The Interpretation of Plato's Hippias Major”

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Interpretation of Plato's Hippias Major” Abstract Travis John Mulroy “Delusions of Grandeur: The Interpretation of Plato's Hippias Major” My dissertation is an interpretation of Plato’s Hippias Major, in which Socrates investigates τό καλόν (usually translated as “the beautiful” or “the noble”). My reading of the Hippias Major focuses on the importance of appearing beautiful, to others and thereby to oneself, and reveals the way in which the impulse to appear beautiful is connected to the desire for the immortal preservation of oneself and one’s own. The impulse to appear beautiful is essential to political life, insofar as the pleasure of praise effects a kind of harmony between the private good and the common. This impulse, however, is also a fundamental impediment to Socratic philosophy, as it prevents the critical examination of oneself and one’s opinions, while hindering a truly erotic experience of the beautiful. In examining these issues, my dissertation seeks to establish the Hippias Major’s connection to and consonance with other more popular Platonic dialogues, such as the Republic, Symposium, and Phaedo. Acknowledgements I would like to thank all the friends and colleagues who have helped deepen my understanding of Plato. I am especially grateful to Professor Ronna Burger for her invaluable assistance, in matters both theoretical and practical. She exemplifies the serious play of philosophy, and I consider myself very fortunate to have had the opportunity to study with her at Tulane University. And finally, I could not have finished this work without the constant love and support of my parents, David and Mary, whose faith – I’m sure – never wavered. I dedicate this study to them. ii Delusions of Grandeur: The Interpretation of Plato’s Hippias Major Table of Contents Acknowledgments……………………………………………………………………………………………….. ii Introduction: On the Difficulty of Beautiful Things………..……………………………………… 1 Part One: Beautiful Wholes Section I (281a1 – 283b4): Wisdom and the Good….……………………………………………. 6 Section II (283b4 – 285b7): Persuasion and Paternal Law…………………………………….. 16 Section III (285b7 – 286c3): Beneficial Education ………………………………………………… 30 Section IV (286c3 – 287e3): Posing the Question, “What is the Beautiful?.............. 43 Section V (287e3 – 289c8): Hippias’ First Answer, a Beautiful Virgin.…………………… 59 Section VI (289c9 – 291c8): Hippias’ Second Answer, Gold.…………………………………. 82 Section VII (291c9 – 293c7): Hippias’ Third Answer, To Be Honored with Funeral Rites…………………………………………………………………………………………….. 111 Part Two: Autopsy of the Beautiful Section VIII (293c7 – 295b7): The Refuter’s Suggestion, the Fitting and the Nature of the Fitting Itself………………………………………………………………………… 139 Section IX (295b7 – 297d9): Socrates’ First Answer, the Useful, the Powerful, and the Beneficial…………………………………………………………………………………….. 159 Section X (297d10 – 304a3): Socrates’ Second Answer, the Pleasant through Hearing and Sight…………………………………………………………………………………….. 194 Section XI (304a3 – 304e9): Hippias’ Indictment and Socrates’ Apology.……………… 218 Endnotes……………………………………………………………………………………………………………… 232 Bibliography…………………………………………………………………………………………………………. 247 iii 1 Introduction: On the Difficulty of Beautiful Things In Plato’s Hippias Major, Socrates poses the question τί ἐστι τοῦτο τὸ καλόν – what is this thing, the beautiful? This question is so important that Socrates repeatedly suggests life is not worth living for anyone who cannot answer it.1 Even a cursory reading of Plato’s dialogues confirms that the nature of the beautiful is a fundamental question for Socratic philosophy. The Hippias Major is the only Platonic dialogue explicitly devoted to answering this question, and so it plays a particularly important role in the Platonic corpus. Despite these considerations, the Hippias Major has been generally ignored by contemporary scholarship. This is due in large part to the fact that the dialogue features a number of characteristics that many scholars deem “Un-Platonic.” The style, for instance, has struck some as so overly comic and crude that they have rejected the dialogue as spurious. In so doing, these scholars bear a striking similarity to Hippias himself, who rejects Socrates’ questions about a lowly pot because they are inappropriate to a refined discussion. Be that as it may, the Hippias Major does present interpreters with a number of difficulties, which at first blush can make the dialogue seem idiosyncratic and disordered. These appearances have led scholars to question the value, if not authenticity, of the dialogue, and as a result the Hippias Major has not received the attention it deserves.2 2 The task of demonstrating the true value of the Hippias Major and the task of understanding what Plato intends to convey by means of the dialogue require the same thing. One must resolve the apparent difficulties by explaining how even the most seemingly inappropriate or incongruous parts of the dialogue are in fact fitting, and how the dialogue as whole forms a rich and coherent consideration of the nature of beauty, despite any initial appearances to the contrary.3 To this end, it is helpful to begin by simply enumerating the main difficulties and questions posed by the dialogue. An immediate difficulty arises in even trying to articulate Socrates’ primary question in the Hippias Major, due to an ambiguity in the idea being examined, τὸ καλόν. The meaning and connotations of τὸ καλόν are so broad that choosing an English translation is unusually problematic. The idea of τὸ καλόν has an important aesthetic sense, and with this in mind many interpreters choose to translate it as “the beautiful.” But, the idea also has a political and moral sense, and in an attempt to capture this some choose to translate it as “the noble.” Still others try to strike a balance between these two, translating it as “the fine.” It is important to note from the outset that there is a way in which the political sense of τὸ καλόν is the focus of the Hippias Major, as indicated by the extended opening discussion of Hippias’ political activities, which sets the stage for Socrates’ question (281a – 286c). But the dialogue also suggests that the political sense can and should be understood on the model of the aesthetic; this appears most clearly in the examination of Hippias’ second answer, which features a discussion of the beautiful statue Athena Parthenos (289c – 291c). This discussion indicates that the aesthetic sense is broader and in certain way more primary 3 than the political, which is why I have chosen to translate τὸ καλόν as “the beautiful” throughout.4 Nevertheless, both senses of τὸ καλόν should be kept in mind while reading the Hippias Major, and an interpretation of the dialogue must explain how the aesthetic and political senses are related and encapsulated by one idea. In addition to the explicit question regarding the beautiful, the dialogue presents the interpreter with a number of implicit questions, the following of which seem to me to be the most important for understanding the dialogue as a whole. In order to learn about the beautiful, Socrates requests the help of Hippias, a renowned sophist from Elis, apparently in Athens on a diplomatic mission during the Peace of Nicias. Socrates approaches Hippias, not the other way around. Why does Socrates want to speak with Hippias in particular? This question is all the more glaring due to the fact that Hippias, for all his intellectual acumen, appears quite foolish in his conversation with Socrates. Why is Hippias the proper interlocutor for such an investigation of the beautiful? The Hippias Major begins with a lengthy discussion of wisdom and law, as these relate to Hippias’ public and private activities. How does this discussion of Hippias’ public and private activities serve as the proper introduction to the question of the beautiful? How might the issues and problems that come to light in the subsequent search for the beautiful be foreshadowed or illustrated by this preliminary discussion? When he asks Hippias to teach him what the beautiful is, Socrates requests that he be allowed to imitate a man who recently perplexed him with the same question and whom Socrates claims always refutes him (whom I therefore refer to throughout as “the 4 Refuter”). As a result, much of what Socrates says in the dialogue is not spoken in his own voice to Hippias, but rather in the voice of the Refuter as he would respond to Socrates, were Socrates to answer him as Hippias instructs. Although Socrates uses similar rhetorical devices in other Platonic dialogues, as when he imitates the Laws in the Crito (50a), in no other dialogue is a similar conceit as elaborate and extended as it is in the Hippias Major. Why does Socrates use such an elaborate rhetorical device in his conversation with Hippias? Why is it necessary that Socrates conduct his inquiry into the beautiful in the guise of the Refuter? When Hippias attempts to explain what the beautiful is, he repeatedly cites particular examples of beautiful things, as opposed to explaining what all beautiful things have in common that makes them beautiful. That is to say, Hippias explains what is beautiful but not what the beautiful is. Although Socrates suggests that Hippias may not understand the question, he does not correct Hippias as explicitly as he could, the way he corrects Meno, for instance (Meno 72a). Why does Hippias repeatedly make this mistake, and why does Socrates allow him to do so? Is this mistake, confusing particular embodiments with the form itself, somehow appropriate to the question of the beautiful? Toward the end of the dialogue, in what appears to be a consideration of aesthetics, the discussion abruptly turns toward issues of ontology, in particular to the question of whether certain affections can apply to two things together but not each individually. Socrates suggests that this is possible, whereas Hippias denies it vehemently. Socrates’ suggestion so angers Hippias that he condemns Socrates and his 5 whole method of investigation. How does this seemingly anomalous ontological digression fit with the rest of the dialogue? And why is Hippias so incensed by Socrates’ claim? The language and style of the Hippias Major raise a few related questions.
Recommended publications
  • The Roles of Solon in Plato's Dialogues
    The Roles of Solon in Plato’s Dialogues Dissertation Presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Samuel Ortencio Flores, M.A. Graduate Program in Greek and Latin The Ohio State University 2013 Dissertation Committee: Bruce Heiden, Advisor Anthony Kaldellis Richard Fletcher Greg Anderson Copyrighy by Samuel Ortencio Flores 2013 Abstract This dissertation is a study of Plato’s use and adaptation of an earlier model and tradition of wisdom based on the thought and legacy of the sixth-century archon, legislator, and poet Solon. Solon is cited and/or quoted thirty-four times in Plato’s dialogues, and alluded to many more times. My study shows that these references and allusions have deeper meaning when contextualized within the reception of Solon in the classical period. For Plato, Solon is a rhetorically powerful figure in advancing the relatively new practice of philosophy in Athens. While Solon himself did not adequately establish justice in the city, his legacy provided a model upon which Platonic philosophy could improve. Chapter One surveys the passing references to Solon in the dialogues as an introduction to my chapters on the dialogues in which Solon is a very prominent figure, Timaeus- Critias, Republic, and Laws. Chapter Two examines Critias’ use of his ancestor Solon to establish his own philosophic credentials. Chapter Three suggests that Socrates re- appropriates the aims and themes of Solon’s political poetry for Socratic philosophy. Chapter Four suggests that Solon provides a legislative model which Plato reconstructs in the Laws for the philosopher to supplant the role of legislator in Greek thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Teachers' Pay in Ancient Greece
    University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Papers from the University Studies series (The University of Nebraska) University Studies of the University of Nebraska 5-1942 Teachers' Pay In Ancient Greece Clarence A. Forbes Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/univstudiespapers Part of the Arts and Humanities Commons This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the University Studies of the University of Nebraska at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in Papers from the University Studies series (The University of Nebraska) by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. Teachers' Pay In Ancient Greece * * * * * CLARENCE A. FORBES UNIVERSITY OF NEBRASKA STUDIES Ma y 1942 STUDIES IN THE HUMANITIES NO.2 Note to Cataloger UNDER a new plan the volume number as well as the copy number of the University of Nebraska Studies was discontinued and only the numbering of the subseries carried on, distinguished by the month and the year of pu blica tion. Thus the present paper continues the subseries "Studies in the Humanities" begun with "University of Nebraska Studies, Volume 41, Number 2, August 1941." The other subseries of the University of Nebraska Studies, "Studies in Science and Technology," and "Studies in Social Science," are continued according to the above plan. Publications in all three subseries will be supplied to recipients of the "University Studies" series. Corre­ spondence and orders should be addressed to the Uni­ versity Editor, University of Nebraska, Lincoln. University of Nebraska Studies May 1942 TEACHERS' PAY IN ANCIENT GREECE * * * CLARENCE A.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Date of the Trial of Anaxagoras
    The Classical Quarterly http://journals.cambridge.org/CAQ Additional services for The Classical Quarterly: Email alerts: Click here Subscriptions: Click here Commercial reprints: Click here Terms of use : Click here On the Date of the Trial of Anaxagoras A. E. Taylor The Classical Quarterly / Volume 11 / Issue 02 / April 1917, pp 81 - 87 DOI: 10.1017/S0009838800013094, Published online: 11 February 2009 Link to this article: http://journals.cambridge.org/abstract_S0009838800013094 How to cite this article: A. E. Taylor (1917). On the Date of the Trial of Anaxagoras. The Classical Quarterly, 11, pp 81-87 doi:10.1017/S0009838800013094 Request Permissions : Click here Downloaded from http://journals.cambridge.org/CAQ, IP address: 128.122.253.212 on 28 Apr 2015 ON THE DATE OF THE TRIAL OF ANAXAGORAS. IT is a point of some interest to the historian of the social and intellectual development of Athens to determine, if possible, the exact dates between which the philosopher Anaxagoras made that city his home. As everyone knows, the tradition of the third and later centuries was not uniform. The dates from which the Alexandrian chronologists had to arrive at their results may be conveniently summed up under three headings, (a) date of Anaxagoras' arrival at Athens, (6) date of his prosecution and escape to Lampsacus, (c) length of his residence at Athens, (a) The received account (Diogenes Laertius ii. 7),1 was that Anaxagoras was twenty years old at the date of the invasion of Xerxes and lived to be seventy-two. This was apparently why Apollodorus (ib.) placed his birth in Olympiad 70 and his death in Ol.
    [Show full text]
  • Protagoras 330-1 David Wol£Sdorf
    ~tKatO<J"UVll and 'Qc.nem,c; at Protagoras 330-1 David Wol£sdorf I Introduction and Review In an argument in Protagoras for the similarity of Ol1WlO(j'\JVTj and oCH6'tTj~ Socrates introduces the following set of propositions: 1 (1) OtKalO(j'\JVT] is OtKlXlOV. 2 (2) oCH6'tTj~ is OCHOV. 3 (3) OtKlX lO(j'\JVTj is ocrWV. 4 (4) oCH6'tT]~ is otKawv. iI , I The meanings of (1)-(4) remain controversial. The objective of this paper is to give an update on the state of the discussion and to offer my own interpretation. The words 'OtKlXtOOUVTj' and 'OtKlXtoV' are typically translated as 'jus- tice' and 'just'. Thus, (1) is rendered as 'Justice is just'. The words '6CH6'tT1~' and 'ocrtoV' are typically translated as 'piety' or 'holiness' and 'pious' or 'holy'. But 'piety' and 'holiness' are not synonyms. Humans and their actions can be pious or holy, but inanimate objects can be holy, 330c4-dl 2 330d2-el 3 331a7-b3 4 331a7-b3 182 David Wolfsdorf ~lKato(jUVT\ and 'CXn6'!T\~ at Protagoras 330-1 183 but not pious. Thus, it is unclear whether to translate (2)-(4) as 'Holiness defined, is a condition that can only occur within a metaphysical discur- is holy', 'Justice is holy', and 'Holiness is just', or 'Piety is pious', 'Justice sive context.9 is pious', and 'Piety is just'. For much of the paper I will retain the original Insofar as the condition of self-predication depends upon the subject Greek and render the key words in English only where necessary.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Project for Education in the Early Socratic Dialogues
    University of Massachusetts Amherst ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 1-1-1996 Plato's project for education in the early Socratic dialogues. Heather Lynne Reid University of Massachusetts Amherst Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1 Recommended Citation Reid, Heather Lynne, "Plato's project for education in the early Socratic dialogues." (1996). Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014. 2285. https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1/2285 This Open Access Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. It has been accepted for inclusion in Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. For more information, please contact [email protected]. PLATO'S PROJECT FOR EDUCATION IN THE EARLY SOCRATIC DIALOGUES A Dissertation Presented by HEATHER LYNNE REID Submitted to the Graduate School of the University of Massachusetts Amherst in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY May 1996 Department of Philosophy © Copyright by Heather Lynne Reid 1996 All Rights Reserved PLATO'S PROJECT FOR EDUCATION IN THE EARLY SOCRATIC DIALOGUES A Dissertation Presented by HEATHER LYNNE REID Approved as to style and content by: ca Gareth B. Matthews, Chair Robert Ackerman, Member J^n Robison, Department Head philosophy ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I would like to thank my dissertation director Gareth B. Matthews for his special balance of support and criticism throughout this project, as well as Bruce Aune and Marios Philippides for their comments on early stages of the manuscript. I also wish to thank the Department of Philosophy of the University of Southern California for providing library privileges and research support necessary to the completion of this dissertation.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Arrangement of the Platonic Dialogues
    Ryan C. Fowler 25th Hour On the Arrangement of the Platonic Dialogues I. Thrasyllus a. Diogenes Laertius (D.L.), Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers 3.56: “But, just as long ago in tragedy the chorus was the only actor, and afterwards, in order to give the chorus breathing space, Thespis devised a single actor, Aeschylus a second, Sophocles a third, and thus tragedy was completed, so too with philosophy: in early times it discoursed on one subject only, namely physics, then Socrates added the second subject, ethics, and Plato the third, dialectics, and so brought philosophy to perfection. Thrasyllus says that he [Plato] published his dialogues in tetralogies, like those of the tragic poets. Thus they contended with four plays at the Dionysia, the Lenaea, the Panathenaea and the festival of Chytri. Of the four plays the last was a satiric drama; and the four together were called a tetralogy.” b. Characters or types of dialogues (D.L. 3.49): 1. instructive (ὑφηγητικός) A. theoretical (θεωρηµατικόν) a. physical (φυσικόν) b. logical (λογικόν) B. practical (πρακτικόν) a. ethical (ἠθικόν) b. political (πολιτικόν) 2. investigative (ζητητικός) A. training the mind (γυµναστικός) a. obstetrical (µαιευτικός) b. tentative (πειραστικός) B. victory in controversy (ἀγωνιστικός) a. critical (ἐνδεικτικός) b. subversive (ἀνατρεπτικός) c. Thrasyllan categories of the dialogues (D.L. 3.50-1): Physics: Timaeus Logic: Statesman, Cratylus, Parmenides, and Sophist Ethics: Apology, Crito, Phaedo, Phaedrus, Symposium, Menexenus, Clitophon, the Letters, Philebus, Hipparchus, Rivals Politics: Republic, the Laws, Minos, Epinomis, Atlantis Obstetrics: Alcibiades 1 and 2, Theages, Lysis, Laches Tentative: Euthyphro, Meno, Io, Charmides and Theaetetus Critical: Protagoras Subversive: Euthydemus, Gorgias, and Hippias 1 and 2 :1 d.
    [Show full text]
  • Thales of Miletus Sources and Interpretations Miletli Thales Kaynaklar Ve Yorumlar
    Thales of Miletus Sources and Interpretations Miletli Thales Kaynaklar ve Yorumlar David Pierce October , Matematics Department Mimar Sinan Fine Arts University Istanbul http://mat.msgsu.edu.tr/~dpierce/ Preface Here are notes of what I have been able to find or figure out about Thales of Miletus. They may be useful for anybody interested in Thales. They are not an essay, though they may lead to one. I focus mainly on the ancient sources that we have, and on the mathematics of Thales. I began this work in preparation to give one of several - minute talks at the Thales Meeting (Thales Buluşması) at the ruins of Miletus, now Milet, September , . The talks were in Turkish; the audience were from the general popu- lation. I chose for my title “Thales as the originator of the concept of proof” (Kanıt kavramının öncüsü olarak Thales). An English draft is in an appendix. The Thales Meeting was arranged by the Tourism Research Society (Turizm Araştırmaları Derneği, TURAD) and the office of the mayor of Didim. Part of Aydın province, the district of Didim encompasses the ancient cities of Priene and Miletus, along with the temple of Didyma. The temple was linked to Miletus, and Herodotus refers to it under the name of the family of priests, the Branchidae. I first visited Priene, Didyma, and Miletus in , when teaching at the Nesin Mathematics Village in Şirince, Selçuk, İzmir. The district of Selçuk contains also the ruins of Eph- esus, home town of Heraclitus. In , I drafted my Miletus talk in the Math Village. Since then, I have edited and added to these notes.
    [Show full text]
  • Notes Du Mont Royal ←
    Notes du mont Royal www.notesdumontroyal.com 쐰 Cette œuvre est hébergée sur « No- tes du mont Royal » dans le cadre d’un exposé gratuit sur la littérature. SOURCE DES IMAGES Google Livres HERIODOTI. HISITORIAR. ï TÎ 1V. P. IL VARIETiAS LECTIONIS IN LIB. VIII. ET 1X. et Index Rem et .Personarum. salariaux. t flashblbllœmk Münchon VARIETAS LECTIONIS IN HERQDOTI LIBRvO VIII. Ins c in PTI o N 1-: M , ut in aliis Heiodoti librîs, sic et hic tenui eam, quam Aldus habet, ’Hp a 361-9 o in". plaît! àyâa’n. 059m1... Similiter fare noster codex F. Héoîo’rov ’Iwoçlô’v Oôçuw’u. à. W588 E L! N G I US, titulum teneus ex Steph. cd. 1. fere pr0pa atum , *Hçoâo’rou 1’05 iAÀmatçvm’a’â-oç ilnofzô’v 9’986", ËmyçœOoMgn Ov’çuw’ac. monuit, cAMmcçwoca-ïoç absque arlic. lscribi in Arc-h. et deesse eidem verha imnmp. 0139m. CAP. I. Lin. 1. 02 8è etc. De initio huius libri, v1» de quae in Var. Lect. ad finem libri VIL monùimus. Ibid. ’EMfivwv Ë; rdv) r’EMovvzç 16v droit. prave. -- Sic qui; dem etF. I. 2. Ëmv) Sic edd. et mssti, exeepto F. in quo 57m», et sic iterum initia capitis sequenfis. l. s Jay. garai un!) d’un nazi Êxœrdv) Sic Arch. et Î’ind. -- Et recte hi quidem; soient enim minores. numeros Graeci prac- ponere maioribus. Alii vulgo omnes ânon-ù un) Juan un! 5nd. Unus Pd. Jan-al pro Êm-œ’. l. 8. ’Aonv. CG! mystéri- mv) Placuit hoc, quod dedit F. Alii vulgo me.
    [Show full text]
  • Meet the Philosophers of Ancient Greece
    Meet the Philosophers of Ancient Greece Everything You Always Wanted to Know About Ancient Greek Philosophy but didn’t Know Who to Ask Edited by Patricia F. O’Grady MEET THE PHILOSOPHERS OF ANCIENT GREECE Dedicated to the memory of Panagiotis, a humble man, who found pleasure when reading about the philosophers of Ancient Greece Meet the Philosophers of Ancient Greece Everything you always wanted to know about Ancient Greek philosophy but didn’t know who to ask Edited by PATRICIA F. O’GRADY Flinders University of South Australia © Patricia F. O’Grady 2005 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise without the prior permission of the publisher. Patricia F. O’Grady has asserted her right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identi.ed as the editor of this work. Published by Ashgate Publishing Limited Ashgate Publishing Company Wey Court East Suite 420 Union Road 101 Cherry Street Farnham Burlington Surrey, GU9 7PT VT 05401-4405 England USA Ashgate website: http://www.ashgate.com British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Meet the philosophers of ancient Greece: everything you always wanted to know about ancient Greek philosophy but didn’t know who to ask 1. Philosophy, Ancient 2. Philosophers – Greece 3. Greece – Intellectual life – To 146 B.C. I. O’Grady, Patricia F. 180 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Meet the philosophers of ancient Greece: everything you always wanted to know about ancient Greek philosophy but didn’t know who to ask / Patricia F.
    [Show full text]
  • Notes Du Mont Royal ←
    Notes du mont Royal www.notesdumontroyal.com 쐰 Cette œuvre est hébergée sur « No- tes du mont Royal » dans le cadre d’un exposé gratuit sur la littérature. SOURCE DES IMAGES Google Livres 1 HISTOIRE D’IHËRO’DOTE. limnon. EN. NEUF VOLUMES. HISTOIRE D’HËRODOTE. ÉDlTl-ON 311. NEUF VOLUMES. mais HlSTOIRE D’HÈRODOTE, TRADUITE DU GREC, Avec des Remarques Historiques et Critiques , un Essai sur la Chronologie d’Hérodote , et une Table Géographique. NOUVELLE ÉDITION, REVUE, CORRIGÉE ET CONSIDÉRABLEMENT AUGMENTÉE, A laquelle on a joint la. Vie d’Homère , attribuée à Hérodote, les Extraits de ,l’Histoire de Perse et de l’Inde de Ctésias, et le Traité de la Malignité d’Hérodote: le tout accompagné de Notes. TOME VIII. TABLE GÉOGRAPHIQUE. DE L’IMPRIMERIE DE C. CRAPELET. A PARIS, omniums liman l’aîné, Libraire de la Biblio- Chez thèque Nationale, rue Serpente, n° 6; THÉOPHILE humons père , Libraire, me Hautefeuille, n° 22. AN x1- 1802. WmM HISTOIRE ’ ÙHÉRODOTE TABLE GÉOGRAPHIQUE. A. B ANTES , peuples qui Occnpoient autrefois la plus grande partie de l’île d’Eubée : sortis de Thrace , d’où ils étoient originaires, ils vinrent d’abord en Phocide, où. ils bâtirent Abe ou Abes , et de là ils passèrent dans.(1) l’Eubée , qui prit d’eux le nom d’Abantis. Ils avoient été ainsi nommés d’Âbas (a) , leur roi , qui se prétendoit fils de Neptune. Il y en eut qui de l’Eubée allèrent en Ionie et se mêlèrent avec ses habitans. Pausanias prétend que ce fut dans l’île de Chics ABDERES , ville de Thracc , vers le bord Est de l’em- bouchure du (5) Nestus: c’était une ville très-puissante.
    [Show full text]
  • Historischw Geographische Studien Über Altsiciliell. Gela. Phintias. Die Siidlichen Sikeler
    Historisch w geographische Studien über Altsiciliell. Gela. Phintias. Die siidlichen Sikeler. (Hierzu zwei Karten.) Ueber die Geschichte, die Lage und die Denkmäler der rhodisch­ kretischen Pflanzstadt Gela und über die benachbarten Städte haben bis jetzt nur Wenige monographisch Untersuchungen und Bericht erstattet; wie es scheint, aus leicht erkennbaren Gründen. Da die Stadt Gela (die wir immer als Mittelpunkt unserer Arbeit fest­ halten) schon im Alterthum zerstört und aufgehoben ist und daher kein heutiger Ort sich in geschiohtlicher Continuität mit ihr weiss, so hat sich auch keine Gemeinde unmittelbar aus Patriotismus zur Erforschung der alten Geschichte derselben angetrieben gefühlt. Zwar ist über den Besitz des zu erbenden geschiohtlichen Glanzes zwischen den beiden Nacbbarstädten Licata und Terranova ein heftiger Kampf entbrannt, welcher mit einer für den Nordländer unbegreiHiche~ glühenden Leidenschaft geruhrt wird. Der Reisende erlebt hinsichtlich desselben nicht nur ergötzliche Dinge, nnd hÖl't noch erstaunlichere Erzählungen, sondern er geräth, wenn er sich hier oder dort bestimmt zu Gunsten der entgegengesetzten Ansicht ausspricht, in GefH.bI'. Aber dieser Streit wird meist nur mit dem Munde oder vermittelaJ; privater und öffentlichel' Demonstrationen geführt, und wenn er auch eine Literatur erzeugt hat, so ermangelt diese meist der Erudition und des wissenschaftlichen Charakters, so dass diejenigen Bücher, welche mir wenigstens zu Gesicht gekommen sind, ohne weiteres zu den Todteu geworfen werden können. Für Unhetbeiligtel'e hat wohl weder die Gegend Reiz genug ausgeübt, noch auch mag die Specialgeschichte dieser südlichen Gegenden besonders anziehend geschienen haben, von wel­ cher zu wenig bekannt ist, als dass man sich ein Bild fortschreitender Entwioklung entwerfen könnte. Zudem giebt es an den Orten, über Bhelll.
    [Show full text]
  • This Course on Plato Provides an In-Depth Account of This Seminal Thinker’S Philosophy
    PLATO PHILO 380(W) Dr. V. Adluri Sec. 001 [4921] Office: Hunter West, 12th floor, Room 1242 Spring 2009 Telephone: 973 216 7874 Prof. Adluri Email: [email protected] Monday/Wednesday, 4:10-5:25pm Office hours: Wednesdays, 6:00 – 7:00 P.M and by appointment DESCRIPTION: This course on Plato provides an in-depth account of this seminal thinker’s philosophy. Major themes such as the nature of knowledge, soul, universe, city, God, language, love, and art will be discussed based on selections from all of his dialogues. Plato’s relationship to Pre- Socratic philosophy, especially Parmenides and Heraclitus will be discussed. We will pay special attention to Plato’s use of the dialogic form and its main protagonist: Socrates. In the second half of the course, we will read the Republic in detail, with special attention to the legacy of Plato’s thought in the history of Western Philosophy. Required Text: Plato. Complete Works. Edited by John Cooper. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1997. $54. All textbooks are on order at Shakespeare & Co. Booksellers (939 Lexington Avenue between 68th and 69th streets; 212 570 0201). Shakespeare & Co. also has a limited number of used copies available at lower prices. COURSE OBJECTIVES: This course is intended to give students a basic familiarity with the Platonic corpus and an in-depth knowledge of the Republic. In the first half of the course, students will gain a basic familiarity with Platonic philosophy, including its method of argumentation, its ultimate aims, and its wider political and literary context. We will then apply these insights to a close- reading of the Republic.
    [Show full text]