Foundations of Algebra

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Foundations of Algebra Foundations of algebra The well-ordering principle In mathematics, a well-order relation (or well-ordering) on a set S is a total order on S with the property that every non-empty subset of S has a least element in this ordering. Equivalently, a well-ordering is a well-founded total order. The set S together with the well-order relation is then called a well-ordered set. Every element, except a possible greatest element, has a unique successor (next element). Every subset which has an upper bound has a least upper bound. There may be elements (besides the least element) which have no predecessor. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Well-order The Well-Ordering Principle for the Naturals (N) is straightforward: Every non-empty subset of the natural numbers has a least element [i.e. the natural numbers are a well-ordered set]. This appears to be common sense; N itself has a least element (0 or 1, depending on text), and of course any subset we examine (the set 4, 5, 6, 7, 8, 9, 10 , the set of primes, the set of odd natural numbers, etc.) will of course have a least{ element. There are} a few interesting things about the Well-Ordering Principle, however: The assumption behind it Saying that a set has a “least element” assumes that there’s some sort of meaningful way of ordering the numbers on that set so that one is clearly less than another. For the naturals, the binary relation fulfills that role (and you can follow the Wiki link to a definition of “total order”). ≤ It’s not always clear cut how to order a set in general, however, even a set of numbers. Imagine the set of ordered pairs (1, 3), (3, 1), (1, 2), (2, 2) . How would you order the pairs themselves? Does (1, 3) come before (3, 1)?{ How about (1, 2)? } No, we’re not going to address that here - just something to think about. “Order” doesn’t just happen naturally - it’s a relation that has to be defined on a set. Name confusion You’d think that something as straightforward as the above would be impossible to botch up, but hey, it’s math. If you start searching a little on the term “well-ordering,” you’ll run into the following well-ordering axiom: Every set can be well-ordered. That’s a pretty strong statement. It’s equivalent to something known as the Axiom of Choice,and that’s one of those historical math controversies that’s been flying around for a while. The Axiom of Choice is to set theory as Euclid’s Fifth (Parallel) Postulate is to geometry - it seems obvious, but you can’t prove the thing, and it has to be taken as an axiom. Replacing it with a different axiom gives you a new system that seems counterintuitive, but is internally consistent. Ditching Euclid’s Fifth gets you some interesting non-Euclidean geometries. Ditching the Axiom of Choice gives you some interesting alternative set theory. We are NOT pursuing any non-Axiom-of-Choice algebra! But if you’re into that sort of thing, follow the links for a while :) Principle of Induction The Well-Ordering Principle on the Naturals (going back to the initial statement) is equivalent to the Principle of Induction - assume one, and you can prove the other. The Principle of Induction is the fifth Peano axiom, and will get a section of its own, coming up next. Generalization of the Well-Ordering Principle We won’t leap right into the idea that every set can be well-ordered, but we would like to generalize the Well-Ordering Principle to other sets of numbers, in particular, the integers. We can’t say that every subset of the integers has a least element; for example the set ..., 3, 2, 1, 0, 1, 2, 3, 4 { − − − } is a subset of the integers, and clearly does not have a least element. Instead, we state the General Well-Ordering Principle: Suppose that n0 is an integer. Suppose that S is a non-empty subset of the integers, and that every element of S is greater than or equal to n0.ThenS has a smallest element. That simply says that any set of integers which is bounded below has a least element. So the example ..., 3, 2, 1, 0, 1, 2, 3, 4 { − − − } wouldn’t contradict the principle, since it isn’t bounded below in the first place. The General Well-Ordering Principle seems trivial, and circular to the point of uselessness: doesn’t it basically say that any set of integers with a least element has a least element? Well, not quite - it’s entirely possible that we know that a set of integers has the property that it’s bounded below (say, we know a rough lower bound for the set is that every element is greater than 10), but we don’t know precisely what’s in the set (we’re not sure if 10 is included, or maybe its least− element is really 9, or even +6). Simply knowing that there is a− lower bound, even with only a rough idea of where− it is, is enough to know that the set has some element which is its least element. So, not useless. Also, not trivial - once again, it’s something that needs to be asserted, and can’t be stated about all sets of numbers. Consider a set of real numbers: the open interval ( 1, 1). That set is bounded below (every element is greater than 1), but we can’t assert that it has− a least element - you can get arbitrarily close to 1. In the same− way that a well-ordering principle for the integers must be stated differently than− the well-ordering principle for the naturals, a well-ordering principle for the reals would have to be stated differently than the one for the integers. So don’t assume that any statements of well-ordering hold outside the set they specifically refer to..
Recommended publications
  • Scott Spaces and the Dcpo Category
    SCOTT SPACES AND THE DCPO CATEGORY JORDAN BROWN Abstract. Directed-complete partial orders (dcpo’s) arise often in the study of λ-calculus. Here we investigate certain properties of dcpo’s and the Scott spaces they induce. We introduce a new construction which allows for the canonical extension of a partial order to a dcpo and give a proof that the dcpo introduced by Zhao, Xi, and Chen is well-filtered. Contents 1. Introduction 1 2. General Definitions and the Finite Case 2 3. Connectedness of Scott Spaces 5 4. The Categorical Structure of DCPO 6 5. Suprema and the Waybelow Relation 7 6. Hofmann-Mislove Theorem 9 7. Ordinal-Based DCPOs 11 8. Acknowledgments 13 References 13 1. Introduction Directed-complete partially ordered sets (dcpo’s) often arise in the study of λ-calculus. Namely, they are often used to construct models for λ theories. There are several versions of the λ-calculus, all of which attempt to describe the ‘computable’ functions. The first robust descriptions of λ-calculus appeared around the same time as the definition of Turing machines, and Turing’s paper introducing computing machines includes a proof that his computable functions are precisely the λ-definable ones [5] [8]. Though we do not address the λ-calculus directly here, an exposition of certain λ theories and the construction of Scott space models for them can be found in [1]. In these models, computable functions correspond to continuous functions with respect to the Scott topology. It is thus with an eye to the application of topological tools in the study of computability that we investigate the Scott topology.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Elementary Set Theory
    1 Elementary Set Theory Notation: fg enclose a set. f1; 2; 3g = f3; 2; 2; 1; 3g because a set is not defined by order or multiplicity. f0; 2; 4;:::g = fxjx is an even natural numberg because two ways of writing a set are equivalent. ; is the empty set. x 2 A denotes x is an element of A. N = f0; 1; 2;:::g are the natural numbers. Z = f:::; −2; −1; 0; 1; 2;:::g are the integers. m Q = f n jm; n 2 Z and n 6= 0g are the rational numbers. R are the real numbers. Axiom 1.1. Axiom of Extensionality Let A; B be sets. If (8x)x 2 A iff x 2 B then A = B. Definition 1.1 (Subset). Let A; B be sets. Then A is a subset of B, written A ⊆ B iff (8x) if x 2 A then x 2 B. Theorem 1.1. If A ⊆ B and B ⊆ A then A = B. Proof. Let x be arbitrary. Because A ⊆ B if x 2 A then x 2 B Because B ⊆ A if x 2 B then x 2 A Hence, x 2 A iff x 2 B, thus A = B. Definition 1.2 (Union). Let A; B be sets. The Union A [ B of A and B is defined by x 2 A [ B if x 2 A or x 2 B. Theorem 1.2. A [ (B [ C) = (A [ B) [ C Proof. Let x be arbitrary. x 2 A [ (B [ C) iff x 2 A or x 2 B [ C iff x 2 A or (x 2 B or x 2 C) iff x 2 A or x 2 B or x 2 C iff (x 2 A or x 2 B) or x 2 C iff x 2 A [ B or x 2 C iff x 2 (A [ B) [ C Definition 1.3 (Intersection).
    [Show full text]
  • Section 8.6 What Is a Partial Order?
    Announcements ICS 6B } Regrades for Quiz #3 and Homeworks #4 & Boolean Algebra & Logic 5 are due Today Lecture Notes for Summer Quarter, 2008 Michele Rousseau Set 8 – Ch. 8.6, 11.6 Lecture Set 8 - Chpts 8.6, 11.1 2 Today’s Lecture } Chapter 8 8.6, Chapter 11 11.1 ● Partial Orderings 8.6 Chapter 8: Section 8.6 ● Boolean Functions 11.1 Partial Orderings (Continued) Lecture Set 8 - Chpts 8.6, 11.1 3 What is a Partial Order? Some more defintions Let R be a relation on A. The R is a partial order iff R is: } If A,R is a poset and a,b are A, reflexive, antisymmetric, & transitive we say that: } A,R is called a partially ordered set or “poset” ● “a and b are comparable” if ab or ba } Notation: ◘ i.e. if a,bR and b,aR ● If A, R is a poset and a and b are 2 elements of A ● “a and b are incomparable” if neither ab nor ba such that a,bR, we write a b instead of aRb ◘ i.e if a,bR and b,aR } If two objects are always related in a poset it is called a total order, linear order or simple order. NOTE: it is not required that two things be related under a partial order. ● In this case A,R is called a chain. ● i.e if any two elements of A are comparable ● That’s the “partial” of it. ● So for all a,b A, it is true that a,bR or b,aR 5 Lecture Set 8 - Chpts 8.6, 11.1 6 1 Now onto more examples… More Examples Let Aa,b,c,d and let R be the relation Let A0,1,2,3 and on A represented by the diagraph Let R0,01,1, 2,0,2,2,2,33,3 The R is reflexive, but We draw the associated digraph: a b not antisymmetric a,c &c,a It is easy to check that R is 0 and not 1 c d transitive d,cc,a, but not d,a Refl.
    [Show full text]
  • [Math.NT] 1 Nov 2006
    ADJOINING IDENTITIES AND ZEROS TO SEMIGROUPS MELVYN B. NATHANSON Abstract. This note shows how iteration of the standard process of adjoining identities and zeros to semigroups gives rise naturally to the lexicographical ordering on the additive semigroups of n-tuples of nonnegative integers and n-tuples of integers. 1. Semigroups with identities and zeros A binary operation ∗ on a set S is associative if (a ∗ b) ∗ c = a ∗ (b ∗ c) for all a,b,c ∈ S. A semigroup is a nonempty set with an associative binary operation ∗. The semigroup is abelian if a ∗ b = b ∗ a for all a,b ∈ S. The trivial semigroup S0 consists of a single element s0 such that s0 ∗ s0 = s0. Theorems about abstract semigroups are, in a sense, theorems about the pure process of multiplication. An element u in a semigroup S is an identity if u ∗ a = a ∗ u = a for all a ∈ S. If u and u′ are identities in a semigroup, then u = u ∗ u′ = u′ and so a semigroup contains at most one identity. A semigroup with an identity is called a monoid. If S is a semigroup that is not a monoid, that is, if S does not contain an identity element, there is a simple process to adjoin an identity to S. Let u be an element not in S and let I(S,u)= S ∪{u}. We extend the binary operation ∗ from S to I(S,u) by defining u ∗ a = a ∗ u = a for all a ∈ S, and u ∗ u = u. Then I(S,u) is a monoid with identity u.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 1 Logic and Set Theory
    Chapter 1 Logic and Set Theory To criticize mathematics for its abstraction is to miss the point entirely. Abstraction is what makes mathematics work. If you concentrate too closely on too limited an application of a mathematical idea, you rob the mathematician of his most important tools: analogy, generality, and simplicity. – Ian Stewart Does God play dice? The mathematics of chaos In mathematics, a proof is a demonstration that, assuming certain axioms, some statement is necessarily true. That is, a proof is a logical argument, not an empir- ical one. One must demonstrate that a proposition is true in all cases before it is considered a theorem of mathematics. An unproven proposition for which there is some sort of empirical evidence is known as a conjecture. Mathematical logic is the framework upon which rigorous proofs are built. It is the study of the principles and criteria of valid inference and demonstrations. Logicians have analyzed set theory in great details, formulating a collection of axioms that affords a broad enough and strong enough foundation to mathematical reasoning. The standard form of axiomatic set theory is denoted ZFC and it consists of the Zermelo-Fraenkel (ZF) axioms combined with the axiom of choice (C). Each of the axioms included in this theory expresses a property of sets that is widely accepted by mathematicians. It is unfortunately true that careless use of set theory can lead to contradictions. Avoiding such contradictions was one of the original motivations for the axiomatization of set theory. 1 2 CHAPTER 1. LOGIC AND SET THEORY A rigorous analysis of set theory belongs to the foundations of mathematics and mathematical logic.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1811.03543V1 [Math.LO]
    PREDICATIVE WELL-ORDERING NIK WEAVER Abstract. Confusion over the predicativist conception of well-ordering per- vades the literature and is responsible for widespread fundamental miscon- ceptions about the nature of predicative reasoning. This short note aims to explain the core fallacy, first noted in [9], and some of its consequences. 1. Predicativism Predicativism arose in the early 20th century as a response to the foundational crisis which resulted from the discovery of the classical paradoxes of naive set theory. It was initially developed in the writings of Poincar´e, Russell, and Weyl. Their central concern had to do with the avoidance of definitions they considered to be circular. Most importantly, they forbade any definition of a real number which involves quantification over all real numbers. This version of predicativism is sometimes called “predicativism given the nat- ural numbers” because there is no similar prohibition against defining a natural number by means of a condition which quantifies over all natural numbers. That is, one accepts N as being “already there” in some sense which is sufficient to void any danger of vicious circularity. In effect, predicativists of this type consider un- countable collections to be proper classes. On the other hand, they regard countable sets and constructions as unproblematic. 2. Second order arithmetic Second order arithmetic, in which one has distinct types of variables for natural numbers (a, b, ...) and for sets of natural numbers (A, B, ...), is thus a good setting for predicative reasoning — predicative given the natural numbers, but I will not keep repeating this. Here it becomes easier to frame the restriction mentioned above in terms of P(N), the power set of N, rather than in terms of R.
    [Show full text]
  • Formal Construction of a Set Theory in Coq
    Saarland University Faculty of Natural Sciences and Technology I Department of Computer Science Masters Thesis Formal Construction of a Set Theory in Coq submitted by Jonas Kaiser on November 23, 2012 Supervisor Prof. Dr. Gert Smolka Advisor Dr. Chad E. Brown Reviewers Prof. Dr. Gert Smolka Dr. Chad E. Brown Eidesstattliche Erklarung¨ Ich erklare¨ hiermit an Eides Statt, dass ich die vorliegende Arbeit selbststandig¨ verfasst und keine anderen als die angegebenen Quellen und Hilfsmittel verwendet habe. Statement in Lieu of an Oath I hereby confirm that I have written this thesis on my own and that I have not used any other media or materials than the ones referred to in this thesis. Einverstandniserkl¨ arung¨ Ich bin damit einverstanden, dass meine (bestandene) Arbeit in beiden Versionen in die Bibliothek der Informatik aufgenommen und damit vero¨ffentlicht wird. Declaration of Consent I agree to make both versions of my thesis (with a passing grade) accessible to the public by having them added to the library of the Computer Science Department. Saarbrucken,¨ (Datum/Date) (Unterschrift/Signature) iii Acknowledgements First of all I would like to express my sincerest gratitude towards my advisor, Chad Brown, who supported me throughout this work. His extensive knowledge and insights opened my eyes to the beauty of axiomatic set theory and foundational mathematics. We spent many hours discussing the minute details of the various constructions and he taught me the importance of mathematical rigour. Equally important was the support of my supervisor, Prof. Smolka, who first introduced me to the topic and was there whenever a question arose.
    [Show full text]
  • Learning Binary Relations and Total Orders
    Learning Binary Relations and Total Orders Sally A Goldman Ronald L Rivest Department of Computer Science MIT Lab oratory for Computer Science Washington University Cambridge MA St Louis MO rivesttheorylcsmitedu sgcswustledu Rob ert E Schapire ATT Bell Lab oratories Murray Hill NJ schapireresearchattcom Abstract We study the problem of learning a binary relation b etween two sets of ob jects or b etween a set and itself We represent a binary relation b etween a set of size n and a set of size m as an n m matrix of bits whose i j entry is if and only if the relation holds b etween the corresp onding elements of the twosetsWe present p olynomial prediction algorithms for learning binary relations in an extended online learning mo del where the examples are drawn by the learner by a helpful teacher by an adversary or according to a uniform probability distribution on the instance space In the rst part of this pap er we present results for the case that the matrix of the relation has at most k rowtyp es We present upp er and lower b ounds on the number of prediction mistakes any prediction algorithm makes when learning such a matrix under the extended online learning mo del Furthermore we describ e a technique that simplies the pro of of exp ected mistake b ounds against a randomly chosen query sequence In the second part of this pap er we consider the problem of learning a binary re lation that is a total order on a set We describ e a general technique using a fully p olynomial randomized approximation scheme fpras to implement a randomized
    [Show full text]
  • Order Relations and Functions
    Order Relations and Functions Problem Session Tonight 7:00PM – 7:50PM 380-380X Optional, but highly recommended! Recap from Last Time Relations ● A binary relation is a property that describes whether two objects are related in some way. ● Examples: ● Less-than: x < y ● Divisibility: x divides y evenly ● Friendship: x is a friend of y ● Tastiness: x is tastier than y ● Given binary relation R, we write aRb iff a is related to b by relation R. Order Relations “x is larger than y” “x is tastier than y” “x is faster than y” “x is a subset of y” “x divides y” “x is a part of y” Informally An order relation is a relation that ranks elements against one another. Do not use this definition in proofs! It's just an intuition! Properties of Order Relations x ≤ y Properties of Order Relations x ≤ y 1 ≤ 5 and 5 ≤ 8 Properties of Order Relations x ≤ y 1 ≤ 5 and 5 ≤ 8 1 ≤ 8 Properties of Order Relations x ≤ y 42 ≤ 99 and 99 ≤ 137 Properties of Order Relations x ≤ y 42 ≤ 99 and 99 ≤ 137 42 ≤ 137 Properties of Order Relations x ≤ y x ≤ y and y ≤ z Properties of Order Relations x ≤ y x ≤ y and y ≤ z x ≤ z Properties of Order Relations x ≤ y x ≤ y and y ≤ z x ≤ z Transitivity Properties of Order Relations x ≤ y Properties of Order Relations x ≤ y 1 ≤ 1 Properties of Order Relations x ≤ y 42 ≤ 42 Properties of Order Relations x ≤ y 137 ≤ 137 Properties of Order Relations x ≤ y x ≤ x Properties of Order Relations x ≤ y x ≤ x Reflexivity Properties of Order Relations x ≤ y Properties of Order Relations x ≤ y 19 ≤ 21 Properties of Order Relations x ≤ y 19 ≤ 21 21 ≤ 19? Properties of Order Relations x ≤ y 19 ≤ 21 21 ≤ 19? Properties of Order Relations x ≤ y 42 ≤ 137 Properties of Order Relations x ≤ y 42 ≤ 137 137 ≤ 42? Properties of Order Relations x ≤ y 42 ≤ 137 137 ≤ 42? Properties of Order Relations x ≤ y 137 ≤ 137 Properties of Order Relations x ≤ y 137 ≤ 137 137 ≤ 137? Properties of Order Relations x ≤ y 137 ≤ 137 137 ≤ 137 Antisymmetry A binary relation R over a set A is called antisymmetric iff For any x ∈ A and y ∈ A, If xRy and y ≠ x, then yRx.
    [Show full text]
  • Mereology Then and Now
    Logic and Logical Philosophy Volume 24 (2015), 409–427 DOI: 10.12775/LLP.2015.024 Rafał Gruszczyński Achille C. Varzi MEREOLOGY THEN AND NOW Abstract. This paper offers a critical reconstruction of the motivations that led to the development of mereology as we know it today, along with a brief description of some questions that define current research in the field. Keywords: mereology; parthood; formal ontology; foundations of mathe- matics 1. Introduction Understood as a general theory of parts and wholes, mereology has a long history that can be traced back to the early days of philosophy. As a formal theory of the part-whole relation or rather, as a theory of the relations of part to whole and of part to part within a whole it is relatively recent and came to us mainly through the writings of Edmund Husserl and Stanisław Leśniewski. The former were part of a larger project aimed at the development of a general framework for formal ontology; the latter were inspired by a desire to provide a nominalistically acceptable alternative to set theory as a foundation for mathematics. (The name itself, ‘mereology’ after the Greek word ‘µρoς’, ‘part’ was coined by Leśniewski [31].) As it turns out, both sorts of motivation failed to quite live up to expectations. Yet mereology survived as a theory in its own right and continued to flourish, often in unexpected ways. Indeed, it is not an exaggeration to say that today mereology is a central and powerful area of research in philosophy and philosophical logic. It may be helpful, therefore, to take stock and reconsider its origins.
    [Show full text]
  • Frege and the Logic of Sense and Reference
    FREGE AND THE LOGIC OF SENSE AND REFERENCE Kevin C. Klement Routledge New York & London Published in 2002 by Routledge 29 West 35th Street New York, NY 10001 Published in Great Britain by Routledge 11 New Fetter Lane London EC4P 4EE Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper. Copyright © 2002 by Kevin C. Klement All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilized in any form or by any electronic, mechanical or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any infomration storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publisher. 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Klement, Kevin C., 1974– Frege and the logic of sense and reference / by Kevin Klement. p. cm — (Studies in philosophy) Includes bibliographical references and index ISBN 0-415-93790-6 1. Frege, Gottlob, 1848–1925. 2. Sense (Philosophy) 3. Reference (Philosophy) I. Title II. Studies in philosophy (New York, N. Y.) B3245.F24 K54 2001 12'.68'092—dc21 2001048169 Contents Page Preface ix Abbreviations xiii 1. The Need for a Logical Calculus for the Theory of Sinn and Bedeutung 3 Introduction 3 Frege’s Project: Logicism and the Notion of Begriffsschrift 4 The Theory of Sinn and Bedeutung 8 The Limitations of the Begriffsschrift 14 Filling the Gap 21 2. The Logic of the Grundgesetze 25 Logical Language and the Content of Logic 25 Functionality and Predication 28 Quantifiers and Gothic Letters 32 Roman Letters: An Alternative Notation for Generality 38 Value-Ranges and Extensions of Concepts 42 The Syntactic Rules of the Begriffsschrift 44 The Axiomatization of Frege’s System 49 Responses to the Paradox 56 v vi Contents 3.
    [Show full text]
  • Ordinal Numbers and the Well-Ordering Theorem Ken Brown, Cornell University, September 2013
    Mathematics 4530 Ordinal numbers and the well-ordering theorem Ken Brown, Cornell University, September 2013 The ordinal numbers form an extension of the natural numbers. Here are the first few of them: 0; 1; 2; : : : ; !; ! + 1;! + 2;:::;! + ! =: !2;!2 + 1;:::;!3;:::;!2;:::: They go on forever. As soon as some initial segment of ordinals has been con- structed, a new one is adjoined that is bigger than all of them. The theory of ordinals is closely related to the theory of well-ordered sets (see Section 10 of Munkres). Recall that a simply ordered set X is said to be well- ordered if every nonempty subset Y has a smallest element, i.e., an element y0 such that y0 ≤ y for all y 2 Y . For example, the following sets are well-ordered: ;; f1g ; f1; 2g ; f1; 2; : : : ; ng ; f1; 2;::: g ; f1; 2;:::;!g ; f1; 2; : : : ; !; ! + 1g : On the other hand, Z is not well-ordered in its natural ordering. As the list of examples suggests, constructing arbitrarily large well-ordered sets is essentially the same as constructing the system of ordinal numbers. Rather than taking the time to develop the theory of ordinals, we will concentrate on well-ordered sets in what follows. Notation. In dealing with ordered sets in what follows we will often use notation such as X<x := fy 2 X j y < xg : A set of the form X<x is called a section of X. Well-orderings are useful because they allow proofs by induction: Induction principle. Let X be a well-ordered set and let Y be a subset.
    [Show full text]