Contexts, Bi-Heyting Algebras and a New Logic for Quantum Systems Oberseminar Theoretische Informatik FAU Erlangen 4

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Contexts, Bi-Heyting Algebras and a New Logic for Quantum Systems Oberseminar Theoretische Informatik FAU Erlangen 4 Contexts, Bi-Heyting Algebras and a New Logic for Quantum Systems Oberseminar Theoretische Informatik FAU Erlangen 4. November 2014 Andreas D¨oring Theoretische Physik I, FAU Erlangen [email protected] Andreas D¨oring (Erlangen) Bi-Heyting algebras and quantum systems 1 / 49 \Never express yourself more clearly than you are able to think." Niels Bohr Andreas D¨oring (Erlangen) Bi-Heyting algebras and quantum systems 2 / 49 References This talk is based on AD,\Topos-based Logic for Quantum Systems and Bi-Heyting Algebras", to appear in Logic & Algebra in Quantum Computing, Lecture Notes in Logic, Association for Symbolic Logic in conjunction with Cambridge University Press (2012); [arXiv:1202.2750] Some good references on standard quantum logic are: G. Birkhoff, J. von Neumann, \The Logic of Quantum Mechanics", Annals of Mathematics 37, No. 4, 823{843 (1936). Varadarajan, Geometry of Quantum Theory, second ed., Springer (1985). M. Dalla Chiara, R. Giuntini, \Quantum Logics", in Handbook of Philosophical Logic, Kluwer (2002); [arXiv:quant-ph/0101028v2] Andreas D¨oring (Erlangen) Bi-Heyting algebras and quantum systems 3 / 49 Standard quantum logic Standard quantum logic Andreas D¨oring (Erlangen) Bi-Heyting algebras and quantum systems 4 / 49 Standard quantum logic Standard quantum logic Some basics of standard quantum logic: Birkhoff and von Neumann suggested to use the complete orthomodular lattice P(H) of projections on a separable, complex Hilbert space H as representatives of propositions. (Fine point: modular vs. orthomodular lattices.) The link between (pre-mathematical) propositions \A " ∆” and projections is provided by the spectral theorem. Pure quantum states j i (roughly) are models of this propositional logic, but only specific projections are assigned true or false: if P^ j i = j i, then the proposition represented by P^ is true in the state j i; if P^ j i = 0, then the proposition is false in the state j i. In general, only a probability between 0 and 1 for finding the outcome of a measurement of A to lie in a Borel set ∆ can be given. After measurement, the quantum state has changed to the eigenstate corresponding to the outcome. Andreas D¨oring (Erlangen) Bi-Heyting algebras and quantum systems 5 / 49 Standard quantum logic Some (problematic) features of quantum logic Propositions form a non-distributive orthomodular lattice. Quantum states do not assign true or false to all propositions \A " ∆”; in general, one can only obtain probabilities. Lack of two-valued models; instrumentalism. A disjunction \A " ∆ or B " Γ” can be true in a state j i despite the fact that neither \A " ∆” nor \B " Γ” are true in the state. This is due to superposition. There a many meets in P(H) that are physically meaningless. This is due to the failure to take contextuality into account. The implication problem: there is no material implication, and the implicative rule does not hold. This is due to non-distributivity. There is no algebra of subsets representing propositions, but an algebra of subspaces. Most problematic features result from this (insufficient?) geometric underpinning of quantum logic. Andreas D¨oring (Erlangen) Bi-Heyting algebras and quantum systems 6 / 49 A state space model for quantum systems A state space model for quantum systems Andreas D¨oring (Erlangen) Bi-Heyting algebras and quantum systems 7 / 49 A state space model for quantum systems The topos approach The topos approach to the formulation of physical theories was initiated by Chris Isham '97 and Isham/Butterfield '98{'02, addresses certain structural and conceptual issues in the foundations of physics, uses topos theory to give new geometric and logical ideas for physics, aims to provide a new way of formulating physical theories in general, and quantum theory in particular { not based on Hilbert spaces, not `just another interpretation', is motivated by questions on the way to quantum gravity (QG) and quantum cosmology (QC), most work so far is on standard, non-relativistic quantum theory { natural starting point, testing ground. Other researchers include: Landsman, Heunen, Spitters, Nakayama, Vickers, Fauser, Flori, ... Andreas D¨oring (Erlangen) Bi-Heyting algebras and quantum systems 8 / 49 A state space model for quantum systems Where are we now? The topos approach is very much work in progress, so think of Andreas D¨oring (Erlangen) Bi-Heyting algebras and quantum systems 9 / 49 A state space model for quantum systems Classical physics In classical physics, a physical quantity A is described by a (measurable) real-valued function fA on the state space (phase space) P: In a given state s 2 P, a physical quantity A has the value fA(s) 2 R. Andreas D¨oring (Erlangen) Bi-Heyting algebras and quantum systems 10 / 49 A state space model for quantum systems Classical physics (2) Propositions such as \A " ∆”, i.e., \the physical quantity A has a value in the Borel set ∆ ⊆ R", are represented by subsets of the state space: The Borel subsets of P form a σ-complete Boolean algebra. Pure states s 2 P are models of this propositional logic. Andreas D¨oring (Erlangen) Bi-Heyting algebras and quantum systems 11 / 49 A state space model for quantum systems The Kochen-Specker theorem and instrumentalism But can quantum theory be cast in such a form? Obstacle: Theorem (Kochen-Specker 1967): If dim(H) ≥ 3, then there is no state space model of quantum theory (under mild and natural conditions). In logical terms, there is no way to assign true or false to all propositions \A " ∆" at the same time. Usual answer: interpret propositions in an instrumentalist way, and use probabilities, because repeatedly measuring the same physical quantity A in the same state j i can give different outcomes { states do not assign truth values to all propositions. This is not what we want to do { we want to provide a quantum state space in spite of the KS theorem. Andreas D¨oring (Erlangen) Bi-Heyting algebras and quantum systems 12 / 49 A state space model for quantum systems C ∗-algebras and von Neumann algebras As a reminder: Definition A C ∗-algebra A is a complex Banach algebra with an involution (−)∗ : A!A such that 8a 2 A : ja∗aj = jaj2: A W ∗-algebra is a C ∗-algebra that is the dual of a Banach space M. Every C ∗-algebra can be faithfully represented as a norm-closed subalgebra of B(H), the algebra of bounded linear operators on some Hilbert space H. Every W ∗-algebra can be represented as a weakly closed subalgebra of some B(H). Weakly closed subalgebras of B(H) are called von Neumann algebras. We will often use `hats' (as in A^; B^; :::) when denoting elements of operator algebras. Andreas D¨oring (Erlangen) Bi-Heyting algebras and quantum systems 13 / 49 A state space model for quantum systems The basic idea With a quantum system (described by a noncommutative von Neumann algebra N , e.g. N = B(H)), we associate a topos and define a spectral object Σ in the topos. The spectral presheaf Σ is a generalised set, playing the role of a state space for the quantum system (notwithstanding the Kochen-Specker theorem!). Structure of state space determines logical structure of a theory: Classical physics: Borel subsets of state space S represent propositions \A " ∆”, form Boolean algebra. Quantum physics: clopen subobjects of the state space Σ represent propositions \A " ∆”, form bi-Heyting algebra. Andreas D¨oring (Erlangen) Bi-Heyting algebras and quantum systems 14 / 49 A state space model for quantum systems The context category Let S be a quantum system, described by a noncommutative von Neumann algebra N ⊆ B(H). Let V be a non-trivial commutative von Neumann subalgebra of N which has the same unit element as N . This gives and is given by a set of commuting self-adjoint operators in N . We call V a context. Each context V is a partial classical perspective on the quantum system. The main idea: take all classical perspectives/contexts together to obtain a complete picture of the quantum system. Concretely, we consider the set V(N ) of all contexts, partially ordered under inclusion. This poset is called the context category. Andreas D¨oring (Erlangen) Bi-Heyting algebras and quantum systems 15 / 49 A state space model for quantum systems Gelfand spectra Each commutative von Neumann algebra V has a Gelfand spectrum ΣV , consisting of the algebra morphisms λ : V −! C: These maps are also pure states of V . The Gelfand topology is the ∗ (relative) weak -topology on ΣV . With respect to this topology, ΣV is an extremely disconnected compact Hausdorff space. For a commutative von Neumann algebra V , the projection lattice P(V ) is a complete Boolean algebra. Let λ 2 ΣV , and let P^ 2 P(V ), representing some proposition about an A^ 2 Vsa. Note that λ(P^) = λ(P^ 2) = λ(P^)2 2 f0; 1g ' ffalse; trueg; so the elements of ΣV are the models of the classical logic described by P(V ). Andreas D¨oring (Erlangen) Bi-Heyting algebras and quantum systems 16 / 49 A state space model for quantum systems The spectral presheaf If V 0 ⊂ V is a von Neumann subalgebra, then there is a canonical restriction map rV ;V 0 :ΣV −! ΣV 0 λ 7−! λjV 0 : This map is continuous, closed, open and surjective. Definition Let N be a von Neumann algebra, and let V(N ) be its context category. The spectral presheaf Σ of N over V(N ) is defined (a) on objects: for all V 2 V(N ), let ΣV := ΣV , 0 (b) on arrows: for all inclusions iV 0V : V ,! V , let Σ(iV 0V ) = rV ;V 0 . Andreas D¨oring (Erlangen) Bi-Heyting algebras and quantum systems 17 / 49 The bi-Heyting algebra of clopen subobjects The bi-Heyting algebra of clopen subobjects Andreas D¨oring (Erlangen) Bi-Heyting algebras and quantum systems 18 / 49 The bi-Heyting algebra of clopen subobjects Bi-Heyting algebras { history Rauszer: bi-Heyting algebras in superintuitionistic logic ('73{'77) Lawvere: co-Heyting and bi-Heyting algebras in category and topos theory, in particular in connection with continuum physics ('86, '91) Reyes/Makkai ('95) and Reyes/Zolfaghari ('96): bi-Heyting algebras and modal logic Bezhanishvili et al.
Recommended publications
  • A First Introduction to the Algebra of Sentences
    A First Introduction to the Algebra of Sentences Silvio Ghilardi Dipartimento di Scienze dell'Informazione, Universit`adegli Studi di Milano September 2000 These notes cover the content of a basic course in propositional alge- braic logic given by the author at the italian School of Logic held in Cesena, September 18-23, 2000. They are addressed to people having few background in Symbolic Logic and they are mostly intended to develop algebraic methods for establishing basic metamathematical results (like representation theory and completeness, ¯nite model property, disjunction property, Beth de¯n- ability and Craig interpolation). For the sake of simplicity, only the case of propositional intuitionistic logic is covered, although the methods we are explaining apply to other logics (e.g. modal) with minor modi¯cations. The purity and the conceptual clarity of such methods is our main concern; for these reasons we shall feel free to apply basic mathematical tools from cate- gory theory. The choice of the material and the presentation style for a basic course are always motivated by the occasion and by the lecturer's taste (that's the only reason why they might be stimulating) and these notes follow such a rule. They are expecially intended to provide an introduction to category theoretic methods, by applying them to topics suggested by propositional logic. Unfortunately, time was not su±cient to the author to include all material he planned to include; for this reason, important and interesting develope- ments are mentioned in the ¯nal Section of these notes, where the reader can however only ¯nd suggestions for further readings.
    [Show full text]
  • The Petit Topos of Globular Sets
    Journal of Pure and Applied Algebra 154 (2000) 299–315 www.elsevier.com/locate/jpaa View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector The petit topos of globular sets Ross Street ∗ Macquarie University, N. S. W. 2109, Australia Communicated by M. Tierney Dedicated to Bill Lawvere Abstract There are now several deÿnitions of weak !-category [1,2,5,19]. What is pleasing is that they are not achieved by ad hoc combinatorics. In particular, the theory of higher operads which underlies Michael Batanin’s deÿnition is based on globular sets. The purpose of this paper is to show that many of the concepts of [2] (also see [17]) arise in the natural development of category theory internal to the petit 1 topos Glob of globular sets. For example, higher spans turn out to be internal sets, and, in a sense, trees turn out to be internal natural numbers. c 2000 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved. MSC: 18D05 1. Globular objects and !-categories A globular set is an inÿnite-dimensional graph. To formalize this, let G denote the category whose objects are natural numbers and whose only non-identity arrows are m;m : m → n for all m¡n ∗ Tel.: +61-2-9850-8921; fax: 61-2-9850-8114. E-mail address: [email protected] (R. Street). 1 The distinction between toposes that are “space like” (or petit) and those which are “category-of-space like” (or gros) was investigated by Lawvere [9,10]. The gros topos of re exive globular sets has been studied extensively by Michael Roy [12].
    [Show full text]
  • Basic Category Theory and Topos Theory
    Basic Category Theory and Topos Theory Jaap van Oosten Jaap van Oosten Department of Mathematics Utrecht University The Netherlands Revised, February 2016 Contents 1 Categories and Functors 1 1.1 Definitions and examples . 1 1.2 Some special objects and arrows . 5 2 Natural transformations 8 2.1 The Yoneda lemma . 8 2.2 Examples of natural transformations . 11 2.3 Equivalence of categories; an example . 13 3 (Co)cones and (Co)limits 16 3.1 Limits . 16 3.2 Limits by products and equalizers . 23 3.3 Complete Categories . 24 3.4 Colimits . 25 4 A little piece of categorical logic 28 4.1 Regular categories and subobjects . 28 4.2 The logic of regular categories . 34 4.3 The language L(C) and theory T (C) associated to a regular cat- egory C ................................ 39 4.4 The category C(T ) associated to a theory T : Completeness Theorem 41 4.5 Example of a regular category . 44 5 Adjunctions 47 5.1 Adjoint functors . 47 5.2 Expressing (co)completeness by existence of adjoints; preserva- tion of (co)limits by adjoint functors . 52 6 Monads and Algebras 56 6.1 Algebras for a monad . 57 6.2 T -Algebras at least as complete as D . 61 6.3 The Kleisli category of a monad . 62 7 Cartesian closed categories and the λ-calculus 64 7.1 Cartesian closed categories (ccc's); examples and basic facts . 64 7.2 Typed λ-calculus and cartesian closed categories . 68 7.3 Representation of primitive recursive functions in ccc's with nat- ural numbers object .
    [Show full text]
  • Distribution Algebras and Duality
    Advances in Mathematics 156, 133155 (2000) doi:10.1006Âaima.2000.1947, available online at http:ÂÂwww.idealibrary.com on Distribution Algebras and Duality Marta Bunge Department of Mathematics and Statistics, McGill University, 805 Sherbrooke Street West, Montreal, Quebec, Canada H3A 2K6 Jonathon Funk Department of Mathematics, University of Saskatchewan, 106 Wiggins Road, Saskatoon, Saskatchewan, Canada S7N 5E6 Mamuka Jibladze CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by ElsevierDepartement - Publisher Connector de Mathematique , Louvain-la-Neuve, Chemin du Cyclotron 2, 1348 Louvain-la-Neuve, Belgium; and Institute of Mathematics, Georgian Academy of Sciences, M. Alexidze Street 1, Tbilisi 380093, Republic of Georgia and Thomas Streicher Fachbereich 4 Mathematik, TU Darmstadt, Schlo;gartenstrasse 7, 64289 Darmstadt, Germany Communicated by Ross Street Received May 20, 2000; accepted May 20, 2000 0. INTRODUCTION Since being introduced by F. W. Lawvere in 1983, considerable progress has been made in the study of distributions on toposes from a variety of viewpoints [59, 12, 15, 19, 24]. However, much work still remains to be done in this area. The purpose of this paper is to deepen our understanding of topos distributions by exploring a (dual) lattice-theoretic notion of dis- tribution algebra. We characterize the distribution algebras in E relative to S as the S-bicomplete S-atomic Heyting algebras in E. As an illustration, we employ distribution algebras explicitly in order to give an alternative description of the display locale (complete spread) of a distribution [7, 10, 12]. 133 0001-8708Â00 35.00 Copyright 2000 by Academic Press All rights of reproduction in any form reserved.
    [Show full text]
  • Bernays–G Odel Type Theory
    Journal of Pure and Applied Algebra 178 (2003) 1–23 www.elsevier.com/locate/jpaa Bernays–G&odel type theory Carsten Butz∗ Department of Mathematics and Statistics, Burnside Hall, McGill University, 805 Sherbrooke Street West, Montreal, Que., Canada H3A 2K6 Received 21 November 1999; received in revised form 3 April 2001 Communicated by P. Johnstone Dedicated to Saunders Mac Lane, on the occasion of his 90th birthday Abstract We study the type-theoretical analogue of Bernays–G&odel set-theory and its models in cate- gories. We introduce the notion of small structure on a category, and if small structure satisÿes certain axioms we can think of the underlying category as a category of classes. Our axioms imply the existence of a co-variant powerset monad on the underlying category of classes, which sends a class to the class of its small subclasses. Simple ÿxed points of this and related monads are shown to be models of intuitionistic Zermelo–Fraenkel set-theory (IZF). c 2002 Published by Elsevier Science B.V. MSC: Primary: 03E70; secondary: 03C90; 03F55 0. Introduction The foundations of mathematics accepted by most working mathematicians is Zermelo–Fraenkel set-theory (ZF). The basic notion is that of a set, the abstract model of a collection. There are other closely related systems, like for example that of Bernays and G&odel (BG) based on the distinction between sets and classes: every set is a class, but the only elements of classes are sets. The theory (BG) axiomatizes which classes behave well, that is, are sets. In fact, the philosophy of Bernays–G&odel set-theory is that small classes behave well.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:2010.05167V1 [Cs.PL] 11 Oct 2020
    A Categorical Programming Language Tatsuya Hagino arXiv:2010.05167v1 [cs.PL] 11 Oct 2020 Doctor of Philosophy University of Edinburgh 1987 Author’s current address: Tatsuya Hagino Faculty of Environment and Information Studies Keio University Endoh 5322, Fujisawa city, Kanagawa Japan 252-0882 E-mail: [email protected] Abstract A theory of data types and a programming language based on category theory are presented. Data types play a crucial role in programming. They enable us to write programs easily and elegantly. Various programming languages have been developed, each of which may use different kinds of data types. Therefore, it becomes important to organize data types systematically so that we can understand the relationship between one data type and another and investigate future directions which lead us to discover exciting new data types. There have been several approaches to systematically organize data types: alge- braic specification methods using algebras, domain theory using complete par- tially ordered sets and type theory using the connection between logics and data types. Here, we use category theory. Category theory has proved to be remark- ably good at revealing the nature of mathematical objects, and we use it to understand the true nature of data types in programming. We organize data types under a new categorical notion of F,G-dialgebras which is an extension of the notion of adjunctions as well as that of T -algebras. T - algebras are also used in domain theory, but while domain theory needs some primitive data types, like products, to start with, we do not need any.
    [Show full text]
  • Topos Theory
    Topos Theory Olivia Caramello Introduction Interpreting logic in categories First-order logic First-order languages First-order theories Categorical semantics Topos Theory Classes of ‘logical’ categories The interpretation of logic in categories The interpretation of formulae Examples Soundness and completeness Olivia Caramello Toposes as mathematical universes The internal language Kripke-Joyal semantics For further reading Topos Theory Interpreting first-order logic in categories Olivia Caramello Introduction • In Logic, first-order languages are a wide class of formal Interpreting logic in categories languages used for talking about mathematical structures of First-order logic any kind (where the restriction ‘first-order’ means that First-order languages quantification is allowed only over individuals rather than over First-order theories collections of individuals or higher-order constructions on Categorical semantics them). Classes of ‘logical’ categories • A first-order language contains sorts, which are meant to The interpretation of formulae represent different kinds of individuals, terms, which denote Examples individuals, and formulae, which make assertions about the Soundness and completeness individuals. Compound terms and formulae are formed by Toposes as mathematical using various logical operators. universes • It is well-known that first-order languages can always be The internal language interpreted in the context of (a given model of) set theory. In Kripke-Joyal semantics this lecture, we will show that these languages can also be For further reading meaningfully interpreted in a category, provided that the latter possesses enough categorical structure to allow the interpretation of the given fragment of logic. In fact, sorts will be interpreted as objects, terms as arrows and formulae as subobjects, in a way that respects the logical structure of compound expressions.
    [Show full text]
  • Induced Morphisms Between Heyting-Valued Models
    Induced morphisms between Heyting-valued models Jos´eGoudet Alvim∗ Universidade de S˜ao Paulo, S˜ao Paulo, Brasil Arthur Francisco Schwerz Cahali† Universidade de S˜ao Paulo, S˜ao Paulo, Brasil Hugo Luiz Mariano‡ Universidade de S˜ao Paulo, S˜ao Paulo, Brasil December 4, 2019 Abstract To the best of our knowledge, there are very few results on how Heyting-valued models are affected by the morphisms on the complete Heyting algebras that de- termine them: the only cases found in the literature are concerning automorphisms of complete Boolean algebras and complete embedding between them (i.e., injec- tive Boolean algebra homomorphisms that preserves arbitrary suprema and arbi- trary infima). In the present work, we consider and explore how more general kinds of morphisms between complete Heyting algebras H and H′ induce arrows ′ between V(H) and V(H ), and between their corresponding localic toposes Set(H) ′ (≃ Sh (H)) and Set(H ) (≃ Sh (H′)). In more details: any geometric morphism ′ f ∗ : Set(H) → Set(H ), (that automatically came from a unique locale morphism ′ f : H → H′), can be “lifted” to an arrow f˜ : V(H) → V(H ). We also provide also ′ some semantic preservation results concerning this arrow f˜ : V(H) → V(H ). Introduction The expression “Heyting-valued model of set theory” has two (related) meanings, both arXiv:1910.08193v2 [math.CT] 3 Dec 2019 parametrized by a complete Heyting algebra H: (i) The canonical Heyting-valued models in set theory, V(H), as introduced in the setting of complete boolean algebras in the 1960s by D. Scott, P.
    [Show full text]
  • Hilbert Algebras As Implicative Partial Semilattices
    DOI: 10.2478/s11533-007-0008-2 Research article CEJM 5(2) 2007 264–279 Hilbert algebras as implicative partial semilattices J¯anis C¯ırulis∗ University of Latvia, LV-1586 Riga, Latvia Received 15 August 2006; accepted 16 February 2007 Abstract: The infimum of elements a and b of a Hilbert algebra are said to be the compatible meet of a and b, if the elements a and b are compatible in a certain strict sense. The subject of the paper will be Hilbert algebras equipped with the compatible meet operation, which normally is partial. A partial lower semilattice is shown to be a reduct of such an expanded Hilbert algebra iff both algebras have the same filters. An expanded Hilbert algebra is actually an implicative partial semilattice (i.e., a relative subalgebra of an implicative semilattice), and conversely. The implication in an implicative partial semilattice is characterised in terms of filters of the underlying partial semilattice. c Versita Warsaw and Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg. All rights reserved. Keywords: Compatible elements, filter, Hilbert algebra, implication, implicative semilattice, meet, partial semilattice MSC (2000): 06A12, 03G25 1 Introduction Hilbert algebras, or positive implication algebras [35], are the duals of Henkin algebras called by him implicative models in [21] (this term has also been used for Hilbert algebras [30, 31]). Positive implicative BCK-algebras [24] are actually another version of Henkin algebras (see, e.g. [28, 37]). As a matter of fact, these algebras are an algebraic counterpart of positive implica- tional calculus. Various expansions of Hilbert algebras by a conjunction-like operation have also been studied in the literature.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Glances at Topos Theory
    Some glances at topos theory Francis Borceux Como, 2018 2 Francis Borceux [email protected] Contents 1 Localic toposes 7 1.1 Sheaves on a topological space . 7 1.2 Sheaves on a locale . 10 1.3 Localic toposes . 12 1.4 An application to ring theory . 13 2 Grothendieck toposes 17 2.1 Sheaves on a site . 17 2.2 The associated sheaf functor . 19 2.3 Limits and colimits in Grothendieck toposes . 21 2.4 Closure operator and subobject classifier . 22 3 Elementary toposes 25 3.1 The axioms for a topos . 25 3.2 Some set theoretical notions in a topos . 26 3.3 The slice toposes . 28 3.4 Exactness properties . 29 3.5 Heyting algebras in a topos . 30 4 Internal logic of a topos 33 4.1 The language of a topos . 33 4.2 Interpretation of terms and formulæ . 35 4.3 Propositional calculus in a topos . 37 4.4 Predicate calculus in a topos . 38 4.5 Structure of a topos in its internal language . 40 4.6 Boolean toposes . 41 4.7 The axiom of choice . 42 4.8 The axiom of infinity . 43 5 Morphisms of toposes 45 5.1 Logical morphisms . 45 5.2 Geometric morphisms . 46 5.3 Coherent and geometric formulæ . 48 5.4 Grothendieck topologies revisited . 49 5.5 Internal topologies and sheaves . 50 5.6 Back to Boolean toposes . 52 3 4 CONTENTS 6 Classifying toposes 53 6.1 What is a classifying topos? . 53 6.2 The theory classified by a topos . 54 6.3 Coherent and geometric theories .
    [Show full text]
  • On the Model-Completion of Heyting Algebras Luck Darnière
    On the model-completion of Heyting algebras Luck Darnière To cite this version: Luck Darnière. On the model-completion of Heyting algebras. 2018. hal-01885531 HAL Id: hal-01885531 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01885531 Preprint submitted on 2 Oct 2018 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. On the model-completion of Heyting algebras Luck Darni`ere∗ October 2, 2018 Abstract We axiomatize the model-completion of the theory of Heyting algebras by means of the \Density" and \Splitting" properties in [DJ18], and of a certain \QE Property" that we introduce here. In addition: we prove that this model-completion has a prime model, which is locally finite and which we explicitly construct; we show how the Open Mapping Theorem of [vGR18] can be derived from the QE Property of existentially closed Heyting algebras; and we construct a certain \discriminant" for equations in Heyting algebras, similar to its ring theoretic counterpart. 1 Introduction It is known since [Pit92] that the second-order intuitionist propositional calculus (IPC2) is interpretable in the first-order one (IPC). This proof-theoretic result, after translation in model-theoretic terms, ensures that the theory of Heyting al- gebras has a model-completion (see [GZ97]).
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1410.8780V2 [Math.RA]
    ON SKEW HEYTING ALGEBRAS KARIN CVETKO-VAH Abstract. In the present paper we generalize the notion of a Heyting algebra to the non-commutative setting and hence introduce what we believe to be the proper notion of the implication in skew lattices. We list several examples of skew Heyting algebras, including Heyting algebras, dual skew Boolean alge- bras, conormal skew chains and algebras of partial maps with poset domains. 1. Introduction Non-commutative generalizations of lattices were introduced by Jordan [11] in 1949. The current approach to such objects began with Leech’s 1989 paper on skew lattices [13]. Similarly, skew Boolean algebras are non-commutative general- izations of Boolean algebras. In 1936 Stone proved that each Boolean algebra can be embedded into a field of sets [20]. Likewise, Leech showed in [14, 15] that each right-handed skew Boolean algebra can be embedded into a generic skew Boolean algebra of partial functions from a given set to the codomain {0, 1}. Bignall and Leech [5] showed that skew Boolean algebras play a central role in the study of discriminator varieties. Though not using categorical language, Stone essentially proved in [20] that the category of Boolean algebras and homomorphisms is dual to the category of Boolean topological spaces and continuous maps. Generalizations of this result within the commutative setting yield Priestley duality [16, 17] between bounded distributive lattices and Priestley spaces, and Esakia duality [9] between Heyting algebras and Esakia spaces. (See [4] for details.) In a recent paper [10] on Esakia’s work, Gehrke showed that Heyting algebras may be understood as those distributive lattices for which the embedding into their Booleanisation has a right adjoint.
    [Show full text]