Texts, We Are Willing to Make More Specific Judgements

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Texts, We Are Willing to Make More Specific Judgements UNIVERSITY OF READING What is the Virtuous Emotional Response to our Wrongdoing? PhD Department of Philosophy George Mason September 2015 Abstract Though we are inclined to think those who have acted wrongly should feel bad, we also worry that feeling bad may be futile: that it may only make things worse. I argue that we ought to feel bad not as a way to secure good outcomes, but because feeling bad is part of what it is to be respectful and to value our ethical standing. Employing Aristotle's method of appearances, I provide an account which can explain our confident judgements and resolve cases we find puzzling. In Part One I consider our initial intuitions and puzzles, and explain my method and assumptions. In Part Two I analyse the emotions of guilt, shame, regret and remorse, arguing that each of these emotions are appropriate in different circumstances. In Part Three, I use this analysis to explain the clear cases and resolve the problem cases. Declaration I confirm that this is my own work and the use of all material from other sources has been properly and fully acknowledged. Page 1 of 140 I am grateful to everyone who has helped me improve this thesis, but especially to my supervisors, David Owens, David Oderberg, and Bart Streumer; my examiners, John Gardner and Max De-Gaynesford; my good friends Owen Scarr and Emily Baxter; and to my colleagues on the University of Reading PhD program. This thesis is dedicated to Julie and Alan, my parents, who could never have been more supportive. Page 2 of 140 Contents Part One: Introduction Chapter 1: The question, and how to answer it 1.1 The Question 1.1.1 The easy answer 7 1.1.2 Problem cases 8 1.2 How I will answer the question 8 Chapter 2: Assumptions 2.1 Two types of assumptions 10 2.2 Necessary assumptions 2.2.1 Cognitivism about emotions 10 2.2.2 Aristotle's method of appearances, or reflective equilibrium 13 2.2.3 Only as much precision as is warranted by the subject matter 14 2.2.4 Summary 15 2.3 Informative assumptions 2.3.1 Particular considered judgements 16 2.3.2 Objectivity 16 2.3.3 Morality, ethics and prudence 16 2.3.4 Emotions are ethically important 17 2.3.5 Mental health 18 Chapter 3: Emotions 3.1 Terminology for the appraisal of emotions 19 3.2 Different types of felt affect 3.2.1 Good and bad feelings 20 3.2.2 Strong and weak feelings 24 3.3 Occurrent and dispositional emotions 25 3.4 Arguments that I will be avoiding 26 3.5 Arguments from valuing 27 Chapter 4: When does the past matter? 4.1 Mattering 4.1.1 Mattering and reasons 28 4.2 Alternatives to the Eudaimonia Principle 4.2.1 The past doesn't matter 29 4.2.2 The past is like the present 29 Page 3 of 140 4.2.3 Gardner's Continuity Thesis 30 4.2.4 Gradually fading importance 32 4.3 The Eudaimonia Principle 4.3.1 Eudaimonia 33 4.3.2 Affecting Eudaimonia 34 4.4 Defending the Eudaimonia Principle 4.4.1 A direct effect on eudaimonia is sufficient for the past to matter 36 4.4.2 Affecting what we need for eudaimonia and whether we have it is sufficient for the past to matter 37 4.4.3 Affecting what is virtuous in the present is sufficient for the past to matter 38 4.4.4 Some effect on eudaimonia is necessary for the past to matter 39 4.5 Objections and replies 4.5.1 Is it true that affecting what is virtuous is sufficient to matter to how we ought to feel? 41 4.5.2 Triviality 43 Part Two: Why feel bad? Chapter 5: Guilt 5.1 What is guilt 5.1.1 The Straightforward Account 45 5.1.2 Greenspan's Identificatory Account 47 5.1.3 Velleman's Normative Vulnerability Account 50 5.1.4 Revising the Straightforward Account 52 5.1.5 Defending the Revised Straightforward Account 55 5.2 Why feel guilty? 5.2.1 Harman's analysis of guilt 58 5.2.2 Harman's arguments against guilt 58 5.3 When is it appropriate to feel guilty? 5.3.1 The appropriateness of different types of guilt 66 5.3.2 Seriousness and appropriateness 68 5.3.3 Unfitting guilt can be appropriate 69 5.3.4 Summary 72 Chapter 6: Shame 6.1 What is shame 6.1.1 Taylor and Williams: shame and self-evaluation 73 6.1.2 Velleman: shame and self-presentation 76 6.1.3 My account of shame 78 Page 4 of 140 6.2 Why feel shame? 6.2.1 Shame and valuing 82 6.2.2 Shame and self-respect 83 6.2.3 Ambition and acceptance 84 6.2.4 Guilt 87 6.2.5 Regret 89 6.3 When is it appropriate to feel shame? 6.3.1 Fittingness and appropriateness 91 6.3.2 Seriousness and appropriateness 92 6.3.3 Control and appropriateness 92 6.3.4 Summary 95 Chapter 7: Regret 7.1 What is regret 7.1.1 Regret as a broad emotion 96 7.1.2 Agent-regret 97 7.2 Why feel regret? 7.2.1 A fortiori arguments for regret 99 7.2.2 Bittner's argument against regret 100 7.2.3 Gardner: The Continuity Thesis as an argument for regret 101 7.2.4 The Eudaimonia Principle and regret 102 7.2.5 Summary 104 7.3 When is it appropriate to feel regret? 7.3.1 An effect on our eudaimonia is necessary for appropriate regret 105 7.3.2 An effect on our eudaimonia is not sufficient for appropriate regret 107 7.3.3 Summary 108 Chapter 8: Remorse 8.1 What is remorse 8.1.1 My stipulative approach to remorse 110 8.1.2 My analysis of remorse 110 8.1.3 Remorse and guilt 113 8.1.4 Remorse and regret 114 8.1.5 Remorse and shame 114 8.2 Why feel remorse? 8.2.1 Remorse shows respect and concern for victims 115 8.2.2 Unemotional reactions are disrespectful to victims 116 8.2.3 Alternatives to remorse can be disrespectful to victims 117 Page 5 of 140 8.3 When is it appropriate to feel remorse? 8.3.1 Remorse and suffering 119 8.3.2 Summary 122 Part Three: Problem cases Chapter 9: The easy answer revisited 9.1 Overview of Part Two 9.1.1 Four emotional responses to wrongdoing 123 9.1.2 Why feel bad? 124 9.2 Easy cases explained 125 Chapter 10: Problem cases 10.1 The out-of-character killing 129 10.1.1 Guilt, shame, regret and remorse in Smith's case 130 10.1.2 Advantages of my account of Smith's case 131 10.2.3 Objections to my account of Smith's case 132 10.2 Cases involving luck 10.2.1 My account applied to moral luck cases 135 10.2.2 Resolving the puzzles of moral luck cases 137 10.3 Conclusion 138 Bibliography 139 Page 6 of 140 Part One: Introduction Chapter 1: The question, and how to answer it 1.1 The Question The question of this thesis is 'What is the virtuous emotional response to wrongdoing?' I have in mind one's own wrongdoing, not the wrongdoing of others. I am therefore interested in emotions like guilt or regret, rather than emotions like resentment. Aside from that I understand wrongdoing broadly: I am interested in wrongs both serious and slight, self-regarding and other-regarding, vicious and accidental. I shall often consider specific examples of wrongdoing, as the virtuous response is often affected by the details of the particular case; still, I will also draw general conclusions. 1.1.1 The Easy Answer So how should you feel after you've done something wrong? That's easy: you should feel bad. Everybody knows this. There are two problems with this easy answer. First, it is light on detail. There are lots of ways to feel bad, so which are appropriate? How bad should we feel? Should we feel bad forever, and, if not, when should we stop? Second, it is not so obviously true as we might at first suppose. Considering the first problem, we may note that the question was very light on detail too. If we add details to the question, it isn't so hard to add in some plausible details to the easy answer. Some principle of proportionality seems to apply: the worse what you did was, the worse you should feel afterwards, and the longer you should feel bad for. What exactly you did also suggests which emotions you should feel. For instance, regret appears more appropriate after an accident or if you only hurt yourself, whereas if you hurt somebody else, especially deliberately, guilt or shame is more appropriate. It also seems that our emotional response ought to be linked to action, otherwise we appear self-indulgent or insincere. Our guilt should motivate us to apologise and try to make amends, for example. This suggests requirements we should meet before we stop feeling bad: we ought to have apologised, received forgiveness, made amends, reformed and so on. Page 7 of 140 The more detail we add to the easy answer, the more the second problem looms: it may not be true that everybody knows it.
Recommended publications
  • 1 the Problem of Life's Definition the Philosophical Literature Is Positively
    Chapter 1. The Problem of Life's Definition The 'mystery' of consciousness today is in roughly the same shape that the mystery of life was before the development of molecular biology or the mystery of electromagnetism was before Clerk-Maxwell's equations. It seems mysterious because we do not know how the system of neuro-physiology/ consciousness works, and an adequate knowledge of how it works would remove the mystery. (Searle 1992, 101-2) The philosophical literature is positively rife1 with claims similar to those made in the epigraph, claims to the effect that the nature of life no longer presents interesting philosophical questions. The field of Artificial Life — a field which bears essentially the relationship to biology that Artificial Intelligence research bears to psychology2 — is currently bringing the nature of life and 1 In addition to Searle's comment, see Searle (1997, 201), Cornman (1992, 5), Crane (1995, 4-5), McGinn (1991, 6, 8, & 45), & Chalmers (1996, 25). The view is commonplace in science as well. Boyce Resenberg says, "life is just so much chemistry and physics", and he quotes biologist Harold Erikson as saying, "The secret of life is not a secret anymore. We have known for twenty or thirty years now that life is not more mysterious than the chemical reactions on which it is based." Cell biologist Tom Pollard is quoted as saying (what may be something quite different) that "What molecular biologists have believed for two generations is now generally regarded as proved beyond any doubt. Life is entirely the result of physics and chemistry inside cells and among cells" (Rensberger 1996, 25.
    [Show full text]
  • Continuity Thesis in World System History - B
    WORLD SYSTEM HISTORY – One World System or Many: Continuity Thesis in World System History - B. K. Gills and R. A. Denemark ONE WORLD SYSTEM OR MANY: THE CONTINUITY THESIS IN WORLD SYSTEM HISTORY B. K. Gills School of Geography, Politics and Sociology, Newcastle University, Newcastle upon Tyne, UK R. A. Denemark Department of Political Science and International Relations, University of Delaware, USA Keywords: continuity, historical materialism, center-periphery-hinterland complex, hegemony, super-hegemony, oikos, humanocentrism. Contents 1. Continuity in World History 2. Historical Materialism 3. Economic Cycles 4. Core-Periphery Hierarchies 5. Hegemony and Super-Hegemony 6. Continuity Thesis and Historical Dialectics 6.1. Capital versus Oikos 6.2. Unfree Labor versus Free Commodified Labor 6.3. Organization versus Entropy 7. Humanocentrism Glossary Bibliography Biographical Sketches Summary The continuity thesis in world system history expresses the idea of long-term historical continuity in contrast to the idea of perpetual change and progression through a series of epoch-alteringUNESCO transformations. This perspective – hasEOLSS important conceptual roots in non- western philosophical traditions. Drawing much inspiration from historical materialism, the continuity thesis nonetheless problematizes any hypothesized transition to capitalism. There are vital processes that remain unchanged across the period of the alleged transition,SAMPLE and the model itself is (poor CHAPTERSly) drawn from the experience of a single world region. Important characteristics of the thesis include concern for economic cycles, the development of core-periphery-hinterland complexes, hegemony and super- hegemony, a set of three dialectical tensions including capital versus oikos, unfree labor versus free commodified labor, and organization versus entropy. In contradistinction to the profoundly Eurocentric nature of much contemporary social thought, the continuity thesis is humanocentric.
    [Show full text]
  • Galileo, Ignoramus: Mathematics Versus Philosophy in the Scientific Revolution
    Galileo, Ignoramus: Mathematics versus Philosophy in the Scientific Revolution Viktor Blåsjö Abstract I offer a revisionist interpretation of Galileo’s role in the history of science. My overarching thesis is that Galileo lacked technical ability in mathematics, and that this can be seen as directly explaining numerous aspects of his life’s work. I suggest that it is precisely because he was bad at mathematics that Galileo was keen on experiment and empiricism, and eagerly adopted the telescope. His reliance on these hands-on modes of research was not a pioneering contribution to scientific method, but a last resort of a mind ill equipped to make a contribution on mathematical grounds. Likewise, it is precisely because he was bad at mathematics that Galileo expounded at length about basic principles of scientific method. “Those who can’t do, teach.” The vision of science articulated by Galileo was less original than is commonly assumed. It had long been taken for granted by mathematicians, who, however, did not stop to pontificate about such things in philosophical prose because they were too busy doing advanced scientific work. Contents 4 Astronomy 38 4.1 Adoption of Copernicanism . 38 1 Introduction 2 4.2 Pre-telescopic heliocentrism . 40 4.3 Tycho Brahe’s system . 42 2 Mathematics 2 4.4 Against Tycho . 45 2.1 Cycloid . .2 4.5 The telescope . 46 2.2 Mathematicians versus philosophers . .4 4.6 Optics . 48 2.3 Professor . .7 4.7 Mountains on the moon . 49 2.4 Sector . .8 4.8 Double-star parallax . 50 2.5 Book of nature .
    [Show full text]
  • Wide Content and Psychological Continuity Views of Personal Identity
    Wide Content and Psychological Continuity Views of Personal Identity Alexander Kilcran UCL MPhil Stud Philosophy 1 I, Alexander Kilcran confirm that the work presented in this thesis is my own. Where information has been derived from other sources, I confirm that this has been indicated in the thesis. Abstract Externalism about mental content is the thesis that the content of at least some of a subject’s men- tal states is individuated by things in the subject’s environment. Psychological continuity accounts of personal identity claim that what it takes for a person to persist over time is to be share a suffi- cient degree of psychological similarity with themselves. I will argue that the truth of externalism about content implies that psychological continuity accounts of personal identity violate a plausible principle about identity, namely the Only x and y principle, which states that an object’s identity and persistence conditions should be not be fixed by anything other than that very object. I will consider whether this result can be avoided by either denying that the Only x and y principle is true or applies in the case of personal identity or by adopting a version of psychological continuity grounded only in narrow content. I argue that taking either of these options means giving up some intuitively plausible views and that this counts against psychological continuity views of personal identity. 2 Contents 1 Introduction 4 2 Externalism and psychological continuity 5 2.1 Externalism . 5 2.2 Psychological Continuity . 9 3 Wide Content and the Only x and y Principle 14 4 Some Possible Neo-Lockean Responses 26 4.1 Narrow Psychological Continuity .
    [Show full text]
  • Problems with Continuity: Defining the Middle Ages for Medievalism Studies
    - 1 - Problems with Continuity: Defining the Middle Ages for Medievalism Studies Karl Fugelso, Towson As can be seen in almost any field of academia, continuity and its antitheses are deceptively difficult to define. Mathematicians have long struggled to pin down a real-number continuum that can do the work required by limit theory. 1 Literary critics continue to grapple with the relationship between narrative flow and the changes that lend it momentum.2 And scholars from many areas of the humanities and social sciences have attempted to clarify the blurred distincti- ons between historical continuity and discontinuity.3 This elusiveness is particularly problematic for medievalism studies, whose subjects are often described as post-medieval responses to the Middle Ages.4 Periods are rarely recognized by those living through them and are almost ne- ver, if ever, characterized twice in precisely the same way.5 This seems to be especially true of the Middle Ages, as is indicated by the plethora of later, mostly derogatory labels for them, including “Middle Ages,” “Dark Ages,” and “A World Lit Only by Fire.”6 Indeed, defining the Middle Ages gave rise to and 1 For more on this discussion, begin with Benjamin Lee Buckley, The Continuity Debate: De- dekind, Cantor, du Bois-Reymond, and Peirce on Continuity and Infinitesimals (Boston: Do- cent Press, 2008). 2 See, for instance, Paul Ricoeur, Time and Narrative, trans. by Kathleen Blamey and David Pellauer, 3 vols. (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1984-88; orig. Temps et Récit, 1981- 85). 3 See, for example, the Harvard economist Alexander Gerschenkron, “On the Concept of Continuity in History,” Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society 106/3 (29 June 1962): 195-209.
    [Show full text]
  • International Journal of Science and Technology (STECH) Bahir Dar- Ethiopia Vol
    IAARR 57 International Journal of Science and Technology Vol. 7 (1) February, 2018 International Journal of Science and Technology (STECH) Bahir Dar- Ethiopia Vol. 7 (1), S/No15, February, 2018: 57-71 ISSN: 2225-8590 (Print) ISSN 2227-5452 (Online) DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.4314/stech.v7i1.5 SCIENTIFIC REVOLUTION, INCOMMENSURABILITY AND TRUTH IN THEORIES: OBJECTION TO KUHN’S PERSPECTIVE IHEJIRIKA, CARDINAL, PhD DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF PORT HARCOURT, NIGERIA PHONE: +2348028279646 E-mail: [email protected] ……………………………………………………………………….. EMEDOLU, CHRISTIAN C., PhD DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF PORT HARCOURT, NIGERIA PHONE: +2348035517505 E-mail: [email protected] …………………………………………………………………………………………… ABSTRACT This is to revaluate the truth-content of scientific theory in the event of scientific revolution. In this paper, we argued that the radical views on incommensurability offered, especially, by Thomas S. Kuhn (shared by Paul Feyerabend, and others) do not actually undermine either the realist or cumulative stature of science. The core of our discussion is, ultimately, to provide a clearer and broader picture of the general characteristics of scientific revolution or theory change. In doing this, the paper pinpoints the audacity behind this change and the nature of truth undergirding any emergent or overthrown scientific theory. The paper has some rebounding echoes of the realist and cumulative features of science while addressing the issue of the real character of theory change. Following some unique interpretations of scientific revolution, truth in science could still be redeemed in the face of theory change and Kuhnian Incommensurability Thesis. To this effect, the hermeneutical approach is considered most suitable in this paper.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle's Journey to Europe: a Synthetic History of the Role Played
    Aristotle’s Journey to Europe: A Synthetic History of the Role Played by the Islamic Empire in the Transmission of Western Educational Philosophy Sources from the Fall of Rome through the Medieval Period By Randall R. Cloud B.A., Point Loma Nazarene University, 1977 M.A., Point Loma University, 1979 M. Div., Nazarene Theological Seminary, 1982 Submitted to the: School of Education Department of Educational Leadership and Policy Studies Program: Educational Policy and Leadership Concentration: Foundations of Education and the Faculty of the Graduate School of the University of Kansas in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Dissertation Committee: _______________________________________ Suzanne Rice, Chairperson _______________________________________ Ray Hiner _______________________________________ Jim Hillesheim _______________________________________ Marc Mahlios _______________________________________ Sally Roberts Dissertation Defended: November 6, 2007 The Dissertation Committee for Randall R. Cloud certifies that this is the approved version of the following dissertation: Aristotle’s Journey to Europe: A Synthetic History of the Role Played by the Islamic Empire in the Transmission of Western Educational Philosophy Sources from the Fall of Rome through the Medieval Period Dissertation Committee: _______________________________________ Suzanne Rice, Chairperson _______________________________________ Ray Hiner _______________________________________ Jim Hillesheim _______________________________________
    [Show full text]
  • The Scientific Revolution and the Origins of Modern
    THE SCIENTIFIC REVOLUTION AND THE ORIGINS OF MODERN SCIENCE Studies in European History Series Editors: Richard Overy John Breuilly Peter Wilson Jeremy Black A Military Revolution? Military Change and European Society, 1550–1800 T.C.W. Blanning The French Revolution: Class War or Culture Clash? (2nd edn) John Breuilly The Formation of the First German Nation-State, 1800–1871 Peter Burke The Renaissance (2nd edn) Michael Dockrill and Michael F. Hopkins The Cold War, 1945–1963 William Doyle The Ancien Régime (2nd edn) William Doyle Jansenism Geoffrey Ellis The Napoleonic Empire (2nd edn) Donald A. Filtzer The Krushchev Era Mary Fulbrook Interpretations of the Two Germanies, 1945–1990 (2nd edn) R. G. Geary European Labour Politics from 1900 to the Depression Graeme Gill Stalinism (2nd edn) Hugh Gough The Terror in the French Revolution John Henry The Scientific Revolution and the Origins of Modern Science (3rd edn) Stefan-Ludwig Hoffman Civil Society, 1750–1914 Henry Kamen Golden Age Spain (2nd edn) Richard Mackenney The City-State, 1500–1700 Andrew Porter European Imperialism, 1860–1914 Roy Porter The Enlightenment (2nd edn) Roger Price The Revolutions of 1848 James Retallack Germany in the Age of Kaiser Wilhelm II Geoffrey Scarre and John Callan Witchcraft and Magic in16th- and 17th-Century Europe (2nd edn) R.W. Scribner and C. Scott Dixon The German Reformation (2nd edn) Robert Service The Russian Revolution, 1900–1927 (3rd edn) Jeremy Smith The Fall of Soviet Communism, 1985–1991 David Stevenson The Outbreak of the First World War Peter H. Wilson The Holy Roman Empire, 1495–1806 Oliver Zimmer Nationalism in Europe, 1890–1940 Studies in European History Series Standing Order ISBN 0–333–79365–X (outside North America only) You can receive future titles in this series by placing a standing order.
    [Show full text]
  • Galileo's Mathematization of Nature at the Crossroad Between the Empiricist and the Kantian Tradition
    Edinburgh Research Explorer Galileo's Mathematization of Nature at the Crossroad between the Empiricist and the Kantian Tradition Citation for published version: Massimi, M 2010, 'Galileo's Mathematization of Nature at the Crossroad between the Empiricist and the Kantian Tradition', Perspectives on Science, vol. 18, no. 2, pp. 152-188. https://doi.org/10.1162/posc.2010.18.2.152 Digital Object Identifier (DOI): 10.1162/posc.2010.18.2.152 Link: Link to publication record in Edinburgh Research Explorer Document Version: Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Published In: Perspectives on Science Publisher Rights Statement: © MIT. Massimi, M. (2010). Galileo's Mathematization of Nature at the Crossroad between the Empiricist and the Kantian Tradition. Perspectives on Science, 18(2), 152-188doi: 10.1162/posc.2010.18.2.152 General rights Copyright for the publications made accessible via the Edinburgh Research Explorer is retained by the author(s) and / or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing these publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Take down policy The University of Edinburgh has made every reasonable effort to ensure that Edinburgh Research Explorer content complies with UK legislation. If you believe that the public display of this file breaches copyright please contact [email protected] providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 26. Sep. 2021 Galileo’s Mathematization of Nature at the Crossroad between the Empiricist and the Kantian Tradition Michela Massimi University College London The aim of this paper is to take Galileo’s mathematization of nature as a springboard for contrasting the time-honoured empiricist conception of phe- nomena, exempliªed by Pierre Duhem’s analysis in To Save the Phenomena (1908), with Immanuel Kant’s.
    [Show full text]
  • Counterfactuals and Unphysical Ceteris Paribus
    Counterfactuals and unphysical ceteris paribus UDK: 524.6:14 FILOZOFIJA I DRUŠTVO XXIV (4), 2013. DOI: 10.2298/FID1304143C Original scientific paper Milan M. Ćirković Astronomical Observatory of Belgrade Future of Humanity Institute Oxford University Counterfactuals and unphysical ceteris paribus: an explanatory fallacy Abstract I reconsider a type of counterfactual argument often used in hi- storical sciences on a recent widely discussed example of the so-called “rare Earth” hypothesis in planetary sciences and astrobiology. The argument is based on the alleged “rarity” of some crucial ingredient for the planetary habitability, which is, in Earth’s case, provided by contingent evolutionary development. For instance, the claim that a contingent fact of history which has created planet Jupiter enables shielding of Earth from most dangerous impact catastrophes, thus increasing Earth’s habitability, leads often to the 143 conclusion that such state-of-affairs must be rare in the Galaxy. I argue that this reasoning is deeply flawed, for several closely related reasons. In addi- tion, the relevance of the philosophical problem of transworld identity for this kind of historical reasoning in science is put forward. This highlights many explanatory problems one faces when using historical counterfactuals in study of complex, nonlinear dynamical systems – and bolsters the relevan- ce of philosophy for evaluation of scientific explanatory claims. Keywords: counterfactuals, astrobiology, philosophy of science, philosophy of history, transworld identity Introduction: the rare earth hypothesis Recent years showed a tremendous increase of interest in explanato- ry strategies based on counterfactual reasoning in many areas of sci- ence and philosophy. Most notably, the emergence of “virtual history” (Ferguson 1999) in historical sciences, and somewhat contemporary re- appraisal of the role of contingency in natural sciences, notably plan- etary sciences, origin of life (abiogenesis) studies and evolutionary bi- ology.
    [Show full text]
  • PIERRE DUHEM THESIS.’ a REAPPRAISAL of DUHEM’S DISCOVERY of the PHYSICS of the MIDDLE AGES Horia-Roman PATAPIEVICI
    THE ‘PIERRE DUHEM THESIS.’ A REAPPRAISAL OF DUHEM’S DISCOVERY OF THE PHYSICS OF THE MIDDLE AGES Horia-Roman PATAPIEVICI ABSTRACT: Pierre Duhem is the discoverer of the physics of the Middle Ages. The discovery that there existed a physics of the Middle Ages was a surprise primarily for Duhem himself. This discovery completely changed the way he saw the evolution of physics, bringing him to formulate a complex argument for the growth and continuity of scientific knowledge, which I call the ‘Pierre Duhem Thesis’ (not to be confused either with what Roger Ariew called the ‘true Duhem thesis’ as opposed to the Quine-Duhem thesis, which he persuasively argued is not Duhem’s, or with the famous ‘Quine-Duhem Thesis’ itself). The ‘Pierre Duhem Thesis’ consists of five sub-theses (some transcendental in nature, some other causal, factual, or descriptive), which are not independent, as they do not work separately (but only as a system) and do not relate to reality separately (but only simultaneously). The famous and disputed ‘continuity thesis’ is part, as a sub-thesis, from this larger argument. I argue that the ‘Pierre Duhem Thesis’ wraps up all of Duhem’s discoveries in the history of science and as a whole represents his main contribution to the historiography of science. The ‘Pierre Duhem Thesis’ is the central argument of Pierre Duhem's work as historian of science. KEYWORDS: Pierre Duhem, physics of the Middle Ages, scientific knowledge, history of science 1. The discoverer of the physics of the Middle Ages was Pierre Duhem (1861-1916) – physicist, philosopher, and historian of science.1 Since this wondrous episode is rarely mentioned, and the importance of the physics of the Middle Ages to the 1 Stanley L.
    [Show full text]
  • Pierre Duhem's Good Sense As a Guide to Theory Choice
    Pierre Duhem’s Good Sense as a guide to Theory Choice Milena Ivanova Department of Philosophy University of Bristol 9 Woodland Road Bristol BS8 1TB United Kingdom Abstract This paper examines Duhem’s concept of good sense as an attempt to support a non rule-governed account of rationality in theory choice. Faced with the underdetermination of theory by evidence thesis and the continuity thesis, Duhem tried to account for the ability of scientists to choose theories that continuously grow to a natural classification. I will examine the concept of good sense and the problems that stem from it. I will also present a recent attempt by David Stump to link good sense to virtue epistemology. I will argue that even though this approach can be useful for the better comprehension of the concept of good sense, there are some substantial differences between virtue epistemologists and Duhem. In the light of this reconstruction of good sense, I will propose a possible way to interpret the concept of good sense, which overcomes the noted problems and fits better with Duhem’s views on scientific method and motivation in developing the concept of good sense. 1 Keywords: good sense, natural classification, novel predictions, theoretical virtues, unification, virtue epistemology 1. Introduction Having advanced the continuity thesis and the underdetermination of theory by evidence thesis, Pierre Duhem was faced with the problem of how scientists could choose between theories with equal empirical consequences. His solution was based on the concept of good sense by which he tried to advance a theory of rationality that combines both descriptive and normative elements.
    [Show full text]