Reprinted 2003 Printed in the United Kingdom at the University Press, Cambridge Typeset in Baskerville and New Hellenic Greek [ao] A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Library of Congress Cataloguing in Publication data Antiphon, of Athens. The fragments / Antiphon the Sophist ; edited with introduction, translation and commentary by Gerard J. Pendrick. p. cm. Ð DCambridge classical texts and commentaries ; 39) Includes bibliographical references and indexes. isbn 0521651611 1. Sophists DGreek philosophy) 2. Philosophy, Ancient. i.Title: Antiphon the Sophist. ii. Pendrick, Gerard J. iii. Title. iv. Series. pa3870. a22001 1830.1Ðdc21 2001035690 isbn 0521651611 CONTENTS Preface page ix INTRODUCTION 1 I The identity of Antiphon 1 II Division of works 26 III On Truth 32 IV On Concord 39 V Politicus 47 VI Dream-book 49 VII Antiphon's thought in its ®fth-century context 53 TEXTS AND TRANSLATIONS 69 COMMENTARY 225 WORKS CITED 431 INDEXES 458 vii INTRODUCTION I THE IDENTITY OF ANTIPHON Among the plethora of Antiphons known from the later ®fth andthe fourth centuries bc, particularly at Athens, are several who have often been confused, in antiquity as well as in modern scholarship.
    [Show full text]
  • The Ancient Tradition on the Identity of Antiphon , Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies, 31:1 (1990:Spring) P.27
    GAGARIN, MICHAEL, The Ancient Tradition on the Identity of Antiphon , Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies, 31:1 (1990:Spring) p.27 The Ancient Tradition on the Identity of Antiphon Michael Gagarin 0NG MANY Antiphons known from antiquity, two fifth­ .Ncentury figures are sometimes thought to be the same person: Antiphon of Rhamnus, an orator and a leader of the oligarchic coup in 411, and 'Antiphon the Sophist', one of Socrates' interlocutors in Xenophon (M em. 1.6) to whom are often attributed the works On Truth, On Concord, and Politicus. 1 The separatist case has usually been based on the papyrus fragments of On Truth, but the most recent separatist argument, by Gerard Pendrick,2 deals almost entirely with the ancient tradition. He concedes that "the majority of ancient opinion is unitarian" (59), but he accords this fact little weight and presents instead a selective discussion of ancient authors who, in his view, support a separatist position. The purpose of this paper is to offer a more comprehensive assessment of the ancient tradition and to show that ancient opinion was more strongly unitarian than Pendrick implies. 3 As far as we can tell, the only separatist views expressed in antiquity were based on stylistic criteria alone, the inadequacy of which is evident, and a unitarian position is taken for granted 1 The partial listing in REI (1894) 2526-30 (ef Suppl. 1 [1903J 93f on the orator and Suppl. 4 [1924J 33-43 on the papyrus fragments from On Truth) gives 18 Antiphons, some of whom may be the same person.
    [Show full text]
  • Historical Review I: from Ancient Greece Through Rome
    2 Historical Review I: From Ancient Greece through Rome This chapter traces the evolution of thought on style from Ancient Greece through the end of antiquity, emphasizing primary texts and interpretations by contemporary historians. Teachers may want to consult the classical treatises described here to develop a sense of what style has meant to different rhetoricians over time. Most of the authors of these treatises were themselves educators and, even if they do not provide particular instructions about how to teach style, their discus- sions of this canon directly impact promoting the value of style in con- temporary college classrooms. These treatises take a range of positions regarding the importance of style to the overall theorizing and teach- ing of rhetoric and writing. Some treatises address style as a small part of a larger rhetorical system, some discuss style as a substantial means of developing arguments, and others are devoted entirely to style, and see it as the most central aspect of effective discourse. Aristotle treated style as one small component of rhetoric, and em- phasized clarity and plainness. By contrast, later rhetoricians such as Demetrius, Longinus, and (much later) Erasmus elevated style as a significant rhetorical tool, encouraging students to develop a wide rep- ertoire of rhetorical devices to enhance their persuasiveness with dif- ferent audiences. The Roman rhetorician Quintilian’s Education of the Orator remains the most thorough and comprehensive catalog of sty- listic devices and their appropriate use in different rhetorical situations. A discussion of St. Augustine’s adaptation of the classical tradition for preaching concludes this chapter.
    [Show full text]
  • A Few Aspects of Well-Known Athenian Isonomia in Ancient Greece and Its Opposition to the Profession of a Logographer
    Scripta Neophilologica Posnaniensia. Tom XVI, strony: 207–218 Wydział Neofilologii, Uniwersytet im. Adama Mickiewicza w Poznaniu, 2016 DOI 10.7169/snp.2016.16.15 A FEW ASPECTS OF WELL-KNOWN ATHENIAN ISONOMIA IN ANCIENT GREECE AND ITS OPPOSITION TO THE PROFESSION OF A LOGOGRAPHER KRYSTYNA TUSZYŃSKA At the beginning of my article I should explain two terms used in the history of ancient Greek culture, that is LOGOGRAPHOS and ISONOMIA. Neither of them is definite. The first one, the Greek technical term LOGOGRAPHOS (English „lo- gographer‟), was in the history of literature popularized by German philologist and archaeologist Georg Friedrich (1771–1858) and was considered to have been connected with two kinds of literary men: (1) the Ionian writer telling stories before Herodotus and (2) the paid speech writer in Athens in the fifth and fourth century B.C. The first meaning is of little interest to us: the authors of the first ethnographical and geographical works did not distinguish facts from fiction; they are, nevertheless, the oldest prose writers in Greek literature. In the opinion of Thucydides, logogra- phers composed their works with a purpose to impress the audience rather than to present the truth (Peloponnesian War, book I, 21.1). The second term is linked with Athenian jurisdiction. The moral value of this term is my main interest in this article. The well-known Greek word ISONOMIA popularly meant no more than „equality before the law‟1. The term is usually related to Greek democracy, but, interestingly, it was used not only in reference to Athenian democracy and not only by Athenian writers.
    [Show full text]
  • Legal Profession in Ancient Athens Anton-Hermann Chroust
    Notre Dame Law Review Volume 29 | Issue 3 Article 2 5-1-1954 Legal Profession in Ancient Athens Anton-Hermann Chroust Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.nd.edu/ndlr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Anton-Hermann Chroust, Legal Profession in Ancient Athens, 29 Notre Dame L. Rev. 339 (1954). Available at: http://scholarship.law.nd.edu/ndlr/vol29/iss3/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by NDLScholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in Notre Dame Law Review by an authorized administrator of NDLScholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. NOTRE DAME LAWYER A QuarterlyLaw Review VOL. XXIX SPRING, 1954 No. 3 THE LEGAL PROFESSION IN ANCIENT ATHENS Introduction T raditionally, the lawyer has three main functions: he may be the expert adviser (counselor) as to how his client should defend or bring legal proceedings, and as to how he should conduct legal transactions; he may be the skilled agent (attorney, solicitor, or proctor) who prepares these legal transactions or even conducts them for his client, as well as prepares cases in advance of trial; or he may be the experienced advocate who presents the case of his client to the court. Naturally, at different times and in different places some, if not all, of these basic functions of the lawyer are either unknown or simply outlawed. In addition, a class of real - that is, professional, expert, intelligent, and skillful - lawyers cannot possibly be found until there has been de- veloped something like a settled jurisdiction with regular courts, a consistent legal procedure, and a distinct body of laws.
    [Show full text]