Cartesianism Revisited1
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Cartesianism Revisited1 Eric P. Lewis Virginia Tech In the summer of 2006 Daniel Garber opened the FME International Seminar in Early Modern Thought by commenting: “This has become the place to be.” The unexplained utterance generated smiles among the small room full of scholars, and could easily have been written off as an in- nocent bit of self-lauding or an ironic reference to the remoteness—even obscurity—of the seminar’s site.2 The list of seminar participants con- tained half a dozen philosophers from prestigious universities dotting the globe. Their research garnered a wide, if not deep, following. However, the dozen or so others listed on the program included graduate students, and tenured and non-tenured faculty who labored in greater obscurity in several academic disciplines. Together, these scholars seemed an unlikely group to deªne the remote town in Romania (at least at that moment) as “the place to be” for researchers of early modern thought. The seminar title, “Disseminating Knowledge in the Seventeenth Cen- tury: Centers and Peripheries in the Republic of Letters,” though innocu- ous enough, is indicative of a style of philosophical research that until fairly recently remained marginalized within the majority of English 1. This article discusses several recently published works about the reception of Des- cartes in the seventeenth century. It argues that the categories traditionally used by mod- ern philosophers to deªne the early modern period have been corrupted by the studies and works represented here. The result is not just a more nuanced view of early modern philos- ophy, but also a substantially different picture of the intellectual landscape. The editors of the books in this review share a similar methodological approach to their subject, an ap- proach that separates them from a more analytical style of philosophy that is practiced by many of their colleagues. The publications under review are: Ariew and Garber 2002, Schmaltz 2002, Schmaltz 2005, and Lennon 2003. 2. The seminar was held in the town of Bran, Romania, best known for the castle asso- ciated with Bram Stoker’s Dracula. Perspectives on Science 2007, vol. 15, no. 4 ©2007 by The Massachusetts Institute of Technology 493 Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/posc.2007.15.4.493 by guest on 26 September 2021 494 Cartesianism Revisited speaking philosophy departments.3 The fact that Garber, chair of the de- partment of philosophy at Princeton, could conªdently make his opening proclamation underscored a methodological struggle to which he success- fully dedicated a career. Garber recently explained: What my generation of historians was reacting against was a bun- dle of practices that characterized the writing of the history of phi- losophy in the period: the tendency to substitute rational recon- structions of a philosopher’s views for the views themselves; the tendency to focus on an extremely narrow group of ªgures (Des- cartes, Spinoza, and Leibniz, Locke, Berkeley, and Hume in my pe- riod);...thetendency to treat the philosophical positions as if they were those presented by contemporaries; and on and on and on.” (Garber 2004, 2.) The young and old present at the seminar likely wished that more of Garber’s generation acted in concert with him; yet the emphasis of “pe- ripheries” and “disseminating knowledge” is precisely the result of this philosophical style. Similar conferences have cropped up over the last decade, often self- consciously struggling with the terminology of “outsiders” and “peripher- ies” as they have explored the role of the contemporaries of Descartes, Hobbes, Spinoza and Leibniz.4 Philosophers such as Walter Charleton, John Davies, Bernardo Telesio, Pierre-Daniel Huet, Pierre-Sylvain Regis, and Robert Desgabets, to name a few, were in no conventional way “out- side” their respective intellectual communities, yet they have been largely excluded from modern discourse about early modern philosophy.5 The par- ticipants of these conferences typically focus much less on the perceived internal coherence of a text such as Descartes’ Meditations than on under- standing the text through the reactions of the author’s contemporaries; or, conversely, understanding a primary philosopher as a reaction to his con- temporaries. They share an assumption that lay behind Garber’s criticism: 3. I call this a “style” of philosophy because I wish to avoid creating false dichotomies. As will be discussed, recent research into late scholasticism and the reception of Cartesian thought demonstrates a rich spectrum of views that challenge the dichotomies tradition- ally drawn. Likewise, modern methods of research span a spectrum that can best be de- scribed in terms of tendencies. 4. Participants at a colloquium titled “Outsiders in Early Modern Philosophy,” The Warburg Institute, London, Fall 2003, discussed the fallacy of calling the subjects of their research “outsiders” when many were at the center of their intellectual community. 5. We might also successfully apply the terms “outsiders” and “peripheries” in a self- reºective way. The methodological struggle precipitated by Garber and others has, at times, elicited attempts to ostracize those whose research has had a greater contextual fo- cus. Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/posc.2007.15.4.493 by guest on 26 September 2021 Perspectives on Science 495 researchers can better recover the meaning of a text when their efforts are applied to intellectual context. The fact that Garber proclaimed to a group of scholars, united in their study of “centers and peripheries,” that they were in “the place to be” is nothing if not ironic as these scholars and their research subjects become better recognized on the “inside” of their respec- tive philosophical circles. No shortage of words has been spilled by philosophers concerning the merits of this increased emphasis on context.6 The late Margaret Wilson called Garber and Michael Ayers to task for comments they wrote in the introduction to The Cambridge History of Seventeenth-Century Philosophy. As editors, Garber and Ayers claimed that commentators in the “analytic tra- dition” not only ignored the philosophical complexities of their subjects and “distorted [philosophy’s] achievements, but also often denied them- selves the tools necessary for the interpretation of the very words and sen- tences they continue to expound” (Garber and Ayers 1998, 4).7 For her part, Wilson promoted a “softening of the ideological division, rather than to advocate any general thesis, factual or normative, about the relation of philosophy and history” (Wilson 1992, 195). But Wilson worried that the “detail and professionalism ...ofthesort desired for their volume by the Cambridge History editors . can tend to discourage “use” of historical ªgures by contemporary philosophers of a certain conscientiousness” (Wil- son 1992, 205). She quoted David Lewis who admitted that he had not discussed Leibniz’s views about the plurality of worlds in a recent work because he lacked the expertise to conªdently represent the philosopher’s ideas on the subject. Lewis had the choice between publishing something that he admitted might be “undeserving of others’ attention,” or sparing philosophers from those pages. Ostensibly, he had a further choice: to de- vote much more attention to Leibniz’s work on the topic. But Lewis said that after reading “what serious historians of philosophy” had to say, he gave up because of the lack of consensus among them (Wilson 1992, 204). He apparently had little desire to tackle the primary sources himself and instead appealed to “serious” historians of philosophy, whomever they might be. Pragmatic concerns thus trumped, in this case, any discussion of Leibniz’s contribution to the issue of the plurality of worlds. Wilson la- mented that Lewis failed to stray from his narrower philosophical project because the demands of current historical research were so high. Lewis 6. A conference titled: “Do Historians and Philosophers of Science Have Anything to Say to Each Other?” was recently held at Duke University, March 2007. 7. Wilson’s criticisms were published in The Philosophical Review, January 1992, well prior to the actual publication of the volume that contained Garber and Ayer’s comments. Garber (2004) later characterized his comments above as a “cartoon version of the “ana- lytic” history of philosophy” and a “useful demon to posit.” Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/posc.2007.15.4.493 by guest on 26 September 2021 496 Cartesianism Revisited simply left his reader to wonder how (or why) he would have used Leibniz in his work if there had been a consensus on his doctrine of the plurality of worlds, and if we should consider this shortage of words problematic. Beyond the pedagogical issues facing philosophers working in early modern history, Bernard Williams claimed that the two different styles of research inevitably yielded incompatible products “in rather the way that Impressionism, by exploring as intensely as possible the surface effects of light, was thereby debarred from giving as much information about struc- ture as was accessible to some other styles of painting” (Williams 1994, 20).8 Though Williams did not explicitly tell his reader which of the two styles was analogous with Impressionism, his claim that the more histori- cally inclined “naturally looks sideways to the context of a philosopher’s ideas” seemed to answer the question. The negative connotations of a “sideways” look may be avoided if Wil- liams meant that the resulting picture exists, or should exist, independ- ently of what he calls “present problems” in philosophy. Context, in this case, may say something novel and interesting about the ideas of an histor- ical ªgure such as Descartes, but tell the modern philosopher nothing (or worse—something distorting) pertaining to one’s present philosophical objectives. However, if Williams is correct, doesn’t this make the two “styles” irrelevant to each other? In Descartes Reinvented (2005) Tom Sorell, like Wilson, purports to offer a reconciliation of sorts between philosophers and their more historically oriented colleagues.