<<

CAN MORAL B E GROUNDED O N ?

By Gordon H. Clark Butler University

Among moral prescriptions common opinion would include the sixth, sev- enth, and eighth of the Ten Commandments. Thou shalt not kill, thou shalt not commit adultery, and thou shalt not steal, have usually been regarded as important moral laws. An orthodox Christian or an orthodox Jew can sincerely and consistently inculcate these laws because he them to be the laws of God. They are right because God has commanded them. And they are laws because God imposes penalties for their transgression. Thus moral education can consistently be grounded on Biblical .

Humanism, naturalism, or obviously does not have this ground for , nor does it uniformly accept these laws. Professor Edwin A. Burtt, himself a humanist, in both editions of his Types of Religious Phil- osophy, indicates the repudiation of Biblical morality by reporting that the more radical humanists regard "sex as an essentially harmless pleasure which should be regulated only by personal and preference.** Sim- ilarly t h e political radicalism of many naturalists in attacking private and advocating confiscatory taxation a n d the redistribution of wealth is a thinly disguised defense of legalized theft. And it is not diffi- cult to identify godless governments which make constant use of murder. Naturalism therefore seems to be consistent with a repudiation of, the Ten C ommandments.

No doubt many humanists in America disapprove of the brutality and mur- der inherent in communism. Some may even have a kind word for private property. And some would not condone adultery. But the problem that naturalism must face is this: Can an empirical , a philosophy that repudiates revelation, an instrumentalist or descriptive philosophy provide a ground -- I do not say for the Ten Commandments -- but for any moral prescriptions whatever? Or do the humanists* arguments that place sexual in the sphere of purely personal preference also imply that all the of life are equally a of private taste ?

The empirical method in axiology can only begin with the discovery in ex- perience of so-called values. and friendship, health and material comfort, are frequently so identified. The precise identification, however, is not the crucial point. These so-called values are all descriptive facts. Burtt discovers in h i s a preference for art and friendship. Someone else may not art at all. Similarly, personal preference varies between monogamy and adultery. And Stalin shows a preference for murder. As Gardner Williams of the University of Toledo, in his vol- ume, Humanistic (p. 6), says, "Selfish ambition, or the w i l l to power, when successful, is intrinsically satisfactory.** Thus murder, as much as friendship, is a value because it has been discovered as a value in experience. How then can a theory which restricts itself to descriptive facts provide grounds for normative prescriptions? If the of an argument is the descriptive fact that someone likes something, by what could one arrive at the conclusion that other people ought to like*the same thing? Any syllogism with a normative conclusion requires a nor- mative premise.

Some naturalists, perhaps most naturalists today, attempt to avoid this patent fallacy by speaking of obligation as a social demand. Instead of de- pending on Almighty God to impose sanctions, these naturalists depend on society. However, the attempt to base morality on society not only fails to

21 . avoid the fallacy but it faces other difficulties as well. In the first place, if morality is a demand of society, one must indicate which society. Is it the demand of the family, the church, the nation, or all humanity ? It can hardly be all humanity, for two . There are no demands which are clearly demands of humanity. Humanity, if it speaks at all, speaks in such an indistinct and ambiguous language that no specific obligation can be proved. And second, if society is to take the place of God as the source of sanctions, then obviously humanity cannot be the basis of obligation, for humanity imposes no sanctions. Therefore an ethical theory based on social demand must appeal to family, church, or nation. Of these three the nation is m o s t a b l e to impose sanctions. Hense morality becomes loyalty to the State, and m u r d e r , adultery, and theft become moral obliga- tions when Nazism, F a s c i s m , and Communism demand them. In the next place, this appeal to society is itself without basis. Where is the argument to establish an individual's obligation to any society? It may be prudent to act so as to avoid penalties, but even the most totalitarian state iá not totally efficient. When possible therefore, disobedience to social custom or even an attempt to overthrow the State may be justified. In any case, a man may commit suicide. How can any society obligate an individual to continue living? Dr. J e r o m e Nathanson, executive secretar y of the Ethical Culture Society, seeing that not everyone will be converted to Christianity, asks orthodox Christians to submerge their faith and c o - operate in a m o r a l enterprise to salvage the world from its present plight. Whether one believes in God or not, still he must go on and try to make the world a fit place in which to live. This appeal grossly begs the ques- tion. Indeed it contains an obviously false . It is not t r ue that we must go on and try to improve the world. We do not have to go on. We can quit the world. It is h e r e that Dr. Nathanson shuts his eyes to the problem. Is life worth-while if there is no God? He thinks so, but hu- manism seems to have no argument to support this . The question reappears, namely, if God be banished, how can society obligate anyone to keep on living? This question seems unanswerable, and instead of C h r i s - tians too polite to ask embarrassing questions, they should repeat this one insistently. F u r t h e r, even if a does not commit suicide, but prefers to live, how can society obligate him to sacrifice his ease for the improvement of the world? If naturalism can do no better than to call such people social sponges and other derogatory , as W. H. Kilpat- rick does, it has abandoned rational argument and can provide no basis for moral education.

In spite of the ethical speculation of the last hundred y e a r s , the best at- tempt to base ethics on , social demands, individual , and all without benefit oí revelation, is still Bentham*s . Ben- tham that all men universally d e s i r e pleasure. This assertion of a single common end supposedly puts all men under a common obligation. On this general basis the right and wrong in specific instances is to be d e - termined by calculating consequences. Murder, adultery, and theft would presumably be means to , and thus m o r a l education would be possible.

Unfortunately for naturalism all such attempts a r e failures because there is no empirical knowledge sufficient to brand m u r d e r as wrong and private property as right. Any empirical calculation to foster the life in all affected by one's conduct is a vain dream. Even if it were true that murder and theft frequently result in pain to the perpetrator, it is clear that this is not universally true. Hitler may have suffered for his murders and confiscations; b u t Stalin lived to a ripe old age, enjoying the almost perfect fruition of his vengeful plans. Few adherents of Bibli- cal morality can boast of such empirical success. Indeed, even in the case of Hitler, h i s final catastrophe included, what purely naturalistic

22 argument could show that his life was not better than the lives of the six million Jews he murdered? He enjoyed excitement, wealth, and power for several years, and suffered only a few moments. Is not this a better life than that of his pitiful victims? Unless there is an Almighty God to i m - pose inescapable penalties on transgressors, why should we not praise the rich, full, stimulating, dangerous life of a dictator ?

Any theory therefore which denies divine sanctions for violation of divine law not only fails to condemn murder, adultery, and theft, but in addition fails to establish any or common distinction between right and wrong. Naturalism therefore cannot serve as a ground for Christian mor- als, not can it serve as a ground even for the inculcation of the personal preferences of its exponents. In an empirical, descriptive philosophy, one may find the verb is; but the verb ought has no logical standing.

Notices The Evangelical Theological Society, in 1956, went on record as favoring institutional support for representation at E.T.S. meetings. Should any member of the Society request that the administration of his institution be notified of this action, the E.T.S. secretary will be happy to do so.

Executive Committee of E.T.S. will meet at 10:30 a.m., Tuesday, Dec. 30, 1958, at the Nyack Missionary College. Dr. Leon Morris, well known evangelical writer, scholar, and teacher of Ridley College, Victoria, Australia, plans to be in the United States during the year I960 and would welcome speaking opportunities at the institutions represented in E.T.S. E.T.S. directory, Vol. V, is planned for issuance the first of next year. So that the listings may be up to date and in the form desired, would all those associated with E.T.S. kindly indicate any changes or corrections on the form below and clip and return to the secretary by Dec. 1^1958. If there are no changes or corrections, please disregard this n o t i c e . Thank you.

J. Barton Payne, S e c , ETS 1726 W. Berteau Ave. Chicago 13, 111.

Change in address from that which is on this Bulletin Changes in status from that which is listed in the 1957 directory and 1958 supplement; or, if a new member, from that which is on application form: Higher degree(s) received: , . Changes in position and/or institution:

In field of major interest:

Books Published: Title Publisher Date

» »

» • »

Name: