The Theory of Value of Christian Von

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Theory of Value of Christian Von From: R. Fabian (ed.), Christian von Ehrenfels: Leben und Werk. 151 Amsterdam: Rodopi, (l986), l50-l71l material, in vol. I of Reinhard Fabian's edition of Ehrenfels' Philosophische Schriften. I shall refer principally to the System der Werttheorie, citing page numbers according to the Fabian edition. What follows is intended as no more than an outline of Ehrenfels' THE THEORY OF VALUE OF CHRISTIAN VON EHRENFELS views, with some reference to the relations between his work and the subjectivist approach to economic values initiated by Carl Menger in Barry SMITH • his Grundsätze der Volkswirtschaftslehre in 1871. All criticism will be spared, as also will detailed considerations of influence. 1 1 shall concentrate exclusively on value theory in the strict sense as Ehrenfels § 1. lntroduction conceived it, avoiding conjecturcs as to the ways in which this theory §2. Foundations of a General Theory of Values rnight be supplemented by ideas from the theory of Gestalten to §3. The Relation between Desire and Feeling produce an account which would be more adequate to the dimension §4. The Objects of Desire of aesthetic value.2 §5. On the Nature of Values §6. Types of Value §2. Foundations of a General Theory of Values §7. What Doth Charity Avail Me? §8. Interpersonal Value-Comparisons Menger founded what has since corne to be known as the "first" §9. The Struggle for Existencc among Values Austrian school of valuc theory. The first-generation members of this § 10. Value and Habit school included also Eugen von Böhm-Bawerk and Friedrich von 3 § 11. Conclusion Wieser, with both of whom Ehrenfels had significant exchanges. The school is today represented by. arnong others, F.A. von Hayek, Ludwig Lachmann and I.M. Kirzner, and passing mention will be § 1. lntroduction rnade in§ 10 below of possible lines of comparison between Ehrenfels' thought and that of Hayek, in particular. Ehrenfels' principal writings on value theory belong to the early Ehrenfels, on the other hand, together with Meinong and other period of his creative life. their publication following immediately pupils of Brentano. belonged to the "second" Austrian school of upon that of his classic paper "Über 'Gestaltqualitäten"'. They are:1 value theory: In contradistinction to the economists, the members of - "Werttheorie und Ethik", a series of five articles published in this school were concerned to develop a genera/ theory of values. 1893-94; They regarded economic value as only one special sort of human - "Von der Wertdefinition zum Motivationsgesetze", published value. and urged that economic values could be properly undetstood in the Archiv für systematische Philosophie in 1896; only when their connection with the entire range of value-phenomena - "The Ethical Theory of Value", a revi!!W of Meinong's Psycho­ had been made clear. logisch-ethische Untersuchungen zur Werttheorie, published in the 1. For discussions of influences on Ehrenfels' value theory see Eaton, International Journal of Ethics in 1896; Grassl, 1982a, and Fabian-Simons. and: 2. The reader is however invited to cornpare the conception of value as - System der Werttheorie, vol. I: Al/gemeine Werttheorie, Psycho­ organic unity set forth by Nozick in ch.5 of his 1981 with ideas sketched by logie des Begehrens (1897) and vol. II: Grundzüge einer Ethik Ehrenfels, e.g. in the fragment "Höhe und Reinheit der Gestalt" (1916). (1898). 3. Grass!, op.cit. is now the definitive survey of these exchanges. All of these writings are now collected, with othcr, supplementary 4. See Eaton and, 011 the wider membership and influence of the schooi, Grassl, 1981 and (forthcoming). 152 153 The rnembers of this second school did however look up to the we do not desire things because we grnsp in them some mysticaL economists as having achieved a theoretical depth and rigour in their incomprehensible essence "vaiue"; rather, we ascribe "value" to things analyses which was at that time lacking in work on values on the part because we desire them (p.219). of their fe llow philosophers. Ethics, in particular, Ehrenfels Of course the immediate suspicion awakened by a view of this kind conceived as having hardly advanced beyond its beginnings with the is that, in spite of the detour through desire. it must amount to some Greeks: form of hedonism, i.e. to the view that the value of an object is it sets as its goal. ..an extraneous and often arbitrary hsting :md ranking of • ultimately a matter of the pleasure (fee iing) it will bring. But ethical and other value-objccts, from whichone might at best glean thost: Ehrenfels is not a hedonist: he does not hold that one's own fee!ings fe..,..,ons inherited from past ages which we ,·all "worldly wisdom" •·­ constitme the u!timate goal of all desiring. To see why not, it is something which we normally learn to understand 10 appreciate only when necessary to mention briefly his account of the relationship between we have acquired it for oursclves and at our own cost (p.214f. ). desire and presentation. Desire is dirccted towards some desired But how is the desired 1heore1ical understanding of values to be objec;t (the word 'object', hcre, beinp: understood in the widest achieved? Here Ehrcnfels turned on the one hand to the task of possible sense, to includr also prnperties, relations, prncesscs, etc.). generalising laws of valuat1on wh1ch had been discovered by the And this desired object, according ro Ehrenfe!s, rnust be presented in economistc;. above all thc iaw of marginal utihty. And on the other some way by he who desires it. Seme 1dea of it must be present as a band hc turned to psyd1ology. This he conceived. with some constituent of the act of desire. The question ol hedonism amounts, diffe rcnces, in ihe way Brentano conceived it in the Psychologie vom therefore. to the question whether, when we desir-:,we also necessari­ empiriJchcn 5itandpunkt. Li!. as a descriprive psychology of diffe rent ly present to ourselves our own pkasure or our own pain, or the kinds of acts and of interrelations betwel:"nac ts. These two strands in removal of the same. And the answer to this quest1on is that in many Ehrenfrls' work and indecd in the work of �'h:inong, whe>musr be cases we do. but not in a/J. creditcd with having taken the first steps m this din:-ctiotL support This is the case fi rst of all beca use: eac:h other mutually: the same laws hold for moral vaiues as for in the most common circumstances of our everyday life our dcsiring goes econormc values because thc two sor!.S of values have the same directly ro certain routine externaltasks such as eating. drinking, waiting, p.syrhological fo undations. sitting, sieeping. etc., w1thout therc bcing presented thereby the state of feeling which corresponds to these tasks (p.236) §3. The Relation between Desire and Feeling - a poi nt which anticipates the important role played by habit in Ehrenfels' theory, to be discussed in §10 below. Ehienfels' psychological foundation of vaiue-theory conceives the And it is the case , secondly, because some desires relate to periods value of things as dependent upon human valuing acts, which are in of time of which the subject will not or could not have experience, or turn wnceived as being dcpendent upon acts of desire. Thus, at least to the feeli ngs of individuals with whom he cou!d have no con• in fi rst approximation, ceivable contact. I might, for example, desire that my remote descendants should have the opportunity to acquire a taste for 5. The most important diffe rence, from our present point of view, is the oysters: or I might wish that the Spanish Inquisition had never taken sharp distinction drawn by Ehrenfels between the two categories offeeling place; and a range of other cases can be brought forward to and desire. These were run together by Brentano into the single category of demonstrate that the concept of an act which is directed towards 'phenomena of love and hate'. Brentano is criticised on this point also by goals other than one's own feelings does not contain any sort of Anscombe in her 1978. lt is the common indebtedness to a Brentanian act­ contradiction.6 psychology which, more than anything eise. makes it appropriate to regard Ehrenfels. Meinong, Kraus, Kreibig and others as members of a single 6. Complement.ary arguments to the same effect are to be found in school. Duncker, 1941. 154 155 Whilst the desiring subject does not in every case desire his own asserts that there is a tendency forthe utility derived frnm a good to happiness, there is of course some relation between desire and decrease with an increase in its supply, expresses one aspect of a happmess or. more generally, between desire and feeling. But this complex relation of dependence involving the <lispositional proper� relation is a complex one, involving both the dispositions of the given ties of a good to yield utility. individual and the relative promotion of happiness which he expe­ Note, too, that it would be unreasonable to assert any law of riences as being associated with given acts. absolute increase in happiness. One might, for exampie, do con­ We can say, very roughly, that the disposition to desire on the part tinuous battle against an evil (for exampie ill-health), which is of a given individual is dependent upon the d1sposit10ns of that nevertheiess continuaily worsening, and still be always relatively individual to have certain feelings. To say more than this. we have to happier than one would otherwise have been. It is necessary, for recognise that acts of desire, according to Ehrenfets,ar e divided into given acts of striving and willing to take place, only that, should one three categories of wishing, striving, and willing.
Recommended publications
  • Social Objects(1)
    Social Objects(1) Barry Smith Department of Philosophy, Center for Cognitive Science, and National Center for Geographic Information and Analysis University at Buffalo [email protected] 1. Introduction 1.1 Two Dogmas of Reductionism Two persistent tendencies have made themselves felt in the course of philosophical history. On the one hand is the Ockhamite tendency, the tendency to embrace one or other of a small repertoire of simplified ontologies, for example atomism or monism, together with a view according to which more complicated entities are to be ‘reduced’ by one or other means to the favoured class of simples. On the other hand is Cartesianism, the tendency to embrace one or other foundationalist doctrine in epistemology, or in other words to prize episteme at the expense of doxa. The two tendencies reinforce each other mutually. Thus foundationalism tilts the attention of philosophers in the direction of ontological simples, for it is held that in relation to the latter knowledge secure against doubt is more easily attainable. Philosophers are thus shielded from any concern with the complex mesoscopic (medium-sized, middle-range, human-scale) objects of our everyday environment and of the social world, since the latter is, after all, a realm of mere opinion, not worthy of the attention of those striving after rigour. Austrian philosophers have been marked no less than philosophers in other traditions by both of these tendencies. Brentano, especially, was an avowed foundationalist, a proponent of psychological immanentism, and in his later philosophizing he embraced an ontology according to which all objects must belong to the single category of thing or substance.
    [Show full text]
  • Comptes Rendus / Book Reviews
    COMPTES RENDUS / BOOK REVIEWS Robin D. Rollinger, Austrian Phenomenology: Brentano, Husserl, Meinong, and Others on Mind and Object. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag, 2008; 326 pages. ISBN: 978-3868380057. Review by Kimberly Baltzer-Jaray, Independent Scholar. Nietzsche was not alone in his skepticism and contempt for systematic philosophy, the stuff Hegel and Kant were made of; in fact on this point he could be called the voice of a generation and a timely man. Many academics in the mid to late 19th century felt a sort of ill will towards phi- losophy, especially given the leaps and bounds happening in science. Philosophy seemed less rigorous, impractical and out of touch with the modern era: who needed to contemplate God, freedom, and immortality when scientists were in their labs or in the field actively discovering laws of energy, plant cells, electromagnetism, radiation and evolution? Meta- physics and epistemology just couldn’t compete with physics and biol- ogy. However, several philosophers in Austria thought they could make philosophy more scientific and definitively show the academic commu- nity that philosophy was not to be retired like a relic of the past, but rather could hold her own as a discipline. One of the most notable groups of philosophers to attempt such a defence of philosophy was the School of Brentano, named after its leader, Franz Brentano, and which included his pupils Carl Stumpf, Anton Marty, Edmund Husserl, Kasimir Twardowski and Christian von Ehrenfels. This is where Rollinger’s book begins. Rollinger’s volume is a collection of revised, previously pub- lished papers. It is a comprehensive and insightful book, a necessity for anyone studying the Austrian philosophical tradition, or the early phe- nomenological movement under Husserl (Munich and Göttingen circles respectively).
    [Show full text]
  • Christian Von Ehrenfels (1859-1932) and Edgar Rubin (1886-1951)
    CHRISTIAN VON EHRENFELS (1859-1932) AND EDGAR RUBIN (1886-1951) Geert-Jan Boudewijnse Introduction Christian von EHRENFELS was an original and creative thinker. His On ‘Gestalt Qualities’ is an early work that had an immediate impact on the small world of GerGer-- man psychologists. When he was professor at the German University of Prague, he wrote several books, including an opus on sexuality. Like many academics, he had the tendency to be radical and his views on sexuality would not be shared by his contemporaries or by later generations. Hence, his fi rst article on Gestalt perception was his only paper that resonated; all his other studies seem to have had no effect on psychology. I will compare EHRENFELS’ notions on Gestalt perception as he developed them in his seminal article with Edgar RUBIN’s (1886-1951) explanation of the fi gure- ground phenomenon. RUBIN was a Danish psychologist and a student of Harold HÖFFDING (1843-1931). He worked for two years in G.E. MÜLLER’s laboratory at Götingen, and in 1915 he published the results of those experiments in Danish (Synsoplevende Figurer). This book was translated into German in 1921 under the title Visuell wahrgenommene Figuren. It is this translation that I will refer to. Michael WERTHEIMER made an abridged English translation of the German version (FigureFigure and Ground). RUBIN had a considerable infl uenceuence onon GestaltGestalt psychology;psychology; KOFFKAKOFFKA wrote a review of RUBIN’s book in 1922, and KOFFKA devoted a whole chapter to the fi gure-ground phenomenon in hisPrinciples of Gestalt Psychology (1935) . The comparison between RUBIN and EHRENFELS will also illustrate the dif- ference between the theoretical or armchair psychology practised at the end of the 19th-century (by EHRENFELS) and the experimental psychology practised at the be- ginning of the 20th-century (by RUBIN).
    [Show full text]
  • The Politics of National Diversity Wolfgang Grassl and Barry Smith
    The Politics of National Diversity Wolfgang Grassl and Barry Smith It is reported that Saint Stephen, first Apostoli~ King of more strictly political sort (allegiances to the State, lor Hungary, had advised his son Emmerich that he·should example, or to the Crown). The culture and morality of not spare to invite foreigners into the Kingdom. His Great Britain have moreover been shaped as much by grounds were that 'unius linguae uniusque morjs regnum supranational allegiances - to Western or Protestant imbecile etfragile est': a kingdom with but one language and Christe·ndom, to the British Empire, to the C0I1111}0\1- one custom is weak and fragile. This remark is, one notes, wealth of English-speaking peoples - as by political at odds with much recent conservative philosophical allegiances in the narrower sense. theorising. For the latter has tended to stress the virtues Unfortunately the British imperial experience pro­ of social and institutional homogeneity - the virtues of duced little in the way of positive philosophical theoris­ the nation state as classically conceived. The present ing on its own behalf: Hence, if we are to find a essay challenges that kind of conservatism. framework which might be used to help us cope with or National conservatism can be contested, it seems, make sense of the internal multi- national dynastic con­ from two complementary perspectives. The first would stitution of present-day British society, we shall have to look as it were beneath the level of the state or nation, to look elsewhere. Now one very clear historical example of social entities and forms of social organisation con­ a supranational state incorporating a multiplicity of stituted by individuals as agents in the market or as racial, linguistic and religious groupings is of course the membra voluntativa of corporate associations of various Danube Monarchy of Austria-Hungary, a response to sorts.
    [Show full text]
  • The Brentano School
    r PIi 10 (2000), 244-259. Neil AIIan 245 1 1 I My own research into the work of Franz Kafka led me to investigate the intellectual atmosphere in Prague at the beginning of the twentieth I1I century, and what is striking, in this context, is that while the short-lived and comparatively infertile "project" of Jena has been the object of such II II retrospective celebration, the "school" which perhaps realized its 1 1'1 culmination in Prague at this time has been somewhat neglected. The 1I 11 The Brentano School philosophical (and literary) fecundity of this period is quite remarkable, as are the dramatis personae of figures only tangentially related to the NEILALLAN "school" in question: Robert Musil, Roman Jakobson, Sigmund Freud, Emst Mach, Albert Einstein.) The central figures (some of whom are well known, while others have been victims of an often unjustified neglect) of this "school" (of which It sometimes happens that a particular place at a particular time (and for Prague was only one centre; Graz was perhaps the most significant other specific historical, social, and political reasons) can witness the location) include Anton Marty, Christian von Ehrenfels, Alexius concentrated and localized emergence of a significant new strain of Meinong, Ewald Hering, Carl Stumpf, Oskar Kraus, Stephan Witasek, thought. Such is the case with Jena at the end of the eighteenth century; Kasimir Twardowski, and Edmund Husserl. What they shared was a indeed "Jena", for the history of philosophy, is less a geographical preoccupation with the work of Franz Brentano, and what is especially notation than a shorthand for the fruition of German idealism, or, for notable is the variety of directions in which their often critical literature, the ephemeral but prophetic project of early romanticism.
    [Show full text]
  • German Holism Revisited: Really?
    Review Essay J¨uri Allik and Wolfgang Drechsler University of Tartu, Estonia German Holism Revisited: Really? Harrington, Anne, Reenchanted Science: Holism in German Culture from Wilhelm II to Hitler. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996. 312 pp. ISBN 0–691–02142–2 Anne Harrington, Professor of the History of Science at Harvard University, has written a so far very well-received book on the history of holism in Germany. The biographies of four men are at its center: Jakob von Uexkull, ¨ Constantin von Monakow, Max Wertheimer and Kurt Goldstein—although Christian von Ehrenfels, Wolfgang K¨ohler, Hans Driesch and others receive considerable treatment as well. It is not clear on which basis the four main characters were selected. To a good extent, the book parallels Mitchell G. Ash’s Gestalt Psychology in German Culture, 1890–1967 (1995). Reenchanted Science belongs to the American ‘Science Wars’ frame- work, in which Harrington is a bridge-builder between the hard-nosed natural scientists and those theoreticians who seem to threaten the absolute truth-claim of the former. Commendable as this is, in order to locate the development of science in the social-political context of its time, one needs some working knowledge about this context. Harring- ton’s knowledge of Nazi Germany, however, is but slight; that of the German Empire and World War I, slighter still and mainly based on 25-year-old textbook-style accounts, rehashing outdated clich´es (see pp. 19–21, 24, 31, 58). While one cannot expect original research on every subject in a book like this, there are by far too many secondary and even tertiary Culture & Psychology Copyright G 1999 SAGE Publications (London, Thousand Oaks, CA and New Delhi) Vol.
    [Show full text]
  • The Legacy of Max Wertheimer and Gestalt Psychology Author(S): D
    The Legacy of Max Wertheimer and Gestalt Psychology Author(s): D. BRETT KING, MICHAEL WERTHEIMER, HEIDI KELLER and KEVIN CROCHETIÈRE Source: Social Research, Vol. 61, No. 4, Sixtieth Anniversary 1934-1994: The Legacy of Our Past (WINTER 1994), pp. 907-935 Published by: The Johns Hopkins University Press Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/40971065 Accessed: 22-02-2019 02:34 UTC JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at https://about.jstor.org/terms The Johns Hopkins University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Social Research This content downloaded from 149.31.21.88 on Fri, 22 Feb 2019 02:34:10 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms The Legacy of Max Wertheimer /BY D. BRETT KING, MICHAEL and Gestalt / WERTHEIMER, HEIDI KELLER AND Psychology/ KEVIN CROCHETIÈRE In 1946, Solomon Asch wrote that the "thinking of Max Wertheimer has penetrated into nearly every region of psychological inquiry and has left a permanent impress on the minds of psychologists and on their daily work. The consequences have been far-reaching in the work of the last three decades, and are likely to expand in the future" (Asch, 1946, p.
    [Show full text]
  • Christian Von Ehrenfels – the Founder of Gestalt Theory Or Merely the Provider of a Trade Mark in Science?
    Christian von Ehrenfels – The Founder of Gestalt Theory or merely the Provider of a Trade Mark in Science? Alf C. Zimmer When looking into modern dictionaries or companions of philosophy, especially in the Anglo- American field, one does not succeed in finding a biographical entry for Christian von Ehrenfels. However, the same books will dwell in detail on the role of his 1890 article on „Gestaltqualitäten“ as the single-handed breakthrough of which later became Gestalt psychology. In the following I will argue that neither the theoretical (and scarce empirical) background of the article was as revolutionary as the research programme of Gestalt Psychology later became nor that the core principle of transposition went beyond Meinong’s Relationism or Richard Wagner’s music theory, which Ehrenfels admired. For these reasons, Meinong as well as Husserl received the article very positively but both suggested to skip the term „Gestalt“ and suggested in turn „fundierter Inhalt“ (Meinong 1969, p. 288, later „fundierter Gegenstand“ Meinong 1971, p. 399) or „Einheitsmoment“ (Husserl 1984, p. 237). Christian Freiherr (baron) von Ehrenfels was born in Rodaun, Austria on the 20 th of June 1859. During his studies at the University of Vienna he was strongly influenced first by Franz Brentano and later by Brentano’s pupil, Alexius Meinong. Less oriented towards experimentation than Meinong, Ehrenfels followed Brentano’s empiricism insofar as his method consisted of posing hypotheses and evaluating them by means of examples and counterexamples, however, in disavowing ‘Evidenz’ as leading to an infinite regress he limited the scope of empiricism to intersubjectively communicatable events.
    [Show full text]
  • Gestalt Theory: an Essay in Philosophy
    Barry Smith Gestalt Theory: An Essay in Philosophy §1. Introduction The Austrian philosopher Christian von Ehrenfels published his essay "On 'Gestalt Qualities'" in 1890. The essay initiated a current of thought which enjoyed a powerful position in the philosophy and psychology of the first half of this century and has more recently enjoyed a minor resurgence of interest in the area of cognitive science, above all in criticisms of the so-called 'strong programme' in artificial intelligence. 1 The theory of Gestalt is of course associated most specifically with psychologists of the Berlin school such as Max Wertheimer, Wolfgang Kohler and Kurt Koffka. We shall see in what follows, however, that an adequate philosophical understanding of the Gestalt idea and of Ehrenfels' achievement will require a close examination not merely of the work of the Berlin school but also of a much wider tradition in Austrian and German philosophy in general. Ehrenfels' essay of 1890 was published in the 'journal of scientific philosophy' [Vierteljahrsschrift fur wissenschaftliche Philosophie1 edited by the positivist philosopher Richard Avenarius, and we can assume that Ehrenfels' decision to publish in Avenarius' journal was influenced by the fact that his essay had been provoked by certain passages on perception in the writings of Ernst Mach, with whom Avenarius is commonly associated. The most important influence on Ehrenfels' thinking was however that of his own principal teacher Franz Brentano, and Ehrenfels belongs to an impressive list of gifted and original thinkers - including Alexius Meinong, Edmund Husserl, Carl Stumpf, Anton Marty and Kasimir Twardowski - whose philosophy was shaped decisively by that of Brentano.
    [Show full text]
  • Carl Stumpf: a Reluctant Revolutionary David Trippett
    Chapter 2 Carl Stumpf: A reluctant revolutionary David Trippett If historical events are to mark the boundaries of a life lived, one could be forgiven for suspecting that Carl Stumpf (1848–1936) might have been a political revolutionary: born during the months of revolutionary uprisings across Europe, he died a few months after Hitler’s troops occupied the Rhineland in violation of the Treaty of Versailles. Yet, as a scientist, his convictions carried no muscular force; still less any politi- cal conviction. His sphere was intellectual. Though, as we shall see, this would prove no less influential in charting the course of the disciplines of psychology and (ethno)musicology, than the events that framed his life would serve to alter the course of European history. Stumpf came from a family of doctors and acknowledged in 1924 that a central portion of his professional life was devoted to bridging his early love of music and his familial inclination towards the natural sciences. Between 1875 (with his work on the Psychology of Tone ) and 1911 (when he published The Origins of Music ) he investigated the phenomenon of sound as a stimulus at once physical, physiological, and psychological, i.e. something following the laws of Newtonian physics, operative within the functions of the brain, and hence traceable within the more opaque realm of the mind. Music, as the perception of sound configurations cultivated by people, thereby effected Stumpf’s theories of sensation, perception, and cognition. With his 1911 hypothesis about the prehis- tory of music, Stumpf added a historical dimension to this study, one that is influenced by, though also differentiated from, Charles Darwin’s evolutionary theory first documented in On the Origin of Species (1859).
    [Show full text]
  • A Thesis Subrnitted to the Facuity of Graduate Studies and Research in Partial Fulfiiment of the Requirements of the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy
    The gestalt line by Geert-Jan A. Boudewijnse Department of Psychology McGill University, Montreal A Thesis subrnitted to the Facuity of Graduate Studies and Research in partial fulfiiment of the requirements of the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Al1 rights reserved Geert-Jan Adriaan Boudewijnse, 1996 National Library Bibliothèque nationale I*(of Canada du Canada Acquisitions and Acquisitions et Bibliographie Services services bibliographiques 395 Wellington Street 395. tue Wellington Ottawa ON KIA ON4 OttawaON KIA ON4 canada Canada The author has granted a non- L'auteur a accordé une licence non exclusive licence allowing the exclusive permettant à la National Library of Canada to Bibliothèque nationale du Canada de reproduce, loan, distribute or sell reproduire, prêter, distribuer ou copies of this thesis in microform, vendre des copies de cette thèse sous paper or electronic formats. la forme de rnicrofiche/~,de reproduction sur papier ou sur format électronique. The author retains ownership of the L'auteur conserve la propriété du copyright in this thesis. Neither the droit d'auteur qui protège cette thèse. thesis nor substantial extracts fkom it Ni la thèse ni des extraits substantiels may be prhted or otherwise de celle-ci ne doivent êeimprimés reproduced without the author's ou autrement reproduits sans son permission. autorisation. CONTENTS RES UME ACKNOWLEDGMENTS TRANSLATOR'S NOTE INTRODUCTION The lineage General Framework Previous work on the history of gestalt theory Overview FRANZ BRENTANO Aristotelean roots Unity of consciousness
    [Show full text]
  • A Gestalt Music Analysis
    JYVÄSKYLÄ STUDIES IN HUMANITIES 39 Jaana Utriainen A Gestalt Music Analysis Philosophical Theory, Method, and Analysis of Iegor Reznikoff’s Compositions JYVÄSKYLÄN YLIOPISTO JYVÄSKYLÄ STUDIES IN HUMANITIES 39 Jaana Utriainen A Gestalt Music Analysis Philosophical Theory, Method, and Analysis of Iegor Reznikoff’s Compositions Esitetään Jyväskylän yliopiston humanistisen tiedekunnan suostumuksella julkisesti tarkastettavaksi yliopiston vanhassa juhlasalissa (S212) elokuun 12. päivänä 2005 kello 12. Academic dissertation to be publicly discussed, by permission of the Faculty of Humanities of the University of Jyväskylä, in Auditorium S212, on August 12, 2005 at 12 o’clock noon. UNIVERSITY OF JYVÄSKYLÄ JYVÄSKYLÄ 2005 A Gestalt Music Analysis Philosophical Theory, Method, and Analysis of Iegor Reznikoff’s Compositions JYVÄSKYLÄ STUDIES IN HUMANITIES 39 Jaana Utriainen A Gestalt Music Analysis Philosophical Theory, Method, and Analysis of Iegor Reznikoff’s Compositions UNIVERSITY OF JYVÄSKYLÄ JYVÄSKYLÄ 2005 Editors Matti Vainio, Department of Music, University of Jyväskylä Pekka Olsbo, Marja-Leena Tynkkynen Publishing Unit, University Library of Jyväskylä Jyväskylä Studies in Humanities Editorial Board Heikki Hanka, Department of Art and Culture Studies, University of Jyväskylä Toivo Nygård, Department of History and Ethnology, University of Jyväskylä Ahti Jäntti, Department of Languages, University of Jyväskylä Matti Vainio, Department of Music, University of Jyväskylä Minna-Riitta Luukka, Centre for Applied Language Studies, University of Jyväskylä Raimo Salokangas, Department of Communication, University of Jyväskylä Cover picture: The acoustical representation of the “bird’s voices” in Liturgie fondamentale (1:41.09-2:00, 1500 Hz). URN:ISBN:9513921816 ISBN 951-39-2181-6 (PDF) ISSN 1459-4331 ISBN 951-39-2143-3 (nid.) ISSN 1459-4323 Copyright © 2005, by University of Jyväskylä Jyväskylä University Printing House, Jyväskylä 2005 ABSTRACT Utriainen, Jaana A Gestalt Music Analysis.
    [Show full text]