Two Traditions of Theorizing About Animal Minds

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Two Traditions of Theorizing About Animal Minds City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works All Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects 2-2020 Continuity as Crisis: Two Traditions of Theorizing about Animal Minds Adam See The Graduate Center, City University of New York How does access to this work benefit ou?y Let us know! More information about this work at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu/gc_etds/3527 Discover additional works at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu This work is made publicly available by the City University of New York (CUNY). Contact: [email protected] CONTINUITY AS CRISIS Two Traditions of Theorizing about Animal Minds by ADAM SEE A dissertation submitted to the Graduate Faculty in Philosophy in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. The City University of New York 2020 ii © 2019 Adam See All Rights Reserved iii Continuity as Crisis: Two Traditions of Theorizing about Animal Minds by Adam See This manuscript has been read and accepted for the Graduate Faculty in Philosophy in satisfaction of the dissertation requirement for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. __________________________ _____________________________ Date Catherine Wilson Chair of Examining Committee __________________________ _____________________________ Date John Greenwood Executive Officer Supervisory Committee: John Greenwood Philip Kitcher Peter Godfrey-Smith Catherine Wilson THE CITY UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK iv ABSTRACT Continuity as Crisis: Two Traditions of Theorizing about Animal Minds by Adam See Advisor: John Greenwood Contemporary philosophers and scientists remain largely resistant to attributing humanlike capacities to non-human animals, particularly great apes, for reasons that are not based on compelling empirical or theoretical grounds. Mental faculties such as reason, agency, and theory of mind are widely seen as differing in kind from functionally analogous abilities in other extant species. This dissertation appraises the current state of the animal minds literature by means of a critical genealogy charting the development of skepticism about animal cognition throughout the history of philosophy. In doing so, this project addresses the sedimentation of epistemic, linguistic, ontological, and methodological impasses that continue to shape debates over human uniqueness and limit comparative discussions of human and animal cognition. Since antiquity, discourse about animal minds has broadly followed two traditions, both of which are representative of positions in the recent philosophical and scientific literature. The dominant path has been to defend fundamental discontinuities between the human mind and the rest of the animal kingdom. I show how this tradition is bound up with common patterns of argumentation and evasive rhetoric that prejudge debates in comparative cognition in favor of discontinuity. Representative figures range from Aristotle, Descartes, and Wallace to modern primatologists such as Daniel Povinelli and Michael Tomasello. This tradition, I argue, is largely defined by the tenacity and v adaptability of “exceptionalism claims,” i.e., claims evoking a cognitive hierarchy in the animal kingdom. It has also been historically preoccupied with so-called “logical problems” suggesting, for example, that decades of experimental research on mindreading in chimpanzees cannot provide evidence for this ability even in principle. Revealing this problem’s underlying ontological, epistemic, and procedural assumptions explains why this tradition repeatedly fails to solve the problems it poses for itself, e.g., does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? In addition to this unhealthy skepticism, I show how the dominant tradition relies on a problematic form of rhetoric whereby animals are said to act “as if” possessing X (a presumably uniquely human faculty) but lack “genuine,” “true,” or “real” X, where X is defined at the highest level of human ability. This has long been, and remains, a common strategy used by discontinuity theorists in reaction to evidence of boundary-threatening abilities in animals. This rhetoric has tacitly encouraged antiquated “all or nothing” accounts of human mental faculties that have no place in the contemporary literature. The critical genealogy this dissertation develops is dialectical — the claims of the dominant tradition are continuously challenged by voices from within a marginalized tradition that take seriously the possibility of cognitive explanations of animal behavior. In illuminating this alternative tradition, my project brings together thinkers as diverse as Plutarch, Lucretius, Montaigne, La Mettrie, Hume, Darwin, Margaret Washburn and Kristin Andrews, who articulate and defend naturalistic approaches to cognition that do not presuppose a cognitive hierarchy with human abilities situated at the top. This tradition has been particularly sensitive to anthropocentric double standards in denying mental capacities to animals, and is home to the original defenders of “minimal” accounts vi of rationality. This project selectively draws from this marginalized tradition to promote a healthy skepticism toward animal cognition, culminating in a chapter undercutting the force of modern discontinuity arguments regarding the socio-cognitive capacities of humans and chimpanzees. vii Acknowledgements My deepest appreciation is owed to the efforts of John Greenwood. John encouraged this project from the beginning and was very helpful in narrowing its content. His immense knowledge of the history of psychology was an invaluable resource at every step. John’s presence at the helm was a constant sense of comfort to me. I looked forward to our meetings in the way that one looks forward to seeing a good friend. He was always affable, heartening, and constructive, and I feel privileged to have him as my advisor. Thank you, John. I am immensely grateful to Philip Kitcher, Peter Godfrey-Smith, and Catherine Wilson for acting on my committee. This project turned out to be much longer than anticipated, and the early stages were quite rocky for me. Philip, Peter, and Catherine: Thank you. Philip in particular has been a formative figure in my intellectual, moral, and professional development. Philip advised me during my Masters degree at Columbia, and I am very thankful that he signed onto this project. Philip was instrumental in helping me through some of my lowest points this past decade, which he always did with grace and compassion. It was Philip who turned me onto John Dewey, my favorite philosopher, and who changed the way I thought about philosophy. The structure of this dissertation owes much to Dewey, and in that way owes much to conversations with Philip that stretch back to 2009. More importantly, Philip encouraged my efforts to put Dewey’s ideas into extra- curricular action. I would not have joined the then-new Philosophy Outreach Program at Teacher’s College, and thus became enamored by the idea of teaching, were it not for Philip. Years later, I have fond memories of returning to Democracy and Education while planning and teaching my first courses at Brooklyn College. Philip was the first to impart viii upon me that teaching can be more significant and rewarding than research. Philip also inspires me a public intellectual. The last time I saw him he was giving a speech on climate change at the Brooklyn Public Library. That’s my kind of philosopher. Outside of academia my greatest supporter has been my girlfriend Caroline Macfarlane. She’s heard me struggle to explain this project hundreds of times, in various states of sobriety, over many years. Most importantly, Caroline was strong enough to provide encouragement and emotional support to me during the darkest year of her life, and I am forever grateful. Thank you Chilla. Mom and Dad, you should be at the top but if you knew John you’d understand. My parents, Myra and George See, have worked as hard or harder than anyone I’ve personally known. The stress they selflessly endure has been difficult for my family. My parents worked themselves up from nothing in rural Ontario, and they put me through three college degrees debt free, studying philosophy of all damn things, in New York City. And they never, ever made me feel a burden. It’s incredible, the faith they have in me, and the respect they’ve always shown to my projects and causes. I don’t know how to love anything more than I love my mom and dad. Nothing I’ve accomplished here is commensurate with what you accomplished to make it possible. A few words for Caitlin Hurst, my most meaningful friend and closest confidante on grad school drama since the beginning. She’s never read this thing, but she was there at every step, having a beer with me, talking about David Berman (RIP) lyrics, helping me to carry on. Thanks Pine. Cody Ross and Taylor Christoffel, my brothers in Otro Lado who’ve seen me in the ugly depths of it. Our band started around the time I began this dissertation. Making ix and performing music with you guys has opened up innumerable non-academic spaces in my life, helping me to complete this project in more ways than I can say. I can’t tell you how important it is for this philosopher to create and argue about music. I also want to acknowledge, in no particular order, the following lovely people. My close friend Jon Lawhead for introducing me to D&D (among other things), for being an inspiring teacher, and for being one of the best philosophers that I know; Jon always had my back and encouraged this project. Jeremy Forster for our deeply personal relationship, and for always being down to play NES till 4am and listen to The Clash. Chris Whalen for making NYC feel like home (those nights on Riverside looking out at the GWB listening to ATCQ were therapy), and for emotional support throughout writing this dissertation and in life generally. I owe thanks to Mateo Duque for helping me understand Aristotle (who I was more anxious to write about than anyone in the history of philosophy) and for being my best friend in my CUNY cohort.
Recommended publications
  • 'Introspectionism' and the Mythical Origins of Scientific Psychology
    Consciousness and Cognition Consciousness and Cognition 15 (2006) 634–654 www.elsevier.com/locate/concog ‘Introspectionism’ and the mythical origins of scientific psychology Alan Costall Department of Psychology, University of Portsmouth, Portsmouth, Hampshire PO1 2DY, UK Received 1 May 2006 Abstract According to the majority of the textbooks, the history of modern, scientific psychology can be tidily encapsulated in the following three stages. Scientific psychology began with a commitment to the study of mind, but based on the method of introspection. Watson rejected introspectionism as both unreliable and effete, and redefined psychology, instead, as the science of behaviour. The cognitive revolution, in turn, replaced the mind as the subject of study, and rejected both behaviourism and a reliance on introspection. This paper argues that all three stages of this history are largely mythical. Introspectionism was never a dominant movement within modern psychology, and the method of introspection never went away. Furthermore, this version of psychology’s history obscures some deep conceptual problems, not least surrounding the modern conception of ‘‘behaviour,’’ that continues to make the scientific study of consciousness seem so weird. Ó 2006 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. Keywords: Introspection; Introspectionism; Behaviourism; Dualism; Watson; Wundt 1. Introduction Probably the most immediate result of the acceptance of the behaviorist’s view will be the elimination of self-observation and of the introspective reports resulting from such a method. (Watson, 1913b, p. 428). The problem of consciousness occupies an analogous position for cognitive psychology as the prob- lem of language behavior does for behaviorism, namely, an unsolved anomaly within the domain of an approach.
    [Show full text]
  • Course Syllabus Animal Studies: an Introduction ANTH S-1625 Harvard Summer School 2016 Dr
    2016.6.10 draft Course Syllabus Animal Studies: An Introduction ANTH S-1625 Harvard Summer School 2016 Dr. Paul Waldau Course Description This course traces the history and shape of academic efforts to study nonhuman animals. Animal studies scholars explore such questions as, how do contemporary Western societies characterize the differences between humans and non-human animals? What ethical debates surround the use of animals in scientific research or the use of animals for food? How different are other cultures’ views of nonhuman animals from the views that now prevail in the United States and other early twenty-first century industrialized societies? What assumptions in educational systems have fostered the study of nonhuman animals, and what assumptions of specific educational systems have hampered such study? Class sessions are discussion-based, and students undertake group work, significant writing, and an individual presentation. In addition, note carefully each of the Learning Objectives listed below. We will discuss these objectives regularly through significant writing, group-based discussion and individual presentations that explore the interdisciplinary implications of weaving together the humanities with sciences (both social and natural). There are no prerequisites for this course. Required Readings and Course Materials • Waldau, Paul 2013. Animal Studies: An Introduction. New York: Oxford University Press • Additional Course Materials will be specified, and most of them will be available online or in .pdf format at the
    [Show full text]
  • Invented Herbal Tradition.Pdf
    Journal of Ethnopharmacology 247 (2020) 112254 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Journal of Ethnopharmacology journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/jethpharm Inventing a herbal tradition: The complex roots of the current popularity of T Epilobium angustifolium in Eastern Europe Renata Sõukanda, Giulia Mattaliaa, Valeria Kolosovaa,b, Nataliya Stryametsa, Julia Prakofjewaa, Olga Belichenkoa, Natalia Kuznetsovaa,b, Sabrina Minuzzia, Liisi Keedusc, Baiba Prūsed, ∗ Andra Simanovad, Aleksandra Ippolitovae, Raivo Kallef,g, a Ca’ Foscari University of Venice, Via Torino 155, 30172, Mestre, Venice, Italy b Institute for Linguistic Studies, Russian Academy of Sciences, Tuchkov pereulok 9, 199004, St Petersburg, Russia c Tallinn University, Narva rd 25, 10120, Tallinn, Estonia d Institute for Environmental Solutions, "Lidlauks”, Priekuļu parish, LV-4126, Priekuļu county, Latvia e A.M. Gorky Institute of World Literature of the Russian Academy of Sciences, 25a Povarskaya st, 121069, Moscow, Russia f Kuldvillane OÜ, Umbusi village, Põltsamaa parish, Jõgeva county, 48026, Estonia g University of Gastronomic Sciences, Piazza Vittorio Emanuele 9, 12042, Pollenzo, Bra, Cn, Italy ARTICLE INFO ABSTRACT Keywords: Ethnopharmacological relevance: Currently various scientific and popular sources provide a wide spectrum of Epilobium angustifolium ethnopharmacological information on many plants, yet the sources of that information, as well as the in- Ancient herbals formation itself, are often not clear, potentially resulting in the erroneous use of plants among lay people or even Eastern Europe in official medicine. Our field studies in seven countries on the Eastern edge of Europe have revealed anunusual source interpretation increase in the medicinal use of Epilobium angustifolium L., especially in Estonia, where the majority of uses were Ethnopharmacology specifically related to “men's problems”.
    [Show full text]
  • Insight from the Sociology of Science
    CHAPTER 7 INSIGHT FROM THE SOCIOLOGY OF SCIENCE Science is What Scientists Do It has been argued a number of times in previous chapters that empirical adequacy is insufficient, in itself, to establish the validity of a theory: consistency with the observable ‘facts’ does not mean that a theory is true,1 only that it might be true, along with other theories that may also correspond with the observational data. Moreover, empirical inadequacy (theories unable to account for all the ‘facts’ in their domain) is frequently ignored by individual scientists in their fight to establish a new theory or retain an existing one. It has also been argued that because experi- ments are conceived and conducted within a particular theoretical, procedural and instrumental framework, they cannot furnish the theory-free data needed to make empirically-based judgements about the superiority of one theory over another. What counts as relevant evidence is, in part, determined by the theoretical framework the evidence is intended to test. It follows that the rationality of science is rather different from the account we usually provide for students in school. Experiment and observation are not as decisive as we claim. Additional factors that may play a part in theory acceptance include the following: intuition, aesthetic considerations, similarity and consistency among theories, intellectual fashion, social and economic influences, status of the proposer(s), personal motives and opportunism. Although the evidence may be inconclusive, scientists’ intuitive feelings about the plausibility or aptness of particular ideas will make it appear convincing. The history of science includes many accounts of scientists ‘sticking to their guns’ concerning a well-loved theory in the teeth of evidence to the contrary, and some- times in the absence of any evidence at all.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter IV Book IV
    Book IV 1 WE have thus spoken of the generation of animals both generally and separately in all the different classes. But, since male and fe- male are distinct in the most perfect of them, and since we say that the sexes are first principles of all living things whether animals or plants, only in some of them the sexes are separated and in others not, therefore we must speak first of the origin of the sexes in the lat- ter. For while the animal is still imperfect in its kind the distinction is already made between male and female. It is disputed, however, whether the embryo is male or female, as the case may be, even before the distinction is plain to our senses, and further whether it is thus differentiated within the mother or even earlier. It is said by some, as by Anaxagoras and other of the physicists, that this antithesis exists from the beginning in the germs or seeds; for the germ, they say, comes from the male while the fe- male only provides the place in which it is to be developed, and the male is from the right, the female from the left testis, and so also that the male embryo is in the right of the uterus, the female in the left. Others, as Empedocles, say that the differentiation takes place in the uterus; for he says that if the uterus is hot or cold what en- ters it becomes male or female, the cause of the heat or cold being the flow of the catamenia, according as it is colder or hotter, more ‘antique’ or more ‘recent’.
    [Show full text]
  • The Joys and Burdens of Our Heroes 12/05/2021
    More Fun Than Fun: The Joys and Burdens of Our Heroes 12/05/2021 An iconic photo of Konrad Lorenz with his favourite geese. Photo: Willamette Biology, CC BY-SA 2.0 This article is part of the ‘More Fun Than Fun‘ column by Prof Raghavendra Gadagkar. He will explore interesting research papers or books and, while placing them in context, make them accessible to a wide readership. RAGHAVENDRA GADAGKAR Among the books I read as a teenager, two completely changed my life. One was The Double Helix by Nobel laureate James D. Watson. This book was inspiring at many levels and instantly got me addicted to molecular biology. The other was King Solomon’s Ring by Konrad Lorenz, soon to be a Nobel laureate. The study of animal behaviour so charmingly and unforgettably described by Lorenz kindled in me an eternal love for the subject. The circumstances in which I read these two books are etched in my mind and may have partly contributed to my enthusiasm for them and their subjects. The Double Helix was first published in London in 1968 when I was a pre-university student (equivalent to 11th grade) at St Joseph’s college in Bangalore and was planning to apply for the prestigious National Science Talent Search Scholarship. By then, I had heard of the discovery of the double-helical structure of DNA and its profound implications. I was also tickled that this momentous discovery was made in 1953, the year of my birth. I saw the announcement of Watson’s book on the notice board in the British Council Library, one of my frequent haunts.
    [Show full text]
  • Lucyna Kostuch Do Animals Have a Homeland
    H U M a N I M A L I A 9:1 Lucyna Kostuch Do animals have a homeland? Ancient Greeks on the cultural identity of animals The role of animals in ancient Greek culture has been discussed in a variety of contexts, — the relation between human and animal, the moral status of animals, animals in the works of naturalists, animals in tragedy, animals in art, zooarchaeological research. 1 In the literature of ancient Greece, animals are used to represent all things that do not belong to civil society or to the Greek community: slaves, women, and foreign peoples (barbaroi ). Symbolically, animals are often placed outside the country. 2 However, a close reading of texts by Greek authors leads to the conclusion that this is just one side of the coin. The Greeks attributed regional identity to animals, defined by the local geography, and by the history of a region enclosed by borders. At the same time, the world of animals seemed to be ethnically diversified, for the Hellenes coined the terms “Hellenic animal,” belonging to the Greek culture, and “barbaric animal,” belonging to a foreign culture. In this way, Greek animals became an inalienable part of the Hellenic “national” legacy. The Greeks imagined the human world and the world of animals as a world of common borders — there were “familiar” and “unfamiliar” animals at all levels of spatial division. This article, based primarily on literary sources, aims to answer the following questions: How did the ancient Greeks associate animals with space, geography, and their own settlements? Did they attribute nationality and territory to animals? Did they think animals missed their homelands? Could a foreign animal experience a process of cultural integration, namely Hellenization? Animals and Greek civilization .
    [Show full text]
  • What the Problem of Other Minds Really Tells Us About Descartes
    What the Problem of Other Minds Really Tells us about Descartes Gideon Manning The College of William and Mary Ever since the first generation Cartesian Gerauld de Cordemoy wrote a self- standing book dedicated to the problem of other minds philosophers have proceeded as though Descartes’ work entails some version of the problem.1 In this paper I evaluate Descartes’ own contribution to creating and answering skepticism about other minds. It is my contention, first, that for most of his working life Descartes did not see the problem as distinct from the problem of the external world. Second, that when he was finally presented with the problem in a late letter from Henry More, Descartes looked not to behavior, but to a body’s origins as a guide to who does and does not have a mind. Specifically, the response Descartes offers to More appeals to a shared “nature,” something which has struck many readers as an ineffectual response, even as a response which begs the question. On the contrary, and this is my third contention, Descartes’ response is a fairly plausible one when read as utilizing the meaning of “nature” as complexio found in Meditation Six.2 Though it may be translated as “complex,” complexio is really a technical Latin term coming from the medical tradition, likely introduced into the lexicon at Salerno in the tenth- or eleventh-century. It means, roughly, a unique composition of elements or qualities distinguishing species (and individual members of a species) from one another. By emphasizing our shared complexio Descartes is telling More that having resolved the problem of the external world we can rely on God’s uniform action in the world to entail joining a mind to members of our species.
    [Show full text]
  • The Neurobehavioral Nature of Fishes and the Question of Awareness and Pain
    Reprinted with permission from CRC Press. 2000 NW Corporate Blvd. Boca Raton, FL 33431, USA Tel: 1(800)272-7737 http://www.crcpress.com 2.1. Reviews in Fisheries Science, 10(1): 1–38 (2002) The Neurobehavioral Nature of Fishes and the Question of Awareness and Pain James D. Rose Department of Zoology and Physiology, University of Wyoming, Laramie, WY 82071 * Send correspondence to: Dr. James D. Rose, Department of Zoology and Physiology, University of Wyoming, Laramie, WY 82071. e-mail: [email protected] 1064-1262 /02/$.50 ©2002 by CRC Press LLC ABSTRACT: This review examines the neurobehavioral nature of fishes and addresses the question of whether fishes are capable of experiencing pain and suffering. The detrimental effects of anthropomorphic thinking and the importance of an evolutionary perspective for understanding the neurobehavioral differences between fishes and humans are discussed. The differences in central nervous system structure that underlie basic neurobehavioral differences between fishes and humans are described. The literature on the neural basis of consciousness and of pain is reviewed, showing that: (1) behavioral responses to noxious stimuli are separate from the psychological experience of pain, (2) awareness of pain in humans depends on functions of specific regions of cerebral cortex, and (3) fishes lack these essential brain regions or any functional equivalent, making it untenable that they can experience pain. Because the experience of fear, similar to pain, depends on cerebral cortical structures that are absent from fish brains, it is concluded that awareness of fear is impossible for fishes. Although it is implausible that fishes can experience pain or emotions, they display robust, nonconscious, neuroendocrine, and physiological stress responses to noxious stimuli.
    [Show full text]
  • (RECENT) EPISTEMOLOGY Christian Beyer Edmund Husserl's
    CHAPTER ONE HUSSERL’S TRANSCENDENTAL PHENOMENOLOGY CONSIDERED IN THE LIGHT OF (RECENT) EPISTEMOLOGY Christian Beyer Edmund Husserl’s transcendental phenomenology represents an epis- temological project which he sometimes refers to as “First Philosophy”. He also speaks of “Cartesian Meditations” and stresses that “the first philosophical act” is “the universal overthrow of all prior beliefs, however acquired” (Hua VIII, 23).1 This project aims at nothing less than a philo- sophical understanding of our whole view of the world and ourselves. I propose to investigate into this undertaking regarding both its method and content and to relate it, where useful, to more recent (analytic) epistemology. For Husserl, the task of First Philosophy is to philosophically explicate our access to, or being in, the world, i.e., the intentionality of our con- sciousness. By an intentional state of consciousness, an intentional (lived) experience, he understands a state of consciousness that has a subject matter which it is directed toward, so to speak (cp. the literal meaning of the Latin verb intendere); a state that is “as of ” something, represents something. It was Husserl’s teacher Franz Brentano who brought this notion to the attention of philosophers and psychologists. In his Psychol- ogy from an Empirical Standpoint he says: Every mental phenomenon is characterized by what the Scholastics of the Middle Ages called the intentional (or mental) inexistence of an object, and what we might call, though not wholly unambiguously, reference to a content, direction toward an object (which is not to be understood here as meaning a real thing [eine Realität]), or immanent objectivity.
    [Show full text]
  • 4​Th​ MINDING ANIMALS CONFERENCE CIUDAD DE
    th 4 ​ MINDING ANIMALS CONFERENCE ​ CIUDAD DE MÉXICO, 17 TO 24 JANUARY, 2018 SOCIAL PROGRAMME: ROYAL PEDREGAL HOTEL ACADEMIC PROGRAMME: NATIONAL AUTONOMOUS UNIVERSITY OF MEXICO Auditorio Alfonso Caso and Anexos de la Facultad de Derecho FINAL PROGRAMME (Online version linked to abstracts. Download PDF here) 1/47 All delegates please note: ​ 1. Presentation slots may have needed to be moved by the organisers, and may appear in a different place from that of the final printed programme. Please consult the schedule located in the Conference Programme upon arrival at the Conference for your presentation time. 2. Please note that presenters have to ensure the following times for presentation to allow for adequate time for questions from the floor and smooth transition of sessions. Delegates must not stray from their allocated 20 minutes. Further, delegates are welcome to move within sessions, therefore presenters MUST limit their talk to the allocated time. Therefore, Q&A will be AFTER each talk, and NOT at the end of the three presentations. Plenary and Invited Talks – 45 min. presentation and 15 min. discussion (Q&A). 3. For panels, each panellist must stick strictly to a 10 minute time frame, before discussion with the floor commences. 4. Note that co-authors may be presenting at the conference in place of, or with the main author. For all co-authors, delegates are advised to consult the Conference Abstracts link on the Minding Animals website. Use of the term et al is provided where there is more than two authors ​ ​ of an abstract. 5. Moderator notes will be available at all front desks in tutorial rooms, along with Time Sheets (5, 3 and 1 minute Left).
    [Show full text]
  • The Evolution of Human Mating: Trade-Offs and Strategic Pluralism
    BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (2000) 23, 573–644 Printed in the United States of America The evolution of human mating: Trade-offs and strategic pluralism Steven W. Gangestad Department of Psychology, University of New Mexico, Albuquerque, NM 87131 [email protected] Jeffry A. Simpson Department of Psychology, Texas A&M University, College Station, TX 77843 [email protected]. Abstract: During human evolutionary history, there were “trade-offs” between expending time and energy on child-rearing and mating, so both men and women evolved conditional mating strategies guided by cues signaling the circumstances. Many short-term matings might be successful for some men; others might try to find and keep a single mate, investing their effort in rearing her offspring. Recent evidence suggests that men with features signaling genetic benefits to offspring should be preferred by women as short-term mates, but there are trade-offs between a mate’s genetic fitness and his willingness to help in child-rearing. It is these circumstances and the cues that signal them that underlie the variation in short- and long-term mating strategies between and within the sexes. Keywords: conditional strategies; evolutionary psychology; fluctuating asymmetry; mating; reproductive strategies; sexual selection Research on interpersonal relationships, especially roman- attributes (e.g., physical attractiveness) tend to assume tic ones, has increased markedly in the last three decades greater importance in mating relationships than in other (see Berscheid & Reis 1998) across a variety of fields, in- types of relationships (Buss 1989; Gangestad & Buss 1993 cluding social psychology, anthropology, ethology, sociol- [see also Kenrick & Keefe: “Age Preferences in Mates Re- ogy, developmental psychology, and personology (Ber- flect Sex Differences in Human Reproductive Strategies” scheid 1994).
    [Show full text]