The Collusion Deterrence Effect of Corporate Leniency Programs

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Collusion Deterrence Effect of Corporate Leniency Programs The Collusion Deterrence Effect of Corporate Leniency Programs Jeong-Yoo Kim∗ Kyung Hee University December 8, 2015 Abstract We examine the deterrence effect of the leniency program. Depending on the rela- tive importance of type I errors and type II errors, we characterize either a separating- equilibrium in which only guilty defendants apply for leniency and a pooling equilib- rium in which guilty and innocent types of defendants both apply for leniency. The leniency program has two conflicting effects on the incentive to collude. On one hand, a discount in fines reduces the expected cost of collusion and therefore increases the collusion rate. On the other hand, it discourages firms from colluding due to its in- formational efficiency. Contrary to the widespread perceptions, the model predicts that the latter effect predominates while the former effect is degenerated, so that the leniency program unambiguously reduces the overall collusion rate. Accordingly, it is socially beneficial, as long as the wrongful conviction probability of innocent firms is very low. The underlying intuition is that the antitrust authority must maintain the expected fine to the level not lower than without the leniency program to minimize type II errors, which prevents a diminution in the deterrence effect. This implies that it is never optimal to waive all penalties for any firm to self-report. Even if there are more than two co-defendants, the general intuition that the optimal leniency program allows a discount only to one defendant and the resultant collusion rate is reduced is carried over. ∗(Mailing address) Department of Economics, Kyung Hee University, 1 Hoegidong, Dongdaenumku, Seoul 130-701, Korea, (Tel & Fax) +82-2-961-0986, Email: [email protected] 1 JEL Classification Code: L41 Key Words: leniency programs, multiple defendants, deterrence Running Head: Corporate Leniency Programs 1 Introduction The leniency program has been used as a means of law enforcement against illegal antitrust behavior starting from US followed by the EU, Germany, South Korea and Japan. According to Korean Fair Trade Commission (KFTC), the corporate leniency program played a role in investigations for 17 out of 25 uncovered and fined cartels in Korea.1 According to U.S. Justice Department (2010), in the U.S. where the program was first introduced in 1978, firms have been fined more than $5 billion for antitrust crimes since 1996, with over 90 percent of the total attributed to leniency applications. Despite its efficiency argument, there are many criticisms against the leniency program. For example, some critics argue that the leniency program is unfair because it leads to inconsistent punishment for the same illegal corporate behavior and the possibility that a corporate criminal who applies to a leniency program may not receive penalty commensurate with the crime or even receive no penalty.2 Also, the leniency program may weaken the deterrent effect because the leniency program reduces the expected cost of illegal behavior. Notwithstanding these criticisms against the leniency program, it is now one of the most effective tools in cartel investigation. Recently, many authors including Aubert, Kovacic and Rey (2006), Motta and Polo (2003), Spragnolo (2003), Feess and Walzl (2004), Motchenkova (2004) and Harrington (2008) made economic analyses of the leniency program, especially focusing on the dynamic incentives of firms and the optimal design of the leniency program. However, most of the work assumes that the antitrust authority's objective is to minimize the occurrence of il- legal activities such as price fixing collusion. This assumption is problematic, because the antitrust authority must be concerned about the judicial errors, that is, the possibilities that innocent defendants are penalized (type-I error) and that guilty defendants are acquitted (type-II error) and the antitrust authority actually does care about the possibility of judicial 1See The Korea Times (2012). 2This argument is incomplete, however, because it considers only one side|the possibility that an actually guilty firm might be acquitted with the leniency program, although the opposite possibility that an actually innocent firm who is likely to be convicted might be acquitted with the leniency program clearly exists. 2 errors.3 The leniency program appears to be quite similar to plea bargaining whereby the pros- ecutor is allowed to bargain with defendants for sentences in exchange for their promise to testify against other co-defendants. Therefore, earlier work on plea bargaining may help understand the mechanism of the leniency program through which the society can be made better off. Most of the economic analysis for plea bargaining, however, focus on the single- defendant setting. There are some exceptions such as Kobayashi (1992) and Kim (2009), which consider the situation of multiple co-defendants who are known to be connected with the same crime. However, neither of the papers addressed the dynamic effect of plea bargain- ing on crime deterrence in a multiple defendant setting. Reinganum (1993) and Miceli (1996) undertook the dynamic issue and examined how the practice of plea bargaining can influence the criminal incentive of a potential defendant, but only in a model of a single defendant. In a companion paper by Kim (2015), we considered a dynamic model of plea-bargaining of a prosecutor accusing multiple co-defendants. Thus, in the model, defendants are not ex ante known to be guilty. Guilt or innocence of defendants are endogenously determined as a result of their criminal decisions. The paper shares much intuition in common with the current paper. We will characterize all possible separating-equilibrium in which only guilty defendants apply for leniency and a pooling equilibrium in which both types of defendants (guilty and innocent) apply for leniency. In both types of equilibria, the reduced fines must be fair in the sense that the more culpable defendant receives a harsher penalty. This stands in sharp contrast to the result of Kobayashi, who demonstrated the possibility of an unfair equilibrium in which the more culpable defendant receives a less harsh penalty in a plea bargaining setting. The difference comes mainly from the equilibrium concept employed. We demonstrate that unfairness cannot happen in equilibrium as long as the spirit of Nash equilibrium is respected by implicitly requiring agents' beliefs (or predictions) to be consistent with equilibrium strategies. The clear empirical regularities in the present-day US leniency institution motivates the model in which well-reinforced beliefs support veridical matching of beliefs and objective frequency as a forcing principle leading to the equilibrium selection. In a separating equilibrium, the reduced fines must be asymmetric because it is more costly to induce a more culpable defendant to report by accepting its respective discounted 3The mission of Federal Trade Commission (FTC) is to prevent anticompetitive business practices and to accomplish this without unduly burdening legitimate business activity. (See http://www.ftc.gov/about-ftc.) This is an evidence that the antitrust authority is concerned about minimizing the occurrence of judicial errors as well, not just minimizing illegal corporate activities nor maximizing the number of convictions. 3 fine and thus only a less culpable defendant is offered a discount. In a pooling equilib- rium, both defendants are offered discounts. Intuitively, higher pooling fines increase the probability of a type-I error and decrease the probability of a type-II error. The optimal pooling equilibrium is determined by the reduction in fines that balance these two effects (i.e., equating the marginal benefit from reducing type-II error with the marginal cost of increased rates of type-I errors for each defendant). The choice between a separating equi- librium and a pooling equilibrium depends on the relative importance of type-I and type-II errors. If type-I errors are relatively important, then the discounted fines must be charac- terizable as the antitrust authority's decisions that convey the larger aggregate rewards that are offered and accepted by both types, which leads to the pooling equilibrium. In contrast, the separating equilibrium is selected whenever type-II errors are relatively important. It is worthwhile to compare our result with that of Kobayashi (1992). Kobayashi considers a complete-information game of plea bargaining with two co-defendants. His setup assumes that it is well-known that the defendants are guilty. Therefore, the prosecutor's objective is specified as maximizing the sum of the expected penalties (or, equivalently, minimizing the sum of expected discounts or aggregate rewards offered in plea-bargain discounts rela- tive to otherwise expected punishment). Kobayashi obtains the counterintuitive result that a more culpable defendant may receive a more lenient penalty, which is intuitively unfair. Such unfair outcomes may occur, for example, when a more culpable defendant (Defendant 1) believes that less culpable Defendant 2 is unlikely to accept his respective offer, while Defendant 2 believes that Defendant 1 is highly likely to accept his respective offer. In this case, Defendant 1 is more likely to reject the offer of the antitrust authority than Defendant 2. Thus, the authority is forced to make a more attractive offer to Defendant 1 to induce him to self-report by accepting its respective offer, implying that the fine offered to Defendant 1 can|in theory|be lower than the fine offered to Defendant 2 (who is less culpable) in equilibrium. This unsettling possibility of the less culpable defendant receiving a more se- vere penalty follows from Kobayashi's assumption that each defendant's belief regarding the other's acceptance decision is exogenously given. However, if the beliefs are required to sat- isfy the consistency condition so as to be consistent with defendants' equilibrium strategies, then Kobayashi's unfair plea bargains cannot occur in equilibrium. Another difference between Kobayashi's model and ours is the meaning of \more culpa- ble." In our model, we define one defendant as being more culpable if he deserves a larger penalty than the other.
Recommended publications
  • Equilibrium Refinements
    Equilibrium Refinements Mihai Manea MIT Sequential Equilibrium I In many games information is imperfect and the only subgame is the original game. subgame perfect equilibrium = Nash equilibrium I Play starting at an information set can be analyzed as a separate subgame if we specify players’ beliefs about at which node they are. I Based on the beliefs, we can test whether continuation strategies form a Nash equilibrium. I Sequential equilibrium (Kreps and Wilson 1982): way to derive plausible beliefs at every information set. Mihai Manea (MIT) Equilibrium Refinements April 13, 2016 2 / 38 An Example with Incomplete Information Spence’s (1973) job market signaling game I The worker knows her ability (productivity) and chooses a level of education. I Education is more costly for low ability types. I Firm observes the worker’s education, but not her ability. I The firm decides what wage to offer her. In the spirit of subgame perfection, the optimal wage should depend on the firm’s beliefs about the worker’s ability given the observed education. An equilibrium needs to specify contingent actions and beliefs. Beliefs should follow Bayes’ rule on the equilibrium path. What about off-path beliefs? Mihai Manea (MIT) Equilibrium Refinements April 13, 2016 3 / 38 An Example with Imperfect Information Courtesy of The MIT Press. Used with permission. Figure: (L; A) is a subgame perfect equilibrium. Is it plausible that 2 plays A? Mihai Manea (MIT) Equilibrium Refinements April 13, 2016 4 / 38 Assessments and Sequential Rationality Focus on extensive-form games of perfect recall with finitely many nodes. An assessment is a pair (σ; µ) I σ: (behavior) strategy profile I µ = (µ(h) 2 ∆(h))h2H: system of beliefs ui(σjh; µ(h)): i’s payoff when play begins at a node in h randomly selected according to µ(h), and subsequent play specified by σ.
    [Show full text]
  • Recent Advances in Understanding Competitive Markets
    Recent Advances in Understanding Competitive Markets Chris Shannon Department of Economics University of California, Berkeley March 4, 2002 1 Introduction The Arrow-Debreu model of competitive markets has proven to be a remark- ably rich and °exible foundation for studying an array of important economic problems, ranging from social security reform to the determinants of long-run growth. Central to the study of such questions are many of the extensions and modi¯cations of the classic Arrow-Debreu framework that have been ad- vanced over the last 40 years. These include dynamic models of exchange over time, as in overlapping generations or continuous time, and under un- certainty, as in incomplete ¯nancial markets. Many of the most interesting and important recent advances have been spurred by questions about the role of markets in allocating resources and providing opportunities for risk- sharing arising in ¯nance and macroeconomics. This article is intended to give an overview of some of these more recent developments in theoretical work involving competitive markets, and highlight some promising areas for future work. I focus on three broad topics. The ¯rst is the role of asymmetric informa- tion in competitive markets. Classic work in information economics suggests that competitive markets break down in the face of informational asymme- 0 tries. Recently these issues have been reinvestigated from the vantage point of more general models of the market structure, resulting in some surpris- ing results overturning these conclusions and clarifying the conditions under which perfectly competitive markets can incorporate informational asymme- tries. The second concentrates on the testable implications of competitive markets.
    [Show full text]
  • Political Game Theory Nolan Mccarty Adam Meirowitz
    Political Game Theory Nolan McCarty Adam Meirowitz To Liz, Janis, Lachlan, and Delaney. Contents Acknowledgements vii Chapter 1. Introduction 1 1. Organization of the Book 2 Chapter 2. The Theory of Choice 5 1. Finite Sets of Actions and Outcomes 6 2. Continuous Outcome Spaces* 10 3. Utility Theory 17 4. Utility representations on Continuous Outcome Spaces* 18 5. Spatial Preferences 19 6. Exercises 21 Chapter 3. Choice Under Uncertainty 23 1. TheFiniteCase 23 2. Risk Preferences 32 3. Learning 37 4. Critiques of Expected Utility Theory 41 5. Time Preferences 46 6. Exercises 50 Chapter 4. Social Choice Theory 53 1. The Open Search 53 2. Preference Aggregation Rules 55 3. Collective Choice 61 4. Manipulation of Choice Functions 66 5. Exercises 69 Chapter 5. Games in the Normal Form 71 1. The Normal Form 73 2. Solutions to Normal Form Games 76 3. Application: The Hotelling Model of Political Competition 83 4. Existence of Nash Equilibria 86 5. Pure Strategy Nash Equilibria in Non-Finite Games* 93 6. Application: Interest Group Contributions 95 7. Application: International Externalities 96 iii iv CONTENTS 8. Computing Equilibria with Constrained Optimization* 97 9. Proving the Existence of Nash Equilibria** 98 10. Strategic Complementarity 102 11. Supermodularity and Monotone Comparative Statics* 103 12. Refining Nash Equilibria 108 13. Application: Private Provision of Public Goods 109 14. Exercises 113 Chapter 6. Bayesian Games in the Normal Form 115 1. Formal Definitions 117 2. Application: Trade restrictions 119 3. Application: Jury Voting 121 4. Application: Jury Voting with a Continuum of Signals* 123 5. Application: Public Goods and Incomplete Information 126 6.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium (PBE)
    1 Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium (PBE) The …nal type of game that we will discuss is one that is dynamic (or sequential) and where players have imperfect information. Recall that a game of perfect information is a game like Chess or Checkers – all players know exactly where they are at every point in the game. When drawing out the game tree for games of perfect information, each information set contained a single decision node. Now, however, we allow for the possibility that some (or all) players do not know which node they are at, so that an information set may contain multiple decision nodes. This basic structure captures many types of card games, such as Bridge, Spades, and Poker, in which one player does not know what cards the other player(s) is holding. When playing games of this type people often use both the knowledge of the entire game as well as the actions that have previously occurred in the game to update their beliefs about which node in the information set they are at. 1.1 De…nition and structure of a PBE With a PBE we will still require that all players choose strategies that are best responses to the other player’sstrategies. However, when there is a player who has multiple decision nodes within an information set we now require that this player speci…es a belief about which node in the information set he is at. The belief is simply a probability. Note that these probabilities (or beliefs) must follow the laws of probability – no probabilities greater than 1 or less than zero, and the probabilities for all decision nodes within an information set must sum to 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Perfect Bidder Collusion Through Bribe and Request*
    Perfect bidder collusion through bribe and request* Jingfeng Lu† Zongwei Lu ‡ Christian Riis§ May 31, 2021 Abstract We study collusion in a second-price auction with two bidders in a dy- namic environment. One bidder can make a take-it-or-leave-it collusion pro- posal, which consists of both an offer and a request of bribes, to the opponent. We show that there always exists a robust equilibrium in which the collusion success probability is one. In the equilibrium, for each type of initiator the expected payoff is generally higher than the counterpart in any robust equi- libria of the single-option model (Eso¨ and Schummer(2004)) and any other separating equilibria in our model. Keywords: second-price auction, collusion, multidimensional signaling, bribe JEL codes: D44, D82 arXiv:1912.03607v2 [econ.TH] 28 May 2021 *We are grateful to the editors in charge and an anonymous reviewer for their insightful comments and suggestions, which greatly improved the quality of our paper. Any remaining errors are our own. †Department of Economics, National University of Singapore. Email: [email protected]. ‡School of Economics, Shandong University. Email: [email protected]. §Department of Economics, BI Norwegian Business School. Email: [email protected]. 1 1 Introduction Under standard assumptions, auctions are a simple yet effective economic insti- tution that allows the owner of a scarce resource to extract economic rents from buyers. Collusion among bidders, on the other hand, can ruin the rents and hence should be one of the main issues that are always kept in the minds of auction de- signers with a revenue-maximizing objective.
    [Show full text]
  • Signalling Games Select Horn Strategies
    ROBERT VAN ROOY SIGNALLING GAMES SELECT HORN STRATEGIES ABSTRACT. In this paper I will discuss why (un) marked expressions typically get an (un)marked interpretation: Horn’s division of pragmatic labor. It is argued that it is a con- ventional fact that we use language this way. This convention will be explained in terms of the equilibria of signalling games introduced by Lewis (1969), but now in an evolutionary setting. I will also relate this signalling game analysis with Parikh’s (1991, 2000, 2001) game-theoretical analysis of successful communication, which in turn is compared with Blutner’s: 2000) bi-directional optimality theory. 1. INTRODUCTION Yesterday, Paul came into my office and told me ‘Miss X produced a series of sounds that corresponds closely with the score of “Home Sweet Home” ’. Paul intended to communicate something to me and he suc- ceeded: I understood that Paul wanted to tell me that Miss X’s performance suffered from some hideous defect. How can this be explained? The above example is just one instance of a general rule that says that (un)marked expressions typically get an (un)marked interpretation. Many other examples are discussed in Horn (1984) and the rule has come to be known as Horn’s division of pragmatic labor. Sometimes I will also denote this rule by Horn’s rule or the Horn strategy. Grice (1975) appeals to his maxim of manner to explain the example I started out with. He also suggests that this maxim, just like the other ones, should be derivable from general principles of rationality.
    [Show full text]
  • Dynamic Bayesian Games
    Preliminary Concepts Sequential Equilibrium Signaling Game Application: The Spence Model Application: Cheap Talk Introduction to Game Theory Lecture 8: Dynamic Bayesian Games Haifeng Huang University of California, Merced Shanghai, Summer 2011 Preliminary Concepts Sequential Equilibrium Signaling Game Application: The Spence Model Application: Cheap Talk Basic terminology • Now we study dynamic Bayesian games, or dynamic/extensive games of incomplete information, as opposed to the static (simultaneous-move) games of incomplete information in the last lecture note. • Incomplte information: a player does not know another player's characteristics (in particular, preferences); imperfect information: a player does not know what actions another player has taken. • Recall that in a dynamic game of perfect information, each player is perfectly informed of the history of what has happened so far, up to the point where it is her turn to move. Preliminary Concepts Sequential Equilibrium Signaling Game Application: The Spence Model Application: Cheap Talk Harsanyi Transformation • Following Harsanyi (1967), we can change a dynamic game of incomeplete information into a dynamic game of imperfect information, by making nature as a mover in the game. In such a game, nature chooses player i's type, but another player j is not perfectly informed about this choice. • But first, let's look at a dynamic game of complete but imperfect information. Preliminary Concepts Sequential Equilibrium Signaling Game Application: The Spence Model Application: Cheap Talk A dynamic game of complete but imperfect information • An entry game: the challenger may stay out, prepare for combat and enter (ready), or enter without making preparations (unready). Each player's preferences are common knowledge.
    [Show full text]
  • Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium When Players Move Sequentially and Have Private Infor- Mation, Some of the Bayesian Nash Equilibria
    Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium When players move sequentially and have private infor- mation, some of the Bayesian Nash equilibria may involve strategies that are not sequentially rational. The problem is that there are usually no proper subgames. That means that all BNE are subgame perfect. We need to modify the idea of subgame perfection so that we are able to evaluate sequential rationality at all information sets. The following version of the Gift Game is a good illustra- tion. Here, player 2 prefers the gift to be coming from a friend, but she would rather accept a gift from an enemy than to refuse the gift. For this game, (NF NE,R) is a BNE. Since there are no proper subgames, this is subgame perfect. Notice that it is clearly irrational for player 2 to refuse a gift, because her payoff from accepting is always greater than her payoff from refusing. This strategy profile is not ruled out as a subgame per- fect NE, because player 2’s information set does start a subgame, and switching to A in the full game does not improve her payoff, since her information set is not reached. But how to reject this equilibrium? The concept of Per- fect Bayesian Equilibrium (PBE) addresses this problem. A PBE combines a strategy profile and conditional beliefs that players have about the other players’ types at every information set. This will allow us to evaluate sequen- tial rationality by computing the expected payoff of every continuation strategy at every information set. Conditional Beliefs about Other Players’ Types In Gift Game 2, player 2 has initial beliefs that player 1 is type F with probability p and type E with probability 1 p.
    [Show full text]
  • III Semi-Separating Equilibrium
    ECONS 424 – STRATEGY AND GAME THEORY HANDOUT ON PERFECT BAYESIAN EQUILIBRIUM- III Semi-Separating equilibrium Let us consider the following sequential game with incomplete information. Two players are playing the following super-simple poker game. The first player gets his cards, and obviously he is the only one who can observe them. He can either get a High hand or a Low hand, with equal probabilities. After observing his hand, he must decide whether to Bet (let us imagine that he is betting a fixed amount of a dollar), or Resign from the game. If he resigns, both when he has a High and a Low hand, his payoff is zero, and player 2 gets a dollar. If he bets, player 2 must decide whether to Call or Fold from the game. Obviously, player makes his choice without being able to observe player 1’s hands, but only observing that player 1 Bets. 2, ‐1 Call Resign Player 1 Bet 0, 1 μ Fold High Hand ½ 1, 0 Nature Player 2 Low Hand ½ ‐1, 2 Call 1 ‐ μ 0, 1 ResignPlayer 1 Bet Fold 1, 0 1 1. Separating PBE where player 1 Bets when having a High hand, and Resigns when having a Low hand: (Bet, Resign) – Reasonable! 2, ‐1 Call Resign Player 1 Bet 0, 1 μ Fold High Hand ½ 1, 0 Nature Player 2 Low Hand ½ ‐1, 2 Call 1 ‐ μ 0, 1 ResignPlayer 1 Bet Fold 1, 0 a) Player 2’s beliefs (responder beliefs) in this separating PBE After observing Bet, μ=1, intuitively indicating that P2 believes that a Bet can only originate from a P1 with a High hand.
    [Show full text]
  • Final Exam—Suggested Answers
    E201B: Final Exam—Suggested Answers David Rahman, UCLA∗,† Winter, 2003 Sequential Equilibrium and Signalling We have the following game in extensive form. E2 1 − x, a P1 1I H1 0, 0 PP r PPP r r r N2 −x, 0 1 p 2 p p r p N 2 p p p b1 p p 2 p E 1 − y, b p 2 p 0, 0 pPP r P1 1D H1 p PPP r r rp N2 −y, 0 r We are given the following parametric restrictions: y > x > 0, 1 > x, and a > 0. (a) For what parameter values is there a sequential equilibrium where both types play P ? For both incarnations of player 1 to play P , player 2 must play N for sure, otherwise player 1I would want to play H. For player 2 to rationally play N he must believe that β = P (I|H) is sufficiently low and b ≤ 0, otherwise N is strictly dominated. Any β is consistent, and, since player 2’s information set is off the equilibrium path, N is immediately sequentially rational. ∗Please send any comments to [email protected]. †Copyright (C) 2003, David Rahman. This document is an open textbook; you can redistribute it and/or modify it under the terms of version 1 of the open text license amendment to version 2 of the GNU General Public License. The open text license amendment is published by Michele Boldrin et al at http://www.dklevine.com/general/gpl.html; the GPL is published by the Free Software Foundation at http://www.gnu.org/copyleft/gpl.html.
    [Show full text]
  • Infodynamics: a Naturalistic Psychosemantics
    City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works All Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects 9-2018 Infodynamics: A Naturalistic Psychosemantics Daniel E. Weissglass The Graduate Center, City University of New York How does access to this work benefit ou?y Let us know! More information about this work at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu/gc_etds/2920 Discover additional works at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu This work is made publicly available by the City University of New York (CUNY). Contact: [email protected] INFODYNAMICS: A NATURALISTIC PSYCHOSEMANTICS by D.E.WEISSGLASS A dissertation submitted to the Graduate Faculty in Philosophy in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, The City University of New York 2018 © 2018 D.E.WEISSGLASS All Rights Reserved ii Infodynamics: A naturalistic psychosemantics by D.E. Weissglass This manuscript has been read and accepted for the Graduate Faculty in Philosophy in satisfaction of the dissertation requirement for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Barbara Montero Date Chair of Examining Committee Nickolas Pappas Date Executive Officer Supervisory Committee: Jesse Prinz Barbara Montero David Papineau THE CITY UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK iii ABSTRACT Infodynamics: A naturalistic psychosemantics by D.E. Weissglass Advisor: Jesse Prinz When we think, we typically think ‘about’ something, a peculiar property of mental states often called ‘intentionality’. My dissertation is a collection of papers addressing key questions about the nature of intentionality. These questions demand answers because intentionality is poorly understood, yet fundamental to the way we talk and think about the mind in both folk and scientific contexts.
    [Show full text]
  • PSCI552 - Formal Theory (Graduate) Lecture Notes
    PSCI552 - Formal Theory (Graduate) Lecture Notes Dr. Jason S. Davis Spring 2020 Contents 1 Preliminaries 4 1.1 What is the role of theory in the social sciences? . .4 1.2 So why formalize that theory? And why take this course? . .4 2 Proofs 5 2.1 Introduction . .5 2.2 Logic . .5 2.3 What are we proving? . .6 2.4 Different proof strategies . .7 2.4.1 Direct . .7 2.4.2 Indirect/contradiction . .7 2.4.3 Induction . .8 3 Decision Theory 9 3.1 Preference Relations and Rationality . .9 3.2 Imposing Structure on Preferences . 11 3.3 Utility Functions . 13 3.4 Uncertainty, Expected Utility . 14 3.5 The Many Faces of Decreasing Returns . 15 3.5.1 Miscellaneous stuff . 17 3.6 Optimization . 17 3.7 Comparative Statics . 18 4 Game Theory 22 4.1 Preliminaries . 22 4.2 Static games of complete information . 23 4.3 The Concept of the Solution Concept . 24 4.3.1 Quick side note: Weak Dominance . 27 4.3.2 Quick side note: Weak Dominance . 27 4.4 Evaluating Outcomes/Normative Theory . 27 4.5 Best Response Correspondences . 28 4.6 Nash Equilibrium . 28 4.7 Mixed Strategies . 31 4.8 Extensive Form Games . 36 4.8.1 Introduction . 36 4.8.2 Imperfect Information . 39 4.8.3 Subgame Perfection . 40 4.8.4 Example Questions . 43 4.9 Static Games of Incomplete Information . 45 4.9.1 Learning . 45 4.9.2 Bayesian Nash Equilibrium . 46 4.10 Dynamic Games with Incomplete Information . 50 4.10.1 Perfect Bayesian Nash Equilibrium .
    [Show full text]