Bertrand Russell's Logic

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Bertrand Russell's Logic BERTRAND RUSSELL’S LOGIC Andrew D. Irvine Bertrand Russell is generally recognized as one of the most important English- speaking philosophers, logicians and essayists of the twentieth century. Often cited along with G.E. Moore as one of the founders of modern analytic philosophy and along with Kurt G¨odel as one of the most influential logicians of his time, Russell is also widely recognized for his sustained public contributions to many of the most controversial social, political and educational issues of his day. Even so, more than anything else, it is Russell’s work in logic and the foundations of mathematics that serves as his core contribution to intellectual history and that makes Russell the seminal thinker he is. His most significant achievements include 1. his refining and popularizing of Giuseppe Peano’s and Gottlob Frege’s first attempts at developing a modern mathematical logic, 2. his discovery of the paradox that bears his name, 3. his introduction of the theory of types (his way of avoiding the paradox), 4. his defense of logicism, the view that mathematics is in some important sense reducible to logic, and his many detailed derivations supporting this view, 5. his ground-breaking advances in technical philosophy, including both his theory of definite descriptions and his theory of logical constructions, 6. his theory of logical relations, including his impressively general theory of relation arithmetic, 7. his formalization of the reals, 8. his theory of logical atomism, and 9. his championing of the many connections between modern logic, mathemat- ics, science, and knowledge in general. Russell’s first important book about logic, The Principles of Mathematics,ap- peared in 1903. This was followed by the landmark articles “On Denoting” (in 1905) and “Mathematical Logic as based on the Theory of Types” (in 1908). A decade of technical work then culminated with the publication (in 1910, 1912 and Handbook of the History of Logic. Volume 5. Logic from Russell to Church Dov M. Gabbay and John Woods (Editors) c 2009 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved. 2 Andrew D. Irvine 1913) of the three-volume Principia Mathematica, co-authored with Russell’s for- mer teacher, Alfred North Whitehead.1 This was followed by several books and articles intended to help underscore the philosophical importance of the new math- ematical logic that Russell, Whitehead, Peano and Frege had developed, including “The Philosophy of Logical Atomism” (in 1918–19), Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy (in 1919), “Logical Atomism” (in 1924), and My Philosophical Devel- opment (in 1959). Russell received the Order of Merit in 1949 and the Nobel Prize in 1950. Born in 1872, he wrote over fifty books, over 4,000 articles, book chapters, reviews and other more minor publications, and over 61,000 letters. He died in 1970, having lived a very full and public life. Developing a comprehensive, coherent interpretation of Russell’s logic and phi- losophy of mathematics is both important and challenging. It is important be- cause of the tremendous influence his work has had on philosophy, mathematics, economics, decision theory, computability theory, computer science and other dis- ciplines over the past one hundred years. It is challenging for at least three rea- sons. First, modern logic is intrinsically abstract and complex. Even mastering the full notation of Principia Mathematica may be judged an accomplishment in itself. (This is especially true given that, over the past century, many parts of the notation have been modified or replaced by more modern kinds of symbolism. Learning it in complete detail is thus something that not even all Russell scholars have achieved.) Second, as with the work of any intellectual pioneer, it is often suggested, not only that Russell’s views changed and developed over time, but that at important times they were also relatively inchoate. Third, as with the work of many other important historical figures, it sometimes can be difficult to distinguish between Russell’s actual views and those attributed to him by various well-known commentators and interpreters. Today there exist two main approaches to understanding the most difficult and demanding aspects of Russell’s philosophy. The first is to claim that Russell’s work is largely a series of almost unconnected views, views that not only changed over time but that also were largely indebted to the work of others. This is the view that characterizes Russell primarily as a popularizer and as a less-than-systematic thinker. The second is to see in Russell’s writings a much more systematic and original body of work. To give just one example, there are many often-overlooked connections between Russell’s logic, his theory of language (especially his theory of definite descriptions), and his epistemology (for example, his multiple-relation theory of judgment). According to this second view we fail to see these many connections at our peril. Significantly, it is also this second view — that Russell is offering us a fully integrated body of intellectual work — that is much more in line with Russell’s own statements about his philosophical aims and achievements, statements that many writers over the years have conveniently chosen to ignore. 1Although anticipated in several respects in the writings of Gottlob Frege, Principia Math- ematica remains just as intellectually impressive an achievement as Frege’s Grundgesetze der Arithmetik. The case might also be made that, without it, Frege’s work might never have re- ceived the prominence it deserves. Bertrand Russell’s Logic 3 Whether explicitly or not, it is also this integrated view of logical, philosophical and scientific knowledge that has influenced an entire century of western philosophy. Understanding not only Russell’s substantive logical and philosophical views, but also his methodological views, is therefore crucial to understanding the domi- nant paradigm of intellectual work carried out in philosophy over the past century. Today it is hard to imagine a philosophy undergraduate anywhere in the western world whose education has not been influenced, at least in part, by Russell’s math- ematical logic and philosophical method. INITIAL INFLUENCES At the age of eleven, I began Euclid, with my brother as my tutor. This was one of the great events of my life, as dazzling as first love. I had not imagined there was anything so delicious in the world. After I had learned the fifth proposition, my brother told me that it was generally considered difficult, but I had found no difficulty whatever. This was the first time it had dawned upon me that I might have some intelligence. From that moment until I met Whitehead and I finished Principia Mathematica, when I was thirty-eight, mathematics was my chief interest and my chief source of happiness. Like all happiness, however, it was not unalloyed. I had been told that Euclid proved things, and was much disappointed that he started with axioms. At first I refused to accept them unless my brother could offer me some reason for doing so, but he said: “If you don’t accept them we cannot go on,” and as I wished to go on, I reluctantly admitted them pro tem. The doubt as to the premises of mathematics which I felt at that moment remained with me, and determined the course of my subsequent work. [Russell, 1967, pp. 37–8] So begins the story in Russell’s Autobiography of how Russell came to be inter- ested in the foundations of mathematics. Educated at home by a series of Swiss and German governesses and tutors before entering Cambridge in 1890, Russell embraced academic life enthusiastically. He obtained a first in Mathematics in 1893. Even so, with the exception of the lectures given by Whitehead, Russell found the teaching of mathematics at Cambridge “definitely bad.”2 As a result, he became even more determined to try to learn exactly what it is that gives mathematics its high degree of certainty. Having finished his undergraduate program in mathematics, Russell “plunged with whole-hearted delight into the fantastic world of philosophy”3 and the follow- ing year he completed the Moral Sciences Tripos. In philosophy he was initially influenced by the absolute idealism of J. M. E. McTaggart, F. H. Bradley and the 2[Russell, 1959, p. 38]. 3[Russell, 1959, p. 38]. 4 Andrew D. Irvine other Ox-bridge neo-Hegelians of the time.4 As Russell understood it, absolute idealism depended crucially on the doctrine of internal relations, the doctrine that any relational fact (for example, that x is related to y) is really a fact about the natures of the related terms. According to this view, if x is greater than y, then being greater than y is a part of the nature of x. Object y is thus, in some sig- nificant sense, a part of x and x, similarly, is a part of y. Given the complexity of relations in the world, it turns out that all objects must be related to all other objects. Hence it follows that there exists only a single, all encompassing unity. Further, since if one is aware of x, x must also (on this view) be a part of one’s mind, it follows that everything conceivable must be a part of consciousness. Initially, Russell used this idealist framework in his approach to mathematics, for example in his Essay on the Foundations of Geometry (1897). However, he became disenchanted with idealism once he realized how incompatible the view was with his developing understanding of both mathematics and science. On Russell’s emerging theory, geometrical points, for example, could be individuated only by their relations. But according to absolute idealism, relations in turn depended on the intrinsic natures of their individual relata.
Recommended publications
  • Analytic Philosophy and the Fall and Rise of the Kant–Hegel Tradition
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-87272-0 - Analytic Philosophy and the Return of Hegelian Thought Paul Redding Excerpt More information INTRODUCTION: ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE FALL AND RISE OF THE KANT–HEGEL TRADITION Should it come as a surprise when a technical work in the philosophy of language by a prominent analytic philosopher is described as ‘an attempt to usher analytic philosophy from its Kantian to its Hegelian stage’, as has 1 Robert Brandom’s Making It Explicit? It can if one has in mind a certain picture of the relation of analytic philosophy to ‘German idealism’. This particular picture has been called analytic philosophy’s ‘creation myth’, and it was effectively established by Bertrand Russell in his various accounts of 2 the birth of the ‘new philosophy’ around the turn of the twentieth century. It was towards the end of 1898 that Moore and I rebelled against both Kant and Hegel. Moore led the way, but I followed closely in his foot- steps. I think that the first published account of the new philosophy was 1 As does Richard Rorty in his ‘Introduction’ to Wilfrid Sellars, Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind, with introduction by Richard Rorty and study guide by Robert Brandom (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1997), pp. 8–9. 2 The phrase is from Steve Gerrard, ‘Desire and Desirability: Bradley, Russell, and Moore Versus Mill’ in W. W. Tait (ed.), Early Analytic Philosophy: Frege, Russell, Wittgenstein (Chicago: Open Court, 1997): ‘The core of the myth (which has its origins in Russell’s memories) is that with philosophical argument aided by the new logic, Russell and Moore slew the dragon of British Idealism ...An additional aspect is that the war was mainly fought over two related doctrines of British Idealism ...The first doctrine is an extreme form of holism: abstraction is always falsification.
    [Show full text]
  • “Silence Is Your Praise” Maimonides' Approach To
    Rabbi Rafael Salber “Silence is your praise” Maimonides’ Approach to Knowing God: An Introduction to Negative Theology Rabbi Rafael Salber The prophet Isaiah tells us, For my thoughts are not your thoughts, neither are my ways your ways, saith the Lord. For as the heavens are higher than the earth, so are my ways higher than your ways. 73 The content of this verse suggests the inability of mankind to comprehend the knowledge and thoughts of God, as well as the 73 Isaiah 55: 8- 9. The context of the verse is that Isaiah is conveying the message to the people of Israel that the ability to return to God (Teshuvah) is available to them, since the “traits” of God are conducive to this. See Moreh Nevuchim ( The Guide to the Perplexed ) 3:20 and the Sefer haIkkarim Maamar 2, Ch. 3. 65 “Silence is your praise”: Maimonides’ Approach to Knowing God: An Introduction to Negative Theology divergence of “the ways” of God and the ways of man. The extent of this dissimilarity is clarified in the second statement, i.e. that it is not merely a distance in relation, but rather it is as if they are of a different category altogether, like the difference that exists between heaven and earth 74 . What then is the relationship between mankind and God? What does the prophet mean when he describes God as having thoughts and ways; how is it even possible to describe God as having thoughts and ways? These perplexing implications are further compounded when one is introduced to the Magnum Opus of Maimonides 75 , the Mishneh Torah .
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle and the Productive Class: Did Aristotle Argue
    ARISTOTLE AND THE PRODUCTIVE CLASS: DID ARISTOTLE ARGUE IN FAVOR OF EDUCATION FOR ALL? by DEANNA M. HACKWORTH, B.A. A THESIS IN PHILOSOPHY Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of Texas Tech University in Pardal Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of MASTER OF ARTS Approved August, 2003 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I am grateful to many people who offered criticism, support, and comments during the writing of this paper, without whom, it is doubtful this thesis would have ever been completed. First and foremost, I must thank the chair of my committee, Howard Curzer, whose support, encouragement, and vast knowledge of Aristotle were both enlightening and infinitely helpfijl. For his continuous help in my attempt to understand the capabilities approach first developed by Sen, and his unwavering commitment to keep my interpretation of Aristotle truthful and correct, I am indebted to Walter Schaller. An earUer and much different version of this paper sparked conversations between myself and Eric Carter, which helped to shape my thinking on Nussbaum, and to whom I would like to offer sincere thanks. LaKrisha Mauldin and Stiv Fleishman edited and provided comments on several drafts, allowing me to see errors that I would not have been able to see otherwise, and proving invaluable in the final hours before the defense of this paper. Several unpublished articles written and sent to me by Dr. Fred Miller proved fertile ground to shape my thinking of objections to my project, and I am forever gratefial. Last but certainly not least, I would like to offer thanks to my family, for giving me large amounts of uninterrupted time which allowed me to work on this project, and supported me to the extent they were able as I endeavored to become a philosopher.
    [Show full text]
  • Bertrand Russell in the Great Soviet Encyclopedia
    Russell's philosophical evolution led him into a broad program of research where he applied the resources of mathematical logic to theoreti­ cal inquiry. In the neorealist and neopositivist stages of Russell's evolution this program led to the formulating of his Theory of Knowledge, and from then on he again recognized the independent significance of philosophical problems. 3 Russell created the concept of logical atomism and he founded logical analysis. Bertrand Russell in the The working out of philosophical questions in mathematics occupies a large place in his works. One of the paradoxes in set theory (Russell's Great Soviet Encyclopedia: Paradox) led him to the formation of the original version of axiomatic set theory4 (see also Theory of Types) and to the consequent attempt at l a translation from Russian reducing mathematics to logic. Russell and Whitehead coauthored the 3­ vol ume work "Principia Mathematica" (1910-1913). They systematized and developed the deductive-axiomatic formation of logic (see Logicism). USSELL2 Bertrand (18.5.1872, Trelleck, Wales--2.2.1970, Penrhyndeu­ Russell developed the original Theory of Descriptions. R draeth, Wales), English philosopher, logician, mathematician, sociolo­ In his sociological views Russell was close to Psychologism. Accord­ gist, public figure. Between 1910 and 1916 Russell was a professor at ing to him, at the foundations of the historical process and the behaviour Cambridge University, where he graduated in 1894. He was professor at of people lie instincts, passions. Russell said that from a combination various universities in Great Britain and the U.S. In 1908 he became a of factors determining historical change it is impossible to pick out the member of the Royal Society.
    [Show full text]
  • Ibn Rushd and the Enlightenment Project in the Islamic World
    Religions 2015, 6, 1082–1106; doi:10.3390/rel6031082 OPEN ACCESS religions ISSN 2077-1444 www.mdpi.com/journal/religions Article Qur’anic Interpretation and the Problem of Literalism: Ibn Rushd and the Enlightenment Project in the Islamic World Chryssi Sidiropoulou Department of Philosophy, Faculty of Arts and Sciences, Boğaziçi University, TB 350, Bebek 343 42, Istanbul, Turkey; E-Mail: [email protected]; Tel.: +90-212-3595400 (ext. 7210); Fax: +90-212-2872469 Academic Editor: Jonathan Hill Received: 4 May 2015 / Accepted: 26 August 2015 / Published: 11 September 2015 Abstract: This article examines the claim that Ibn Rushd of Cordoba (“Averroës,” 12th century B.C.) is a precursor of the Enlightenment and a source of inspiration for the emancipation of contemporary Islamic societies. The paper critically discusses the fascination that Ibn Rushd has exercised on several thinkers, from Ernest Renan to Salman Rushdie, and highlights the problem of literalism in Qur’anic interpretation. Based on Ibn Rushd’s Decisive Treatise (Fasl al-maqāl), the paper investigates Ibn Rushd’s proposed division of (Muslim) society into three distinct classes. The main question here is whether there is a substantial link between the people of the Muslim community, given the three distinct kinds of assent (tasdīq) introduced by Ibn Rushd. I argue that if such a link cannot be supplied, then it is hard to see in Ibn Rushd an enlightened social model for today’s Muslim societies. Furthermore, that the great majority of people are prevented from having any contact with non-literal interpretation of the Scripture and non-revealed ways of thinking.
    [Show full text]
  • Brsq 0096.Pdf
    /,,-,,,.I (hrir"M/W:|J,„'JJ(// Bulk Mail -:::-``.::`:.1:.t` U.S. Postage ci{08O#altruntr%%ditl.i PAID Permit No. 5659 CfldemmJin, ORE 23307 Alexandria, VA MR. DENNIS J. DARLAND /9999 .1965 WINDING HILLS RD. (1304) DAVENPORT IA 52807 T=..:€,,5fa=.`¥ _ atiTst:.:..¥5 3`=3 13LT„j§jLj;,:j2F,f:Lu,i,:,„„„„3.,§§.i;§„L„;j„§{j;;`„„:i THE BHRTRAND RUSSELL SOCIHTY QUARTERLY Newsletter o the Bertrand Russell Socie November 1997 No. 96 FROM THH EDITOR John Shosky ................................... 3 FROM THE PRESIDHNT John R. Lenz ................................... 4 BERTRAND RUSSELL SOCIETY CONFERENCH: 19-21 JUNE 1998 ...................... RUSSELL NEWS: Publications, etc ....................... 6 RUSSELL'S PLATO David Rodier ................................... 7 A BOOK REVIEW John Shosky .................................. 19 MEMORY COMES AND GOES: A Video Review Cliff Henke ................................... 22 THE GREATER ROCHESTER RUSSELL SET Peter Stone ................................... 24 BERTRAND RUSSELL SOCIETY Membership PI.orlles ............................ 25 BERTRAND RUSSELL SOCIETY 1998 Call for Board Nominations .................. 27 BERTRAND RUSSELL SOCIETY Membership pror]]e Form . 29 1 FROM THE EDITOR BHRTRAND RUSSELL SOCIETY John Shosky 1998 Membership Renewal Form ................... 31 American University Wc beSn this issue with a report from the society president, John Lenz. He will announce the preliminary details of the Annual Bertrand Russell Society Corferencc, which will be held June 19-21 at the Ethics Center of the University of South Florida in St. Petersburg. John's report will be followed by "Russell News", which is a column of short blurbs about Russell, works on Russell, society happenings, reports on members, general gossip, and other vital talking points for the informed and discerning society member. In my view, the standard of information one should strive for, in a Platonic sense, is Ken Blackwell, the guru of Russell trivia, realizing that Ken has a considerable head start on all of us.
    [Show full text]
  • Two Problems for Resemblance Nominalism
    Two Problems for Resemblance Nominalism Andrea C. Bottani, Università di Bergamo [email protected] I. Nominalisms Just as ‘being’ according to Aristotle, ‘nominalism’ can be said in many ways, being currently used to refer to a number of non equivalent theses, each denying the existence of entities of a certain sort. In a Quinean largely shared sense, nominalism is the thesis that abstract entities do not exist. In other senses, some of which also are broadly shared, nominalism is the thesis that universals do not exist; the thesis that neither universals nor tropes exist; the thesis that properties do not exist. These theses seem to be independent, at least to some degree: some ontologies incorporate all of them, some none, some just one and some more than one but not all. This makes the taxonomy of nominalisms very complex. Armstrong 1978 distinguishes six varieties of nominalism according to which neither universals nor tropes exist, called respectively ‘ostrich nominalism’, ‘predicate nominalism’, ‘concept nominalism’, ‘mereological nominalism’, ‘class nominalism’ and ‘resemblance nominalism’, which Armstrong criticizes but considers superior to any other version. According to resemblance nominalism, properties depend on primitive resemblance relations among particulars, while there are neither universals nor tropes. Rodriguez-Pereyra 2002 contains a systematic formulation and defence of a version of resemblance nominalism according to which properties exist, conceived of as maximal classes of exactly resembling particulars. An exact resemblance is one that two particulars can bear to each other just in case there is some ‘lowest determinate’ property - for example, being of an absolutely precise nuance of red – that both have just in virtue of precisely resembling certain particulars (so that chromatic resemblance can only be chromatic indiscernibility).
    [Show full text]
  • Basic Concepts of Set Theory, Functions and Relations 1. Basic
    Ling 310, adapted from UMass Ling 409, Partee lecture notes March 1, 2006 p. 1 Basic Concepts of Set Theory, Functions and Relations 1. Basic Concepts of Set Theory........................................................................................................................1 1.1. Sets and elements ...................................................................................................................................1 1.2. Specification of sets ...............................................................................................................................2 1.3. Identity and cardinality ..........................................................................................................................3 1.4. Subsets ...................................................................................................................................................4 1.5. Power sets .............................................................................................................................................4 1.6. Operations on sets: union, intersection...................................................................................................4 1.7 More operations on sets: difference, complement...................................................................................5 1.8. Set-theoretic equalities ...........................................................................................................................5 Chapter 2. Relations and Functions ..................................................................................................................6
    [Show full text]
  • Ludwig.Wittgenstein.-.Philosophical.Investigations.Pdf
    PHILOSOPHICAL INVESTIGATIONS By LUDWIG WITTGENSTEIN Translated by G. E. M. ANSCOMBE BASIL BLACKWELL TRANSLATOR'S NOTE Copyright © Basil Blackwell Ltd 1958 MY acknowledgments are due to the following, who either checked First published 1953 Second edition 1958 the translation or allowed me to consult them about German and Reprint of English text alone 1963 Austrian usage or read the translation through and helped me to Third edition of English and German text with index 1967 improve the English: Mr. R. Rhees, Professor G. H. von Wright, Reprint of English text with index 1968, 1972, 1974, 1976, 1978, Mr. P. Geach, Mr. G. Kreisel, Miss L. Labowsky, Mr. D. Paul, Miss I. 1981, 1986 Murdoch. Basil Blackwell Ltd 108 Cowley Road, Oxford, OX4 1JF, UK All rights reserved. Except for the quotation of short passages for the purposes of criticism and review, no part of this publication may be NOTE TO SECOND EDITION reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or THE text has been revised for the new edition. A large number of otherwise, without the prior permission of the publisher. small changes have been made in the English text. The following passages have been significantly altered: Except in the United States of America, this book is sold to the In Part I: §§ 108, 109, 116, 189, 193, 251, 284, 352, 360, 393,418, condition that it shall not, by way of trade or otherwise, be lent, re- 426, 442, 456, 493, 520, 556, 582, 591, 644, 690, 692.
    [Show full text]
  • A New Logic for Uncertainty
    A New Logic for Uncertainty ∗ LUO Maokang and HE Wei† Institute of Mathematics Institute of Mathematics Sichuan University Nanjing Normal University Chengdu, 610064 Nanjing, 210046 P.R.China P.R.China Abstract Fuzziness and randomicity widespread exist in natural science, engineering, technology and social science. The purpose of this paper is to present a new logic - uncertain propositional logic which can deal with both fuzziness by taking truth value semantics and randomicity by taking probabilistic semantics or possibility semantics. As the first step for purpose of establishing a logic system which completely reflect the uncertainty of the objective world, this logic will lead to a set of logical foundations for uncertainty theory as what classical logic done in certain or definite situations or circumstances. Keywords: Fuzziness; randomicity; UL-algebra; uncertain propositional logic. Mathematics Subject Classifications(2000): 03B60. 1 Introduction As one of the most important and one of the most widely used concepts in the whole area of modern academic or technologic research, uncertainty has been involved into study and applications more than twenty years. Now along with the quickly expanding requirements of developments of science and technology, people are having to face and deal with more and more problems tangled with uncertainty in the fields of natural science, engineering or technology or even in social science. To these uncertain prob- arXiv:1506.03123v1 [math.LO] 9 Jun 2015 lems, many traditional theories and methods based on certain conditions or certain circumstances are not so effective and powerful as them in the past. So the importance of research on uncertainty is emerging more and more obviously and imminently.
    [Show full text]
  • Getting Realistic About Nominalism
    Getting Realistic about Nominalism Mark F. Sharlow URL: http://www.eskimo.com/~msharlow ABSTRACT In this paper I examine critically the relationship between the realist and nominalist views of abstract objects. I begin by pointing out some differences between the usage of existential statements in metaphysics and the usage of such statements in disciplines outside of philosophy. Then I propose an account of existence that captures the characteristic intuitions underlying the latter kind of usage. This account implies that abstract object existence claims are not as ontologically extravagant as they seem, and that such claims are immune to certain standard nominalistic criticisms. Copyright © 2003 Mark F. Sharlow. Updated 2009. 1 I. What Do People Really Mean by "Exist"? There appears to be a marked difference between the way in which philosophers use the word "exist" and the way in which many other people use that word. This difference often shows itself when beginners in philosophy encounter philosophical positions that deny the existence of seemingly familiar things. Take, for example, nominalism — a view according to which multiply exemplifiable entities, such as properties and relations, really do not exist. (This definition may not do justice to all versions of nominalism, but it is close enough for our present purpose.) A strict nominalist has to deny, for example, that there are such things as colors. He can admit that there are colored objects; he even can admit that we usefully speak as though there were colors. But he must deny that there actually are colors, conceived of as multiply exemplifiable entities. A newcomer to philosophy might hear about the nominalist view of colors, and say in amazement, "How can anyone claim that there are no such things as colors? Look around the room — there they are!" To lessen this incredulity, a nominalist might explain that he is not denying that we experience a colorful world, or that we can usefully talk as if there are colors.
    [Show full text]
  • Russell's Theory of Descriptions
    Russell’s theory of descriptions PHIL 83104 September 5, 2011 1. Denoting phrases and names ...........................................................................................1 2. Russell’s theory of denoting phrases ................................................................................3 2.1. Propositions and propositional functions 2.2. Indefinite descriptions 2.3. Definite descriptions 3. The three puzzles of ‘On denoting’ ..................................................................................7 3.1. The substitution of identicals 3.2. The law of the excluded middle 3.3. The problem of negative existentials 4. Objections to Russell’s theory .......................................................................................11 4.1. Incomplete definite descriptions 4.2. Referential uses of definite descriptions 4.3. Other uses of ‘the’: generics 4.4. The contrast between descriptions and names [The main reading I gave you was Russell’s 1919 paper, “Descriptions,” which is in some ways clearer than his classic exposition of the theory of descriptions, which was in his 1905 paper “On Denoting.” The latter is one of the optional readings on the web site, and I reference it below sometimes as well.] 1. DENOTING PHRASES AND NAMES Russell defines the class of denoting phrases as follows: “By ‘denoting phrase’ I mean a phrase such as any one of the following: a man, some man, any man, every man, all men, the present king of England, the centre of mass of the Solar System at the first instant of the twentieth century, the revolution of the earth around the sun, the revolution of the sun around the earth. Thus a phrase is denoting solely in virtue of its form.” (‘On Denoting’, 479) Russell’s aim in this article is to explain how expressions like this work — what they contribute to the meanings of sentences containing them.
    [Show full text]