Texas Uil Lincoln-Douglas Debate Research Series Vol. 19 Spring 2013 No

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Texas Uil Lincoln-Douglas Debate Research Series Vol. 19 Spring 2013 No 1 TEXAS UIL LINCOLN-DOUGLAS DEBATE RESEARCH SERIES VOL. 19 SPRING 2013 NO. 2 RESOLVED: IN MATTERS OF JUSTICE, JOHN RAWLS' DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE OUGHT TO BE PREFERRED OVER ROBERT NOZICK'S ENTITLEMENT THEORY. Lincoln Douglas was created as a debate format designed to emphasize questions of value. Effective participation in Lincoln Douglas debate produces familiarity with the great philosophers of the ages. The Spring 2013 UIL Lincoln-Douglas topic offers an exciting opportunity to explore the two leading theories of justice. This topic will give debaters an opportunity to understand how the current political divide in American politics finds its roots in classic philosophical theories. Libertarians, such as Kentucky Senator Rand Paul, and Tea Party candidates such as Minnesota Representative Michele Bachman, argue for lower taxes, less welfare spending, and minimal government. President Obama, along with most Congressional Democrats, argues that wealthy individuals should pay more taxes so that the federal government can continue to support domestic welfare spending. John Stick, professor of law at the University of Southern California Law Center, traces the origin of these current political divisions to the competing philosophies of Rawls and Nozick: The relationship between Rawls and Nozick is not a matter of interest for philosophers only. Although the first burst of discussion that greeted their work in the early 1970s has passed, many of the present legal policy debates between liberals and conservatives over the distribution of wealth, the nature of property rights, and the proper role of government in regulating the market are strongly influenced by Nozick and Rawls. Most contemporary theorists that oppose progressive taxation because it interferes with the functioning of the market rely on Nozick's political arguments. Rawls and Nozick are central to the contemporary debate over welfare rights, the strength of property rights, the interpretation of the takings clause, and general theoretical discussions on the nature of property law. (Northwestern University Law Review, Spring 1987, p 364) Anupam Chandler, professor of law at the University of California at Davis School of Law, also identifies the justice theories of Rawls and Nozick as central to political controversies: “Robert Nozick stands as one of the foremost intellectual antagonists to claims for distributive justice. John Rawls, meanwhile, penned the most important modern political theory justifying an egalitarian society” (U.C. Davis Law Review, March 2007, p. 564). John Rawls’ Difference Principle John Rawls (1921-2002), long-time professor of philosophy at Harvard University, is the author of the classic 1971 work, A Theory of Justice. In the Preface to his book, Rawls explains his intention to provide an alternative to the justice theories of the “great utilitarians,” David Hume, Adam Smith, Jeremy Bentham, and John Stuart Mill. He expresses concern that the critics of utilitarian justice have failed to provide a well-developed alternative theory. His intention is to correct this shortcoming: “What I have attempted to do is to generalize and carry to a higher order of abstraction the traditional theory of the social contract as represented by Locke, Rousseau, and Kant. In this way I hope that the theory can be developed so that it is no longer open to the more obvious objections often thought fatal to it. Moreover this theory seems to offer an alternative systematic account of the tradition. The theory that results is highly Kantian in nature” (p. viii). So what does it mean that Rawls wants to position himself in the Kantian tradition, rather than as a utilitarian philosopher? The German philosopher, Immanuel Kant, believed that justice must be examined deontologically – meaning we must always ask about our duties and moral obligations before looking to the consequences of those acts. This means that “the right must precede the good.” Karen Lebacqz, professor of ethics at the Pacific School of Religion, offers the following explanation in her book, Six Theories of Justice: Traditional notions of justice appear to be flouted by a theory that claims the "right" act is whatever maximizes the good. Individual rights or claims would be overridden by consideration of the "happiness" of others. For example, if the bloodshed of a threatened race riot could be averted by framing and lynching an innocent person, it seems that the utilitarian would have to say it is "right" to do so. long as the "greater good" required it, all individual rights and claims would be ignored. 2 Because of such apparent implications of utilitarian theory, issues of justice have consistently been a stumbling block for utilitarians. (1986, pp. 17-18) Rawls offers what he calls his “two principles of justice:” First: Each person is to have an equal right to the most extensive basic liberty compatible with a similar liberty for others. Second: Social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are both (a) reasonably expected to be to everyone's advantage, and (b) attached to positions and offices open to all. (A Theory of Justice, 1971, p. 60) The “Difference Principle” arises from Rawls’ second principle of justice. Before explaining this principle, however, it is essential to recognize that Rawls makes his first principle more important than the second: “These principles are to be arranged in a serial order with the first principle prior to the second. This ordering means that a departure from the institutions of equal liberty required by the first principle cannot be justified by, or compensated for, by greater social and economic advantages. The distribution of wealth and income and the hierarchies of authority, must be consistent with both the liberties of equal citizenship and equality of opportunity” (A Theory of Justice, 1971, p. 61). So if “basic liberties” must be assured before the “Difference Principle” kicks in, what does Rawls mean by “basic liberties?” He offers the following explanation: “The basic liberties of citizens are, roughly speaking, political liberty (the right to vote and be eligible for public office) together with the freedom of speech and assembly; liberty of conscience and freedom of thought; freedom of the person along with the right to hold (personal) property; and freedom from arbitrary arrest and seizure as defined by the concept of the rule of law. These liberties are all required to be equal by the first principle, since citizens of a just society are to have the same basic rights” (A Theory of Justice, 1971, p. 61). After these basic liberties have been assured, inequalities (or differences) in things such as income or property can be just so long as the inequalities work to “everyone’s advantage.” Consider the following example: workers could reason that everyone working at their factory should receive the same income at $15 per hour. Suppose we discover that we could hire a person with expert skill in supervision at $30 per hour. By hiring such a person, factory output improves such that everyone else in the factory can now earn $20 per hour. Would factory workers insist on retaining equality of income at $15 per hour, or would they accept the income difference that seems to work to everyone’s advantage? For Rawls, the question is always whether the difference is of benefit to the “least advantaged.” Why is he not equally concerned about the welfare of those at the top of the income scale? Well, an income difference obviously works to the advantage of those at the top of the scale. If we want to know whether the difference works to “everyone’s advantage,” our attention must turn to the impact of the difference on the least advantaged. Rawls believes that a properly functioning free market system can “lift all boats.” But it will do so only if proper attention is given to equalizing opportunity for all. John Schaar, professor of philosophy at the University of California at Santa Cruz, offers the following explanation of the “Difference Principle:” The Difference Principle asserts that inequalities are justifiable only if they are to the advantage of the worst-off representative man or group. We are to agree to consider the unequal distribution of talents and abilities among a population as a general social resource which can be arranged to work to the advantage of all, rather than as a source of strength for some and weakness for others. No one is to benefit from the contingencies of nature or social position "except in ways that redound to the well-being of others". In the conception of justice as fairness, people in effect agree to share one another's fate. Reciprocity and mutual benefit must prevail over considerations of social efficiency and technocratic values. (John Rawls’ Theory of Social Justice, 1980, p. 170) How does Rawls know that his theory of justice is the correct one? His answer is a theoretical device that he calls “the veil of ignorance” in the “original position:” The idea of the original position is to set up a fair procedure so that any principles agreed to will be just. The aim is to use the notion of pure procedural justice as a basis of theory. Somehow we must nullify the effects of specific contingencies which put men at odds and tempt them to exploit social and natural circumstances to their own advantage. Now in order to do this I assume that the parties are situated behind a veil of ignorance. They do not know how the various alternatives will affect their own particular case and they are obliged to evaluate principles solely on the basis of general considerations. It is assumed, then, that the parties do not know certain kinds of particular 3 facts. First of all, no one knows his place in society, his class position or social status; nor does he know his fortune in the distribution of natural assets and abilities, his intelligence, and strength, and the like.
Recommended publications
  • Markets Not Capitalism Explores the Gap Between Radically Freed Markets and the Capitalist-Controlled Markets That Prevail Today
    individualist anarchism against bosses, inequality, corporate power, and structural poverty Edited by Gary Chartier & Charles W. Johnson Individualist anarchists believe in mutual exchange, not economic privilege. They believe in freed markets, not capitalism. They defend a distinctive response to the challenges of ending global capitalism and achieving social justice: eliminate the political privileges that prop up capitalists. Massive concentrations of wealth, rigid economic hierarchies, and unsustainable modes of production are not the results of the market form, but of markets deformed and rigged by a network of state-secured controls and privileges to the business class. Markets Not Capitalism explores the gap between radically freed markets and the capitalist-controlled markets that prevail today. It explains how liberating market exchange from state capitalist privilege can abolish structural poverty, help working people take control over the conditions of their labor, and redistribute wealth and social power. Featuring discussions of socialism, capitalism, markets, ownership, labor struggle, grassroots privatization, intellectual property, health care, racism, sexism, and environmental issues, this unique collection brings together classic essays by Cleyre, and such contemporary innovators as Kevin Carson and Roderick Long. It introduces an eye-opening approach to radical social thought, rooted equally in libertarian socialism and market anarchism. “We on the left need a good shake to get us thinking, and these arguments for market anarchism do the job in lively and thoughtful fashion.” – Alexander Cockburn, editor and publisher, Counterpunch “Anarchy is not chaos; nor is it violence. This rich and provocative gathering of essays by anarchists past and present imagines society unburdened by state, markets un-warped by capitalism.
    [Show full text]
  • Entitlement Theory of Justice and End-State Fairness in the Allocation of Goods
    University of Massachusetts Amherst ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst Economics Department Working Paper Series Economics 2016 Entitlement theory of justice and end-state fairness in the allocation of goods Biung-Ghi Ju Department of Economics, Seoul National University, Korea Juan D. Moreno-Ternero Department of Economics, Universidad Pablo de Olavide, Spain, and CORE, Université catholique de Louvain, Belgium. Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umass.edu/econ_workingpaper Part of the Economics Commons Recommended Citation Ju, Biung-Ghi and Moreno-Ternero, Juan D., "Entitlement theory of justice and end-state fairness in the allocation of goods" (2016). Economics Department Working Paper Series. 213. https://doi.org/10.7275/9452364 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Economics at ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. It has been accepted for inclusion in Economics Department Working Paper Series by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. For more information, please contact [email protected]. DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS Working Paper Entitlement theory of justice and end-state fairness in the allocation of goods by Biung-Ghi Ju Juan D. Moreno-Ternero Working Paper 2016-14 UNIVERSITY OF MASSACHUSETTS AMHERST Entitlement theory of justice and end-state fairness in the allocation of goods⇤ Biung-Ghi Ju† Juan D. Moreno-Ternero‡ November 18, 2016 Abstract Robert Nozick allegedly introduced his liberal theory of private ownership as an objec- tion to theories of end-state justice. Nevertheless, we show that, in a stylized framework for the allocation of goods in joint ventures, both approaches can be seen as complemen- tary. More precisely, in such a context, self-ownership (the basis for Nozick’s entitlement theory of justice) followed by voluntary transfer (Nozick’s principle of just transfer) can lead to end-state fairness (as well as Pareto efficiency).
    [Show full text]
  • Murray N. Rothbard: Mr. Libertarian
    Murray N. Rothbard: Mr. Libertarian di Wendy McElroy Murray N. Rothbard (1926-1995) – the greatest libertarian theorist of the 20th century – expressed what he considered to be the central political issue confronting mankind. He wrote, “My own basic perspective on the history of man...is to place central importance on the great conflict which is eternally waged between Liberty and Power.”1 Liberty v. Power. In its most blatant form, the struggle manifests itself as war between the peaceful, productive individual and the intrusive State that usurps those products. The tension between freedom and authority is hardly a new subject for political commentary. But Rothbard managed to bring a newness to everything he touched intellectually. Rothbard was a system builder. Unsatisfied with past attempts to present a “philosophy of freedom,” Rothbard sought to create an interdisciplinary system of thought that used the struggle between Liberty and Power as its integrating theme. He explained, “Strands and remnants of libertarian doctrines are, indeed, all around us. ... But only libertarianism takes these strands and remnants and integrates them into a mighty, logical, and consistent system.”2 Without such a systematic world view, he believed Liberty could not succeed. In forty-five years of scholarship and activism, Rothbard produced over two dozen books and thousands of articles that made sense of the world from a radical individualist perspective. In doing so, it is no exaggeration to say that Rothbard created the modern libertarian movement.3 Specifically, he refined and fused together: • natural law theory, using a basic Aristotelian or Randian approach; • the radical civil libertarianism of 19th century individualist-anarchists, especially Lysander Spooner and Benjamin Tucker; • the free market philosophy of Austrian economists, in particular Ludwig von Mises, into which he incorporated sweeping economic histories; and, • the foreign policy of the American Old Right – that is, isolationism.
    [Show full text]
  • Natural Resources and Natural Law Part I: Prior Appropriation
    SJ Quinney College of Law, University of Utah Utah Law Digital Commons Utah Law Faculty Scholarship Utah Law Scholarship 3-2018 Natural Resources and Natural Law Part I: Prior Appropriation Robert W. Adler S.J. Quinney College of Law, University of Utah Follow this and additional works at: https://dc.law.utah.edu/scholarship Part of the Environmental Law Commons, and the Natural Resources Law Commons Recommended Citation Adler, Robert W., "Natural Resources and Natural Law Part I: Prior Appropriation" (2018). Utah Law Faculty Scholarship. 93. https://dc.law.utah.edu/scholarship/93 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Utah Law Scholarship at Utah Law Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Utah Law Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of Utah Law Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Natural Resources and Natural Law Part I: Prior Appropriation Robert W. Adler* Abstract In recent years there has been a resurgence of civil disobedience over public land policy in the West, sometimes characterized by armed confrontations between ranchers and federal officials. This trend reflects renewed assertions that applicable positive law violates the natural rights (sometimes of purportedly divine origin) of ranchers and other land users, particularly under the prior appropriation doctrine and grounded in Lockean theories of property. At the same time, Native Americans and environmental activists on the opposite side of the political-environmental spectrum have also relied on civil disobedience to assert natural rights to a healthy environment, based on public trust and other principles.
    [Show full text]
  • Individual Autonomy and State Involvement in Health Care
    J Med Ethics: first published as 10.1136/jme.27.4.240 on 1 August 2001. Downloaded from Journal of Medical Ethics 2001;27:240–244 Individual autonomy and state involvement in health care Thomas Rice UCLA School of Public Heath, Los Angeles, USA Abstract this have for the role that government does–and This article examines the ethical basis for government should–have in health care? This article considers involvement in health care. It first provides the case for these issues. individual autonomy, focusing on the justifications–particularly ethical ones–for allowing The case for individual autonomy individuals to make their own choices in health care, There are many reasons to believe that individuals and to control more of their own resources in doing so. should be able to make their own choices in health Next, it provides the opposite case–for abridging care. Moreover, there are reasons to think they individual autonomy, and in particular, for should have control over (more of) their resources redistributing resources from those who are well oV to in order to make these choices rather than having those who are not. The overriding reason for favouring them taxed away by government. This section the latter case, which trumps the notion of individual focuses on three major advantages of consumer autonomy, is to ensure that individuals who are at a sovereignty in health care. These advantages are disadvantage have an equal probability of attaining categorised below under the headings of economic good health. eYciency, psychology, and fairness. (Journal of Medical Ethics 2001;27:240–244) Keywords: Distributive justice; ethics; government; health ECONOMIC EFFICIENCY care The central tenet of traditional economic theory is that consumers will be best oV if they are allowed to make their own choices about the goods and serv- Introduction ices they consume.
    [Show full text]
  • Self-Ownership, World-Ownership, and Initial Acquisition
    LIBERTARIAN PAPERS VOL. 2, ART. NO. 36 (2010) SELF-OWNERSHIP, WORLD-OWNERSHIP, AND INITIAL ACQUISITION TRISTAN ROGERS* 1. Introduction G.A. COHEN’S WORK Self-Ownership, Freedom, and Equality1 is a highly regarded and widely influential critique of Robert Nozick’s canonical libertarian work Anarchy, State, and Utopia.2 Since much contemporary libertarian theory is indebted to Nozick, a successful dismantling of Nozick’s theory would seem to pose quite a threat to libertarianism more generally. But as Nozick himself said, “There is room for words on subjects other than last words.”3 Indeed, one of the chief virtues of Nozick’s work is its open exploratory approach. So, just as Nozick provides a starting point for the exploration of libertarianism, Cohen forces the libertarian theorist to confront difficult challenges, which sometimes result in the reaffirmation of a position, sometimes in revision. This eventually spawns a deeper and stronger theory. It is a modest step towards this lofty goal that this paper attempts. To orient the debate, I begin by briefly sketching Nozick’s familiar Entitlement Theory of Justice. I then present and respond to Cohen’s criticism at three stages. The first is the self-ownership stage, where Cohen does not attempt to refute the thesis of self-ownership, but instead attempts to cast doubt on it, in *Tristan Rogers ([email protected]) is an MA Candidate, Department of Philosophy, Queen’s University, in Kingston, ON, Canada. Thanks are due to Pablo Gilabert, Tara Myketiak, Jan Narveson, David Schmidtz, the editor of this journal, and an anonymous referee for helpful comments on earlier drafts.
    [Show full text]
  • WINTER 2014 Journal of Austrian Economics
    The VOL. 17 | NO. 4 | 543–549 QUARTERLY WINTER 2014 JOURNAL of AUSTRIAN ECONOMICS BOOK REVIEW MASTERS OF THE UNIVERSE: HAYEK, FRIEDMAN, AND THE BIRTH OF NEOLIBERAL POLITICS DANIEL STEDMAN JONES PRINCETON: PRINCETON UNIVERSITY PREss, 2012, 418 pp. GREG KAZA ritics of neoliberalism and its variants including Misesianism have responded to its emergence in two distinct ways: Cpejoratively,1 or scholarly discourse that seeks to engage neoliberal proponents. The first approach is traceable to the Marxists Kapelush (1925) and Marcuse ([1934] 1968). This low road has been traveled more recently by Krohn (1981), Delong (2009) and Seymour (2010), who, a la Marcuse, smear Mises as pro-fascist when government and private archives show the Austrian worked Greg Kaza ([email protected]) is executive director of the Arkansas Policy Foundation. 1 Murray Rothbard has used the term smearbund to describe this approach. 543 544 The Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics 17, No. 4 (2014) with U.S. intelligence against Italian fascism and German Nazism in the World War II era.2 The second is a high road, a sincere, scholarly approach to understand and/or engage neoliberalism, the term chosen by participants at the Colloque Walter Lippmann in 1938. Early examples include Brutzkus (1928) and Lange (1939). Recent works include Mirowski and Plehwe (2009),3 and this book by Jones, a London barrister relying on private archives in the U.S. and U.K. Jones claims three historiographic contributions: neoliberalism’s transatlantic nature; intellectual history; and emergence as a political and intellectual movement. His work explains neoliberals’ emergence on macroeconomics and public policy, but overlooks Mises’s archives, and is selective in reporting on the 1960s-era U.S.
    [Show full text]
  • Farm Tenancy and Productivity in Agriculture: the Case of the United St a Tes*
    JAMES O. BRAY FARM TENANCY AND PRODUCTIVITY IN AGRICULTURE: THE CASE OF THE UNITED ST A TES* The need to attain increased food production in underdeveloped countries has encouraged the continuing search for the secrets of agricultural success in the United- States. The complexity of American agriculture in its unique social and economic setting is so great that it is futile to hope for a simple explanation. There is one conclusion, nevertheless, which seems to have gained wide acceptance. It is the belief that American agricultural performance is, to an important degree, a result of the system of land tenure characterized by the family-owned and -operated farm. The purpose of this paper is to re-examine, in the light of American experi­ ence, certain issues concerning agricultural land use, hitherto emphasized by economists, arising from farm lease contracts. An effort will be made to inquire into the relative merits of owner operation and tenant operation as competitive ways of organizing agricultural production. Public preference for, and support of, farm ownership by operators has been a dominant feature of United States agricultural policy. The weight of economic opinion has generally favored the conclusion that the operation of a large pro­ portion of farm land by tenants is likely to lead to inefficient, if not wasteful or destructive, resource use. Yet, in 1959, a higher proportion of all land in farms was operated either by tenants or by part owners than in 1900. Moreover, in the areas with the most advanced production techniques, the proportion of leased tenant-operated land was in 1959 larger than the national average.
    [Show full text]
  • Austrian Economics As Political Philosophy J. Mikael Olsson
    S TOCKHOLM STUDIES IN POLITICS 161 Austrian Economics as Political Philosophy J. Mikael Olsson Austrian Economics as Political Philosophy J. Mikael Olsson ©J. Mikael Olsson, Stockholm University 2015 ISSN 0346-6620 ISBN 978-91-7649-062-4 Printed in Sweden by US-AB, Stockholm 2015 Distributor: Department of Political Science, Stockholm University. Cover image: Micaela Adolfsson (based on “Under the Thumb” by Thomas Nast, 1871). Contents I. Introduction ............................................................................................... 7 Aims of the Study ...................................................................................... 12 Some Words on Method ............................................................................ 17 The Metaethical Dimension ...................................................................... 22 Earlier Research ........................................................................................ 31 Sources ...................................................................................................... 33 Disposition ................................................................................................ 34 Part 1: Economics ........................................................................................ 35 II. A Brief History of Economic Thought ................................................. 37 Mercantilism and Its Critics ...................................................................... 38 Quesnay and Smith ...................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • The Moral Duty to Reject Nozick's Entitlement Theory and Advocate
    The moral duty to reject Nozick’s Entitlement Theory and advocate for Distributive Justice Cathy Darling The philosopher Robert Nozick argues that taxation to fund distributive justice such as welfare payments is morally wrong.1 This essay will explain and assess his entitlement theory of justice and will conclude that an ideal moral code ought to reject Nozick’s theory. Nozick’s Entitlement Theory of Justice As a libertarian, Nozick argues that the starting ethical principle to guide state action ought to be the non-violation of individual rights. Since assets and goods originated from somewhere, he proposes that we establish the justice of both the original acquisition and the later transfer of assets and goods (“holdings”). If current possession of goods came about through past injustice, Nozick argues that ‘rectification’ is necessary.2 Simply put, Nozick’s entitlement theory of justice demands that if the historic transactions of exchange were fair, there is no moral justification for state infringement on the current ownership of holdings. Imagine both myself and Bob are college students. In my spare time I work 20 hours a week while Bob prefers to spend his spare time reading philosophical texts. When I am paid, my salary has tax deductions which reduce my earnings by 20%. Ultimately I have worked 4 hours for free for the state coffers. Bob and I benefit equally from the goods that a minimum 1 Robert, Nozick. The Entitlement Theory of Justice. p, 537. 2 ibid., p, 528. state provides such as defence, security and policing. Yet all things being equal, should Bob be forced to give up 4 hours of his time reading philosophy to work for the common good of serving the needs of others? Presumably most would agree forced labour would be an unjustified infringement on Bob’s personal freedom.
    [Show full text]
  • Justice and Property Rights
    Justice and Property Rights di Murray N. Rothbard THE FAILURE OF UTILITARIANISM Until very recently, free-market economists paid little attention to the entities actually being exchanged on the very market they have advocated so strongly. Wrapped up in the workings and advantages of freedom of trade, enterprise, investment, and the price system, economists tended to lose sight of the things being exchanged on that market. Namely, they lost sight of the fact that when $10,000 is being exchanged for a machine, or $1 for a hula hoop, what is actually being exchanged is the title of ownership to each of these goods. In short, when I buy a hula hoop for $1, what I am actually doing is exchanging my title of ownership to the dollar in exchange for the ownership title to the hula hoop; the retailer is doing the exact opposite. 1 But this means that economists’ habitual attempts to be wertfrei , or at the least to confine their advocacy to the processes of trade and exchange, cannot be maintained. For if myself and the retailer are indeed to be free to trade the dollar for the hula hoop without coercive interference by third parties, then this can only be done if these economists will proclaim the justice and the propriety of my original ownership of the dollar and the retailer’s ownership of the hula hoop. In short, for an economist to say that X and Y should be free to trade Good A for Good B unmolested by third parties, he must also say that X legitimately and properly owns Good A and that Y legitimately owns Good B.
    [Show full text]
  • Libertarianism and Original Appropriation
    Historia i Polityka No. 22 (29)/2017, pp. 43–56 ISSN 1899-5160, e-ISSN 2391-7652 www.hip.umk.pl DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.12775/HiP.2017.026 Łukasz DomINIAK Nicolaus Copernicus University, Toruń, Poland Libertarianism and Original Appropriation Libertarianizm i pierwotne zawłaszczenie • A bst ra kt • • A bst ract • Artykuł poświęcony jest problemowi struktury The article is devoted to the problem of the libertariańskiej teorii sprawiedliwości. Prezen- structure of libertarian theory of justice. It tuje on mapę głównych pojęć i zasad tej teorii tries to present a map of the main concepts oraz bada jej możliwe uzasadnienia. Artykuł wy- and principles of this theory and to investigate jaśnia takie fundamentalne pojęcia jak posiada- its possible justifications. It explains such fun- nie, własność, pierwotne zawłaszczenie, labory- damental concepts as original appropriation, styczna czy posesoryjna teoria własności. Arty- homesteading, labour theory of property or kuł analizuje mocne i słabe strony alternatyw- first possession theory of original appropria- nych zasad libertariańskiej teorii sprawiedliwo- tion. The article shows merits and drawbacks ści rządzących pierwotnym nabyciem oraz kre- of alternative libertarian principles of justice śli szkic oryginalnego uzasadnienia posesoryjnej in first acquisition and proposes a sketch of teorii własności. an original justification for the first possession theory of original appropriation. Słowa kluczowe: libertarianizm, pierwot- Key words: libertarianism, original appro- ne zawłaszczenie, laborystyczna teoria własno- priation, homesteading, mixing labour, first po- ści, zmieszanie pracy, posesoryjna teoria wła- ssession, occupancy, non-contradiction law, ri- sności, pierwsze posiadanie, prawo niesprzecz- ghts compossibility, theory of justice ności, komposybilność uprawnień, teoria spra- wiedliwości 44 Historia i Polityka • No.
    [Show full text]