Abstract: According to Harry Frankfurt, We Enjoy Free Will Only When We Wholeheartedly Endorse Our Actions

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Abstract: According to Harry Frankfurt, We Enjoy Free Will Only When We Wholeheartedly Endorse Our Actions Abstract: According to Harry Frankfurt, we enjoy free will only when we wholeheartedly endorse our actions. Thus Frankfurt views ambivalence as a “disease of the will” that undermines our freedom by undermining the coherence of our volitional identity. While I agree that there’s a link between free will and identity, I argue that the unification of the self may involve holding together an incoherent set of identifications—especially for personalities forged within culturally diverse communities. I hope to show that the ambivalence inherent in such “intersectional identity” allows for the self-reflection and creativity that is essential for free will. Word Count: 3258 Free Will and Wholehearted Ambivalence In this paper I explicate and critique Harry Frankfurt’s influential theory of free will. On his view, we enjoy free will only when we act on desires we wholeheartedly endorse. Frankfurt contrasts wholeheartedness with ambivalence, which he views as a “disease of the will” (“Faintest” 100) that undermines our freedom by undermining the unity and coherence of our identity. While I agree that there’s an important conceptual link between free will and the “unity” of our identity, I claim, contra Frankfurt, that the unification of the self may involve holding together an incoherent set of identifications. This is especially true of personalities forged at the intersections of culturally disparate communities. I argue that the ambivalence inherent in “intersectional identity” allows for critical self-reflection, intentional self-creation, and thoughtful action, all of which are essential to our freedom of will. I. To see clearly why Frankfurt thinks ambivalence undermines free will, let me briefly review the main points of his theory. Many creatures have “first-order desires,” which are “desires to do or not do one thing or another” (67). But unlike other creatures, we persons also form “second-order desires,” which have as their object, not our actions, but our first-order desires. Frankfurt reserves the term “will” for our effective first-order desires—those that move us to action (68). A second-order desire that some first-order desire should become our will, Frankfurt terms a “second-order volition.” The capacity to evaluate our first-order desires and form second-order volitions is integral to his conceptions of free will and personhood. Frankfurt claims that when our effective first-order desires “mesh” with our second-order volitions, our actions reflect our volitional identity and thus are the products of our free will. But why, Gary Watson has asked, should we treat second-order volitions as authoritative? In response, Frankfurt introduced the notion of “wholeheartedness.” He claims we constitute our “selves” by wholeheartedly endorsing some desires and rejecting others (“Identification” 170). Further, among our endorsed desires, we must establish a “single ordering” that establishes our priorities over time (170). This process of “ordering and rejection” doesn’t necessarily remove conflict between desires (nor does rejection entail repression1); rather, the conflict is “transformed into a conflict between one of [the desires] and the person who has identified himself with its rival” (“Identification” 170, 172). Wholeheartedness, then, constitutes the self as a coherent and stable set of rank ordered desires. “In the absence of whole-heartedness,” however, “the person is ... himself divided” (“Identification” 165). Such ambivalence is, for Frankfurt, a “disease of the will” that involves endorsing conflicting desires or attitudes toward the same object (“Faintest” 99-100). On this view, ambivalence destroys free will because it undermines the coherence of the self. However, as I’ll argue, Frankfurt exaggerates the dangers of ambivalence and gives short shrift to its agentic potential. No doubt ambivalence can be self-defeating, but ambivalent agents may take constructive and self-expressive action (which they “own”) in spite, or even because, of ambivalence. Indeed, ambivalence may be central to our self-conceptions. This raises the 1 See Frankfurt, Harry. “Reply to J. David Velleman.” FREE WILL AND WHOLEHEARTED AMBIVALENCE possibility (which Frankfurt denies) of wholehearted ambivalence—which I construe not as unequivocal endorsement of our actions, but as unequivocal identification with the ambivalent self our actions reflect. While we should try to resolve “self”-defeating ambivalence, the capacity to identify with conflicting perspectives allows for a richer, more internally diverse, self- conception and enables us to better negotiate a complex social world. In developing this point, I draw on Edwina Barvosa-Carter’s work on relational autonomy, which itself is a development of Gloria Anzaldúa’s work on “mestiza consciousness.” II. Interestingly, Frankfurt’s compatibilist theory of free will accommodates the significant role socialization plays in forming our character. However, his theory doesn’t say enough about how cultural influences shape our desires. For example, a young man raised in a small Bible Belt town who experiences homosexual desires likely would internalize heterosexist values and reject such desires while endorsing his effective first-order desires to conform with local gender and sex norms. That his second-order volitions and effective first-order desires mesh, despite persistent “outlaw” desires, doesn’t dispel the suspicion that his effective hetero-normative desires don’t reflect his “real” self. Being socialized in an isolated, homogenous community affords little opportunity to develop the critical self-consciousness which Frankfurt sometimes recognizes as essential for agentic development. In contrast to such wholeheartedness, ambivalence is inescapable for those socialized at the intersections of culturally disparate communities. Barvosa-Carter has pointed to the significance of Anzaldúa’s notion of “mestiza consciousness” to capture the ambivalent mode of self-awareness and self-creation characteristic of intersectional identity. The term “mestiza” refers to a woman of mixed Spanish and American Indian descent. As Barsova-Carter notes, FREE WILL AND WHOLEHEARTED AMBIVALENCE however, “mestiza consciousness” may refer to any “subjectivity characterized by a diversity of different identities ... that mingle and collide within the self” (6-7). Thus mestiza consciousness is not uncommon. Given the complexity and interconnectedness of our world, most of us have multiple identities shaping our endorsements. Unlike the young man’s repressive hetero- normative socialization, the ambivalence inherent in intersectional identity allows for critical self-reflection, intentional self-creation, and thoughtful action. Borvosa-Carter has coined the term “mestiza autonomy,” which she defines as an “account of autonomy in which an agent who has a diversity of social relations and group memberships critically reflects upon the contents of her particular social and personal identities to forge a set of guiding endorsements” (9). Despite her claims to the contrary, it seems that such an account is compatible with Frankfurt’s notion of wholeheartedness. An agent who displays mestiza autonomy, in Barvosa-Carter’s sense, has a coherent set of guiding endorsements— though they’re drawn from multiple sources. Barvosa-Carter defines the “ambivalence” within mestiza autonomy as “an equivocating connection to selected principles that [the agent] ultimately does not endorse and will not act upon” (14). This is not what Frankfurt means by ambivalence. Whatever this “equivocating connection” amounts to, it isn’t something that entails conflict within the agent’s guiding endorsements. Frankfurt’s view implies that, insofar as our identities beget conflicting endorsements, we have less free will. But given the inherent multiplicity of, and conflict within, mestiza consciousness, the standard of volitional coherence fails to recognize the agentic capacities of intersectional subjects. As Anzaldúa argues, la mestiza’s plural identity allows her to break from set patterns of thought in a holistic movement of self-creation that incorporates conflicting identifications without forcing coherence—she “learns to be an Indian in Mexican culture, to be FREE WILL AND WHOLEHEARTED AMBIVALENCE Mexican from an Anglo point of view” (101). Significantly, la mestiza’s ambivalence doesn’t leave her unable to act in a self-affirming way; rather, the “Western mode” (to use Anzaldua’s term) is crippling insofar as it forces an inauthentic coherence. Insofar as la mestiza’s contrasting identities beget conflicting endorsements (e.g., “traditionalist” versus “assimilationist” attitudes), their co-existence in one psyche begets ambivalence. On the Western (either/or) conception of identity, which Frankfurt endorses, la mestiza’s integrity as an agentic person hinges on her ability to overcome ambivalence and, where there is conflict, unequivocally side with her indigenous self, her Euro/Spanish-American self, or some third conceptual and/or normative perspective. While it’s possible to construct a coherent, non-ambivalent personality from diverse sources (as with Borvosa-Carter’s notion of mestiza autonomy), such a person wouldn’t exemplify mestiza consciousness because she wouldn’t view herself as authentically Indian, Mexican, and/or Anglo, but rather as an atomic individual who has constructed her own identity out of cultural materials from which she stands apart. Mestiza consciousness, by contrast, is structurally conflicted. On the view
Recommended publications
  • Frankfurt, Harry
    Tanner25_pp_i-214 4/19/05 2:11 PM Page 167 I. Taking Ourselves Seriously II. Getting It Right HARRY FRANKFURT The Tanner Lectures on Human Values Delivered at Stanford University April 14–16, 2004 Tanner25_pp_i-214 4/19/05 2:11 PM Page 168 Harry G. Frankfurt is Professor Emeritus of Philosophy at Prince- ton University. He was educated at Johns Hopkins University, where he received his Ph.D. He has held positions at Ohio State University, the State University of New York at Binghamton, Rockefeller University, and at Yale. He was also a visiting fellow at All Souls College, Oxford. He is a fellow of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences. He has written more than 50 scholarly articles, essays, and reviews and is the author of three books: Demons, Dreamers and Madmen: The Defense of Reason in Descartes’ Meditations (1970); The Importance of What We Care About (1988); and Necessity, Volition and Love (1999); and the editor of Leibniz: A Collection of Critical Essays (1972). Tanner25_pp_i-214 4/19/05 2:11 PM Page 169 I. TAKING OURSELVES SERIOUSLY 1 I suppose some of you must have noticed that human beings have a tendency to be heavily preoccupied with thinking about themselves. Blind rollicking spontaneity is not exactly the hallmark of our species. We put very considerable effort into trying to get clear about what we are really like, trying to figure out what we are actually up to, and trying to decide whether anything can be done about this. The strong likeli- hood is that no other animal worries about such matters.
    [Show full text]
  • Self-Directedness and Resoluteness. the Two Dimensions of Autonomy
    Self-Directedness and Resoluteness. The Two Dimensions of Autonomy Dissertation zur Erlangung des akademischen Grades Doctor philosophiae (Dr. phil.) eingereicht an der Philosophischen Fakultät I der Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin von M.A. Jan Prause-Stamm Prof. Dr. Jan-Hendrik Olbertz, Präsident der Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin Prof. Michael Seadle, PhD, Dekan der Philosophischen Fakultät I Gutachter 1. Prof. Dr. Michael Pauen 2. Prof. Dr. Dr. Henrik Walter 3. Prof. Dr. Kirsten Meyer Tag der Promotion (Disputation): 11. Februar 2013 Danksagung Diese Arbeit ist im Rahmen des von der Volkswagen-Stiftung geförderten Projekts „Autonomie – Handlungsspielräume des Selbst“ entstanden. Ich bedanke mich bei der Volkswagen-Stiftung für das Stipendium, das ich zur Anfertigung meiner Dissertation erhalten habe. Besonderer Dank gilt meinen beiden Betreuern, Prof. Dr. Michael Pauen und Prof. Dr. Dr. Henrik Walter, die mich stets unterstützt und bestärkt haben. Schließlich möchte ich mich auch bei der Berlin School of Mind and Brain bedanken, deren Graduiertenprogramm ich während meiner Promotionszeit absolvieren durfte. Dortmund, 22.06.2012 Jan Prause-Stamm Summary I explore and explicate a notion of personal autonomy which has its sources (1) in the political concept of autonomy as it was developed in ancient Greece, (2) in Kant’s theory of autonomy as a property of person, and (3) in Frankfurt’s individualistic approach towards autonomy. From a systematic point of view I conceptualize autonomy as a natural and gradual property of persons, which is not tied to norms, and which differs from free will. Autonomy deals with an agent’s authentic expression of her standpoint and her aptitude in prevailing in conflicts or difficult situations.
    [Show full text]
  • The Discomfort in Frankfurt
    Erasmus Student Journal of Philosophy Koen Schoenmakers | The Discomfort in Frankfurt The Discomfort in Frankfurt ESJP #16 | 2019 Koen Schoenmakers “The standards […] of practical reason are grounded, so far as I can see, only be a much more comfortable world, yet reality does not seem in ourselves. More particularly, they are grounded only in what we cannot help to care. caring about and cannot help considering important.” When it comes to uncomfortable conclusions of Harry Frankfurt in ‘Getting it right’, p. 190 astronomy, - an extinction-sized asteroid could at any point Don’t try to prove a Nazi wrong. head in our direction - we accept it. When it comes to (Discomfort of normative subjectivism) conclusions of medicine, - anyone can die of a stroke at any time - we accept it. Sure, we try to prevent these things; in The quote reported above makes some people very fact practitioners and scientists do so every day. Still, we uncomfortable1. These people believe that ‘doing the right accept it. Upon learning about these things, we include them thing’ is somehow grounded in something outside of us. in our system of beliefs. No strings attached. But for some Whether it is God, human rights or the undeniable law of reason, when it comes to human actions, such as modern-day 48 reason, they claim something outside of us has to determine slavery, we do something odd. We acknowledge that this what is good. If not, would we not be able to justify phenomenon exists, but in addition we claim that the people anything? Are we then permitted to simply do whatever? who inflict these crimes are wrong and mistaken.
    [Show full text]
  • Harry G. Frankfurt
    CHARLES HOMER HASKINS PRIZE LECTURE FOR 2017 A Life of Learning Harry G. Frankfurt ACLS OCCASIONAL PAPER, No. 74 The 2017 Charles Homer Haskins Prize Lecture was presented at the ACLS Annual Meeting in Baltimore, Maryland, on May 12, 2017. © 2018 by Harry G. Frankfurt CONTENTS On Charles Homer Haskins iv Haskins Prize Lecturers v Brief Biography of vi Harry G. Frankfurt Introduction viii by Pauline Yu A Life of Learning 1 by Harry G. Frankfurt ON CHARLES HOMER HASKINS Charles Homer Haskins (1870–1937), for whom the ACLS lecture series is named, organized the founding of the American Council of Learned Societies in 1919 and served as its first chairman from 1920 to 1926. He received a PhD in history from Johns Hopkins University at the age of 20. Appointed an instructor at the Univer- sity of Wisconsin, Haskins became a full professor in two years. After 12 years there, he moved to Harvard University, where he served as dean of the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences from 1908 to 1924. At the time of his retirement in 1931, he was Henry Charles Lea Professor of Medieval History. A close advisor to President Woodrow Wilson (whom he had met at Johns Hopkins), Haskins attended the Paris Peace Conference of 1919 as chief of the Division of Western Europe of the American Commission to Negotiate Peace. He served as president of the American Historical Association in 1922, and was a founder and the second president of the Medieval Academy of America in 1926–27. A great American teacher, Haskins also did much to establish the reputation of American scholarship abroad.
    [Show full text]
  • Identification and Autonomy: a Meditation on the Philosophy of Harry Frankfurt
    ABSTRACT Title of Dissertation: IDENTIFICATION AND AUTONOMY: A MEDITATION ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF HARRY FRANKFURT Teresa Marie Chandler, Doctor of Philosophy, 2004 Dissertation directed by: Emeritus Professor Raymond Martin, Department of Philosophy, University of Maryland at College Park & Professor, Union College, Schenectady, NY Harry Frankfurt offers an account of freedom as “autonomy” in which identification plays a central role. Identification is supposed to be a process or psychic configuration by which attitudes – desires in particular – become or count in some sense as one’s own. When we are propelled to action by desires with which we “identify,” we’re acting autonomously. On Frankfurt’s view, whenever we act, a desire is involved, but sometimes the desire that moves us is one by which we do not want to be moved, a desire from which we are alienated – with which we fail to identify. Paradigm examples are addictions and compulsions. When moved by one of these “alien” des ires, we lack autonomy. Frankfurt’s account of autonomy, then, rests on a basic distinction. Of the desires that move us to action – “effective desires” – only some will be desires with which we identify. The main claim of this dissertation is that Fra nkfurt needs to maintain this distinction, but in the end, doesn’t. There are two basic problems. First, as Frankfurt develops his conception of identification, it shifts, and as it shifts, it becomes broader, so much so that it no longer marks the narro w internality. Second, neither of Frankfurt’s alternatives – wholeheartedness, caring – clearly functions to mark out a narrow internality, either.
    [Show full text]
  • Hume on the Nature of Moral Freedom
    Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy Summer 7-11-2012 Hume on the Nature of Moral Freedom Getty L. Lustila Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses Recommended Citation Lustila, Getty L., "Hume on the Nature of Moral Freedom." Thesis, Georgia State University, 2012. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses/118 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Theses by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. HUME ON THE NATURE OF MORAL FREEDOM by GETTY L. LUSTILA Under the Direction of Eric E. Wilson ABSTRACT Paul Russell argues that the interpretation of Hume as a classical compatibilist is misguided. Russell defends a naturalistic reading of Humean freedom and moral responsibility. On this account, Hume holds two theses: that moral responsibility is a product of our moral sentiments, and that our concept of moral freedom is derived from our considerations of moral responsibility. Russell claims that Hume’s theory of the passions is non-cognitivist, and thus that his account of moral judgment fails to distinguish between voluntary and involuntary actions or qualities of mind. He concludes that Hume’s account of moral responsibility is inadequate. I argue that Hume has a cognitivist account of the passions. For Hume, our character is judged to be a proper object of praise or censure on account of our ability to partake in a moral community with our fellows.
    [Show full text]
  • Stoody Dissertation
    UC Santa Barbara UC Santa Barbara Electronic Theses and Dissertations Title Defending Frankfurt: Moral Responsibility without Alternative Possibilities Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/7xh9n06r Author Stoody, Rick Lee Publication Date 2015 Peer reviewed|Thesis/dissertation eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA Santa Barbara Defending Frankfurt: Moral Responsibility without Alternative Possibilities A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy by Rick Lee Stoody Committee in charge: Professor C. Anthony Anderson, Co-Chair Professor John Martin Fischer, University of California, Riverside, Co-Chair Professor Aaron Zimmerman September 2015 The dissertation of Rick Lee Stoody is approved. ____________________________________________ Aaron Zimmerman ____________________________________________ John Martin Fischer, Co-Chair ____________________________________________ C. Anthony Anderson, Co-Chair August 2015 To Jen, who helped make this, and so many other good things in my life, a reality. iii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I thank the members of my committee (professors John Martin Fischer, C. Anthony Anderson, and Aaron Zimmerman) for their valuable feedback on many drafts of the chapters in this dissertation. I am grateful to the late Anthony Brueckner whose course “Freedom and Determinism” back in Spring 2009 kindled my interest in the present topic. I also wish to thank a few of the exceptional teachers I have had over the years: Dave Horner, J. P. Moreland, Doug Geivett, Garry Deweese, William Lane Craig, and Thomas Holden. A word of thanks extends to my fellow graduate students in the UC Santa Barbara philosophy department, in particular: Timothy Linehan, Justin Clark, Dan Dolson, Christopher Cloos, Keith Hess, Joe Lee, and David Spewak.
    [Show full text]
  • Reasons and Real Selves MANUEL VARGAS University of San Francisco
    Ideas y Valores: Revista Colombiana de Filosofía (forthcoming) Reasons and Real Selves MANUEL VARGAS University of San Francisco Most accounts of responsibility begin from either of two prominent points of departure: the idea that an agent must have some characterological or expressive connection to the action, or alternately, the idea that an agent must be in some sense responsive to reasons.1 Indeed, we might even understand much of the past couple of decades of philosophical work on moral responsibility as concerned with investigating which of these two approaches offers the most viable account of moral responsibility. Here, I wish to revisit an idea basic to all of this work. That is, I consider whether there is even a fundamental distinction between these approaches. I will argue that the relationship between these two approaches to moral responsibility is much more complicated than is ordinarily assumed. I shall argue that there are reasons to think that one of these views may ultimately collapse into the other, and if not, that there is nevertheless reason to think one of these views has misidentified the features of agency relevant to moral responsibility. The view that follows is one that we might call the primacy of reasons. In the second half of the article I consider whether recent experimental work speaks in favor of the alternative to the primacy of reasons. Its proponents argue that it does. I argue that it does not. 1. Real Selves and Reasons: Some initial considerations One inspiration for those accounts of responsibility that emphasize a characterological or expressive connection between agent and action is the idea that it can only make sense to hold someone responsible if the action in some way expresses a deep fact about the particular agent.
    [Show full text]
  • The Capabilities Approach to Metaphysical Personhood
    Claremont Colleges Scholarship @ Claremont CMC Senior Theses CMC Student Scholarship 2020 The Capabilities Approach To Metaphysical Personhood Mohnish Shah Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.claremont.edu/cmc_theses Part of the Metaphysics Commons Recommended Citation Shah, Mohnish, "The Capabilities Approach To Metaphysical Personhood" (2020). CMC Senior Theses. 2464. https://scholarship.claremont.edu/cmc_theses/2464 This Open Access Senior Thesis is brought to you by Scholarship@Claremont. It has been accepted for inclusion in this collection by an authorized administrator. For more information, please contact [email protected]. CLAREMONT MCKENNA COLLEGE THE CAPABILITIES APPROACH TO METAPHYSICAL PERSONHOOD SUBMITTED TO PROFESSOR AMY KIND BY MOHNISH SHAH FOR SENIOR THESIS SPRING 2020 MAY 11, 2020 Abstract It is accepted that humans are persons, but what does this mean? Society equates personhood with legal rights, moral worth, and metaphysical status. But exactly what makes us persons and distinguishes us from non-persons? What does our conception of this distinction and the value and rights we grant to persons but not to non-persons say about the type of creature that we are? Many philosophers have tried to define metaphysical personhood. However, this thesis argues that current accounts of metaphysical personhood are inadequate. Next, this thesis borrows and modifies Martha Nussbaum’s capabilities approach to human dignity in order to construct a new account of metaphysical personhood. This thesis defines metaphysical personhood as the existence of seven innate abilities: ability for self- awareness, ability to sense, ability to imagine, ability to think, ability to reason, ability to feel emotion, and ability to empathize.
    [Show full text]
  • Frankfurt on Identification and Satisfaction Frankfurt on Identification and Satisfaction ESJP a Critical Response #10 | 2016 Bas Peeters
    Erasmus Student Journal of Philosophy Bas Peeters | Frankfurt on Identification and Satisfaction Frankfurt on Identification and Satisfaction ESJP A Critical Response #10 | 2016 Bas Peeters In his seminal 1971 essay Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person, self-evaluation’ (ibid.), as Frankfurt calls it, is in itself necessary but not Harry Frankfurt provides an insightful account of free will and the prob- sufficient for human personhood. In fact, it is the capacity for reflec- 19 lem of determinism, that is not metaphysical, but rather psychological tive self-evaluation that distinguishes human beings from the rest of and practical. First and foremost, though, Frankfurt offers a philosophical the animal kingdom. Frankfurt argues that, in order to be considered analysis of the nature of personhood. He does so by providing an alterna- a person, an individual should not only have second-order desires in tive to the account of personhood advanced by Peter Strawson. In the general, but also specifically, desires to have certain desires to be his will. Strawsonian view, a person is defined exclusively as a subject having both In Frankfurt’s terminology, such ‘second-order volitions’ are that sub- physical and mental properties, so that the concept of a person can simply set of second-order desires, which are directly concerned with which of be equated with the concept of a human being. Frankfurt argues against our first-order desires should be effective in moving us into action. Sup- this view, assuming that mere membership in the biological species homo pose that Sharon now has become addicted.
    [Show full text]
  • The Routledge Companion to Free Will Reasons-Responsive Theories
    This article was downloaded by: 10.3.98.104 On: 29 Sep 2021 Access details: subscription number Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: 5 Howick Place, London SW1P 1WG, UK The Routledge Companion to Free Will Kevin Timpe, Meghan Griffith, Neil Levy Reasons-Responsive Theories of Freedom Publication details https://www.routledgehandbooks.com/doi/10.4324/9781315758206.ch3 Michael McKenna Published online on: 29 Nov 2016 How to cite :- Michael McKenna. 29 Nov 2016, Reasons-Responsive Theories of Freedom from: The Routledge Companion to Free Will Routledge Accessed on: 29 Sep 2021 https://www.routledgehandbooks.com/doi/10.4324/9781315758206.ch3 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR DOCUMENT Full terms and conditions of use: https://www.routledgehandbooks.com/legal-notices/terms This Document PDF may be used for research, teaching and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproductions, re-distribution, re-selling, loan or sub-licensing, systematic supply or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents will be complete or accurate or up to date. The publisher shall not be liable for an loss, actions, claims, proceedings, demand or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material. 3 REASONS-RESPONSIVE THEORIES OF FREEDOM Michael McKenna Reasons-responsive theories of freedom explain free agency in terms of an agent’s sensi- tivity to reasons. An agent who acts freely is responsive to variation in a suitable spectrum of reasons.
    [Show full text]
  • Frankfurt's Compatibilist Theory of Free Will
    Frankfurt's compatibilist theory of free will Jeff Speaks March 19, 2009 1 Free will and second-order volitions . 1 2 Frankfurt on the principle of alternate possibilities . 3 Last time we discussed van Inwagen's consequence argument, which is the most important argument for incompatibilism about free will and determinism. Harry Frankfurt is a prominent defender of a compatibilist view of free will. We will be talking about one piece which can be read as a counterexample to an apparent in- compatbilist principle (`Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility') and one which explains a view of free actions which has the consequence that free will is compatible with determinism (`Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person'). 1 Free will and second-order volitions In \Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person", Frankfurt presents a theory of free action. Note that this is something which van Inwagen did not try to do; van Inwagen argued for the claim that free will is inconsistent with determinism, but never tried to say what about certain actions makes them free (other than the necessary condition that they cannot be determined by facts about which the subject has no choice). Frankfurt's argumentative strategy can be thought of like this: he will defend a theory of the form A's φing is free iff A's φing is F for some property of actions F . Let's suppose we are convinced that his theory, or one like it, is correct. Then we can raise the question of compatibilism in a new form: if the world were deterministic, could any actions have property F ? If the answer is `Yes,' as he thinks, then Frankfurt's theory of free will will be an indirect argument for compatibilism.
    [Show full text]