Communication

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Communication 0 DOCUMENT RESUME ED 114 877. CS 501 163 AUTHOR Berger, Charles R. TITLE The Covering Law Model in CoLemunication PUB DATE 75 NOTE 31p..; Paper prese.nted at the 4nnual Meeting of the Speech Commlinicati3On Association '(61St, Houstoh, December'7-30, 1975) EDRS PRICE MF-50.76.HC-$1.95.Plus Postage DESCRIPTOPS Behavior Theories; *Communication (Thought Tfansfer);' Educational Research; Educational Theories; *Models; *Speech; *TheOrieS IDENTIFIERS Communication Theories; *Covering Law Modelt I ABSTRACT The first Section of thii paper defines -covering law explanation as a theory which maintains that explanation may be achieved, and'may be achieved, by subsuming what is to beexplained under a general law. The modelis examined in light of the deductive-nomological explanation, the deductive-statistical explanation, and the inductive-st'atistical explanation. The second section of the paper examines the'feasibility of.covering law models and examines some criticism of the covering-law approach,'including Paws versus rules, cultural variation, and temporal,variation. Thee third section of the paper-examines potential barriers to theory construction and discusses irrelevant variety,, irrelevant change, realism versus nominalism, 'insensitivity to,embeddedness, and overemphasis on statistical techniques. It is concluded that, a ' defense Oof the covering law approach does not deny the_usefulness of the rule governed approach or the systems approach, and that the covering law approach probably does provide the most complete explanation of a phenomenon when the explanans are,true.- (TS) I ******************************************************************'*** DOcuments acquired.by,ERIC include many informal' unpublished * * materials.not available from other sources; ERIC makes every effort * ,* to obtain the best- copy available. Nevrtheles's; items of marginal * * reproddcibility, are ften encountered and this .affects the quality .* * of the,microfiche in# hardcopy reproductions EPIC makes available * pia the ERIC Docment ReprodqdtiOn Service (EDRS) .EDRS' is not 4 responsible for the quality of the original document. Reproductions * supplied by EDRS are the best that can 'be made from the original. 4 *****************14*******************)y******************************** U S OEPARTmENTOFHELi," EOOCATION t WELFARE NATIONAL 4NSTITLITEOF EOLICATiOre, : eFE% t,k^ 0, (EC 4E-E .E:, wFPE PSC'. Z.:. PC ,,Y.Fe. OPS ;;;S, l'ATED D'..) ..E:Es- L.e k,,,E sEyr oc; E0,.,CA' 04 0k P7 V THE- COVERING LAW MODEL IN COMMUNICATION INQUIRY* *By Charles R. Berger I Department of Communication Studies. Northwestern University 1822 Sheridan Road Evanston, Illinois '60201 I .. 4 1j ` e. fi; , Irl *The author would like to e?tpresshis deep appreciation to Paul H. Arntson, Glen W..Clatterbuck and Gerald R.Miller for their helpful criticisms of an .\ 0 earlic4T draft\ of the present paper. .10 ,,: * , r;. .i .... - 4. V ry. NNW J THE COVERING LAW MODEL IN CMIUNICATION INQUIRY Charles R. Berger NorthWestern University During tliT 1950's and 1960's,, persons interested in behavioral scientific approaches to the study of human communication concentrated most of their efforts on the task of acquiring and tiring various methodological and statistical tech-: niques. In part, this was a healthy trend at the tithe; however, it turned many _good researchers in our field into well trained hypothesis testers for theory builders' in, such disciplines as social psychology, sociology, psycholinquistics, sociolinguistics and political science. The role models for communication researchers in terms of'theory construction were found in these and related disciplinds. In the past few years, there has be an increase'in the number of papers, . ji-/' journal articles, and bookS concerned with either issues related to the process of theory, construction in gen J/,or the presentation of substantive theories .., or models withincon nunicati j #Fger and Calabrese,'1975; Cappella, 1974; , / '111/ Cushman and Whiting, lani 41975;.14onge, 1973.; Parks, 1974; andPerce, /1 ! a , 1973). It is probably fa do say that only thrOUgh the development of a unique . 10 ,... 7 / body of theory will commpidation achieve a disciplinary status equal to the . 1,54.-N,'' . , . ..1,1 ,. statuses of the other beha ioral sciences. Obviously, methodology and statisticalt . r.7 ... ..$ techniques do not define a discipline. Biology and. sociology employed path , 1 analysis long before it'wap, .introduced to communication (Dqncan, 1966,and Wright,..1934, 1954). The employment of. ,arious techniques in communication , research, no matter how eSoteric the methodology, will not serve to define us as a unique discipline. If the primary ta4Lof prese'nt day communication researchers is to develop and test communicatidnAeeries, it is imperative than they know what theory 41000!". V' -2- generating options 5-Fe available to them and what these various options have to offer. The alternative discussed in the present paper is one which has served as the dothinant model in both the physical and social sciences: the covering - law model. In the first section of the paper, the basic structure of the cover- . ing law model will be sketched. We will then examine some criticisms of the covering law approach. Finally, we will look at some issues surrounding the realization of covering law theories in communication inquiry. a. -THE COVERING LAW MODEL The basic aim of scientific theory is to provide explanations for observed phenomena. Some might argue that theories also aim to predict; however, explana- tion tak7sprecedence over prediction., If a theory can provide a complete explanation for a phenomenon, it can predict the phenomenon. By contrast, it is possible to have accufate prediction without explanation. In the case of scientific explanation, the paramount question for which the theoretical structure ti must provide an answer is the 'question."why?". Why do certain groups of persons have higher rates Of interpersonal conflict than others.?Why did a particular kind of message induce a large amount of attitude change? Why do persons engage in more self-disclosure in certain circumstances? These are some questions .cornunication researchers might wish to answer. The only way.that they can provide an answer for them is to build a theory. For we might -be able to predict and cli,:,monstrate with 100% success the rule that the person who answers the tel;phone always says "hello".before the caller says "hello", but after observing the phenomenon 1,000 times, we would still not be able to answer yr the question "Why,is it so?". Uncovering a regularity of behavior either in a "natural-setting"or in a laboratory does not explain it. This issue will .be explored in greater depth later in the present paper. , -a- The term "covering law model" was introduced by Dray (1957) in his dis- . cussion of historical explanation. Dray defined the notion of covering law explanation as follows: To put it in a summary way, what the theory maintains is that explanation is achieved, and only achieved,jaysubsuming what is to be explained under a Reneral law. Such an account of basic structure bf explanation is sometimes'referred toas. 40* 'the regularity analysis'; but because it makes use'of the notion of bringing case under a law, i.e. (covering'-it with a law I shall often speak of it hereafter as 'the covering law model.'" (p. 1). .. Dray cites Braithwaite (1953) and Gardiner (1952) as sources for his definition- of the covering law model of explanation. For a number of reasons which will not, be dealt with in the present paper, Dray rejects the position that covering 'law explanations are possible in historical inquiry. He argues that such explana- tions are likely td be misleading when One attempts .to employ them in,historical 9 research. A more detailed explication bf the covering law approach tips presented by Hempel (1965). Hempel distinguished among the following three kinds'of explana- tions: DeductivelNomological (D-N), Deductive Statistical (D-S), and Inductive '1 Statistical (I-S). Of the three, the D-N explanation is considered to bethe pure case of the covering law model. However, Hempel asserts that both and I-S forms of explanation contain elements ofthepure covering law model. H considers both D-S and I-S paradigms of explanation to be at leastpartially subvumed under the general of covering law model. In the remainder of ' this section we will focus our attention on the characteristics of D-N explana- tion and show how it differs from the other two types of explanations. r. Deductive-Numological Explanation A 11-N ex planation is divided 'ntothe'following two general parts: (1) that Which is to be explainedor tie explanandum, and (2) that which does.the; expi fining, the explanans. The .exp1an.aii3s, in turn, is, dividedinto-two groups . of tatements. The first type of statement contains particularfacts or initial o conditions under which the explanandum-phOnomenonwill occur. The second kind statement expres.ses a trtfl)ormity by means of general law. Taken together, t e initial conditions and the generallaws give rise` to-the explanandum. In other words, the explanandumcan he deduced fr6M the combination of the initial conditions and the general laws. Most theories contain a number ofinitial 'conditions as well as general laws. It is also assumed that the explanandum- sentence itself is true. Finally, when we refer to the fact that theexplanandum. is deduced from the explanans,we do not mean Co imply' that only syllogifstic
Recommended publications
  • Some Thoughts About Natural Law
    Some Thoughts About Natural Law Phflip E. Johnsont My first task is to define the subject. When I use the term "natural" law, I am distinguishing the category from other kinds of law such as positive law, divine law, or scientific law. When we discuss positive law, we look to materials like legislation, judicial opinions, and scholarly anal- ysis of these materials. If we speak of divine law, we ask if there are any knowable commands from God. If we look for scientific law, we conduct experiments, or make observations and calculations, in order to come to objectively verifiable knowledge about the material world. Natural law-as I will be using the term in this essay-refers to a method that we employ to judge what the principles of individual moral- ity or positive law ought to be. The natural law philosopher aspires to make these judgments on the basis of reason and human nature without invoking divine revelation or prophetic inspiration. Natural law so defined is a category much broader than any particular theory of natural law. One can believe in the existence of natural law without agreeing with the particular systems of natural law advocates like Aristotle or Aquinas. I am describing a way of thinking, not a particular theory. In the broad sense in which I am using the term, therefore, anyone who attempts to found concepts of justice upon reason and human nature engages in natural law philosophy. Contemporary philosophical systems based on feminism, wealth maximization, neutral conversation, liberal equality, or libertarianism are natural law philosophies.
    [Show full text]
  • Scientific Explanation
    Scientific Explanation Michael Strevens For the Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, second edition The three cardinal aims of science are prediction, control, and expla- nation; but the greatest of these is explanation. Also the most inscrutable: prediction aims at truth, and control at happiness, and insofar as we have some independent grasp of these notions, we can evaluate science’s strate- gies of prediction and control from the outside. Explanation, by contrast, aims at scientific understanding, a good intrinsic to science and therefore something that it seems we can only look to science itself to explicate. Philosophers have wondered whether science might be better off aban- doning the pursuit of explanation. Duhem (1954), among others, argued that explanatory knowledge would have to be a kind of knowledge so ex- alted as to be forever beyond the reach of ordinary scientific inquiry: it would have to be knowledge of the essential natures of things, something that neo-Kantians, empiricists, and practical men of science could all agree was neither possible nor perhaps even desirable. Everything changed when Hempel formulated his dn account of ex- planation. In accordance with the observation above, that our only clue to the nature of explanatory knowledge is science’s own explanatory prac- tice, Hempel proposed simply to describe what kind of things scientists ten- dered when they claimed to have an explanation, without asking whether such things were capable of providing “true understanding”. Since Hempel, the philosophy of scientific explanation has proceeded in this humble vein, 1 seeming more like a sociology of scientific practice than an inquiry into a set of transcendent norms.
    [Show full text]
  • Two Concepts of Law of Nature
    Prolegomena 12 (2) 2013: 413–442 Two Concepts of Law of Nature BRENDAN SHEA Winona State University, 528 Maceman St. #312, Winona, MN, 59987, USA [email protected] ORIGINAL SCIENTIFIC ARTICLE / RECEIVED: 04–12–12 ACCEPTED: 23–06–13 ABSTRACT: I argue that there are at least two concepts of law of nature worthy of philosophical interest: strong law and weak law . Strong laws are the laws in- vestigated by fundamental physics, while weak laws feature prominently in the “special sciences” and in a variety of non-scientific contexts. In the first section, I clarify my methodology, which has to do with arguing about concepts. In the next section, I offer a detailed description of strong laws, which I claim satisfy four criteria: (1) If it is a strong law that L then it also true that L; (2) strong laws would continue to be true, were the world to be different in some physically possible way; (3) strong laws do not depend on context or human interest; (4) strong laws feature in scientific explanations but cannot be scientifically explained. I then spell out some philosophical consequences: (1) is incompatible with Cartwright’s contention that “laws lie” (2) with Lewis’s “best-system” account of laws, and (3) with contextualism about laws. In the final section, I argue that weak laws are distinguished by (approximately) meeting some but not all of these criteria. I provide a preliminary account of the scientific value of weak laws, and argue that they cannot plausibly be understood as ceteris paribus laws. KEY WORDS: Contextualism, counterfactuals, David Lewis, laws of nature, Nancy Cartwright, physical necessity.
    [Show full text]
  • Ast#: ___Science Knowledge Study Guide Physical
    Name: ______________________________ Pd: ___ Ast#: _____ Science Knowledge Study Guide Physical Science Honors Provide a short response to the following prompts. 1. Describe how scientific knowledge is affected by new evidence (if the new evidence does NOT support the current understanding). Scientific knowledge grows and changes as new evidence is uncovered. 2. What is scientific knowledge built from? (list 3 things) Continuous testing and observation Debate (argumentation) All contribute to the EMPIRICAL EVIDENCE Confirmation (repetition & replication) 3. Why is it important that we use phrases such as “the results suggest…” or “the evidence supports…” rather than using words such as “prove” or “proof”? Using words such as “prove” violate the tentative nature of science. They imply that scientific knowledge is concrete and unchanging. However, scientific knowledge must remain open to change. 4. Under what circumstances will a scientific theory become a law? Explain. A scientific theory will NEVER become a scientific law; it cannot, nor is it supposed to. A scientific theory and a scientific law are two different things with different purposes (an apple will never become an orange). 5. Why are scientific theories rarely discarded (completely abandoned), even when new evidence doesn’t fit within the current theory? Scientific theories are rarely completely discarded because they are heavily-tested and well-supported explanations. It is rare that new evidence completely invalidates a theory; rather, it is more likely that the theory can be “tweaked” or changed slightly to accommodate the new evidence. 6. What represents the BEST explanation that science can offer? Scientific theories represent the best explanations science has to offer.
    [Show full text]
  • THE SCIENTIFIC METHOD and the LAW by Bemvam L
    Hastings Law Journal Volume 19 | Issue 1 Article 7 1-1967 The cS ientific ethoM d and the Law Bernard L. Diamond Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.uchastings.edu/hastings_law_journal Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Bernard L. Diamond, The Scientific etM hod and the Law, 19 Hastings L.J. 179 (1967). Available at: https://repository.uchastings.edu/hastings_law_journal/vol19/iss1/7 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Journals at UC Hastings Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Hastings Law Journal by an authorized editor of UC Hastings Scholarship Repository. THE SCIENTIFIC METHOD AND THE LAW By BEmVAm L. DIivmN* WHEN I was an adolescent, one of the major influences which determined my choice of medicine as a career was a fascinating book entitled Anomalies and Curiosities of Medicine. This huge volume, originally published in 1897, is a museum of pictures and lurid de- scriptions of human monstrosities and abnormalities of all kinds, many with sexual overtones of a kind which would especially appeal to a morbid adolescent. I never thought, at the time I first read this book, that some day, I too, would be an anomaly and curiosity of medicine. But indeed I am, for I stand before you here as a most curious and anomalous individual: a physician, psychiatrist, psychoanalyst, and (I hope) a scientist, who also happens to be a professor of law. But I am not a lawyer, nor in any way trained in the law; hence, the anomaly. The curious question is, of course, why should a non-lawyer physician and scientist, like myself, be on the faculty of a reputable law school.
    [Show full text]
  • Rules of Law, Laws of Science
    Rules of Law, Laws of Science Wai Chee Dimock* My Essay is a response to legal realism,' to its well-known arguments against "rules of law." Legal realism, seeing itself as an empirical practice, was not convinced that there could be any set of rules, formalized on the grounds of logic, that would have a clear determinative power on the course of legal action or, more narrowly, on the outcome of litigated cases. The decisions made inside the courtroom-the mental processes of judges and juries-are supposedly guided by rules. Realists argued that they are actually guided by a combination of factors, some social and some idiosyncratic, harnessed to no set protocol. They are not subject to the generalizability and predictability that legal rules presuppose. That very presupposition, realists said, creates a gap, a vexing lack of correspondence, between the language of the law and the world it purports to describe. As a formal system, law operates as a propositional universe made up of highly technical terms--estoppel, surety, laches, due process, and others-accompanied by a set of rules governing their operation. Law is essentially definitional in this sense: It comes into being through the specialized meanings of words. The logical relations between these specialized meanings give it an internal order, a way to classify cases into actionable categories. These categories, because they are definitionally derived, are answerable only to their internal logic, not to the specific features of actual disputes. They capture those specific features only imperfectly, sometimes not at all. They are integral and unassailable, but hollowly so.
    [Show full text]
  • Criminal Responsibility and Causal Determinism J
    Washington University Jurisprudence Review Volume 9 | Issue 1 2016 Criminal Responsibility and Causal Determinism J. G. Moore Follow this and additional works at: https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/law_jurisprudence Part of the Criminal Law Commons, Jurisprudence Commons, Legal History Commons, Legal Theory Commons, Philosophy Commons, and the Rule of Law Commons This document is a corrected version of the article originally published in print. To access the original version, follow the link in the Recommended Citation then download the file listed under “Previous Versions." Recommended Citation J. G. Moore, Criminal Responsibility and Causal Determinism, 9 Wash. U. Jur. Rev. 043 (2016, corrected 2016). Available at: http://openscholarship.wustl.edu/law_jurisprudence/vol9/iss1/6 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Law School at Washington University Open Scholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in Washington University Jurisprudence Review by an authorized administrator of Washington University Open Scholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Criminal Responsibility and Causal Determinism Cover Page Footnote This document is a corrected version of the article originally published in print. To access the original version, follow the link in the Recommended Citation then download the file listed under “Previous Versions." This article is available in Washington University Jurisprudence Review: https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/law_jurisprudence/vol9/ iss1/6 CRIMINAL RESPONSIBILITY AND CAUSAL DETERMINISM: CORRECTED VERSION J G MOORE* INTRODUCTION In analytical jurisprudence, determinism has long been seen as a threat to free will, and free will has been considered necessary for criminal responsibility.1 Accordingly, Oliver Wendell Holmes held that if an offender were hereditarily or environmentally determined to offend, then her free will would be reduced, and her responsibility for criminal acts would be correspondingly diminished.2 In this respect, Holmes followed his father, Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • Universal Determinism and Relative Dertermination
    University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Transactions of the Nebraska Academy of Sciences and Affiliated Societies Nebraska Academy of Sciences 1983 Universal Determinism and Relative Dertermination Leroy N. Meyer University of South Dakota Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/tnas Part of the Life Sciences Commons Meyer, Leroy N., "Universal Determinism and Relative Dertermination" (1983). Transactions of the Nebraska Academy of Sciences and Affiliated Societies. 252. https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/tnas/252 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Nebraska Academy of Sciences at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in Transactions of the Nebraska Academy of Sciences and Affiliated Societiesy b an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. 1983. Transactions of the Nebraska Academy of Sciences. XI:93-98. PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE UNIVERSAL DETERMINISM AND RELATIVE DETERMINATION Leroy N. Meyer Department of Philosophy University of South Dakota Vermillion, South Dakota 57069 Recent works have shown that it is possible to devise a clear have been developed. There is of course a variety of versions thesis of universal determinism. Two such theses are formulated. Ap­ of determinism, but of primary concern here is one general parently the motivations for universal determinism have been: (I) to kind of physical determinism, which may be called universal account for the explanatory power of scientific laws, (2) to support the principle of sufficient reason, and (3) to provide a methodological determinism, though remarks extend to some other kinds of criterion for scientific progress. Universal determinism is, however, deterministic theses as well.
    [Show full text]
  • Deterministic View of Criminal Responsibility, a Willard Waller
    Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology Volume 20 Article 4 Issue 1 May Spring 1929 Deterministic View of Criminal Responsibility, A Willard Waller Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarlycommons.law.northwestern.edu/jclc Part of the Criminal Law Commons, Criminology Commons, and the Criminology and Criminal Justice Commons Recommended Citation Willard Waller, Deterministic View of Criminal Responsibility, A, 20 Am. Inst. Crim. L. & Criminology 88 (1929-1930) This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Northwestern University School of Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology by an authorized editor of Northwestern University School of Law Scholarly Commons. A DETERMINISTIC VIEW OF CRIMINAL RESPONSIBILITY WILLARD WALLER' Science is detached, and not evaluative. It seeks to isolate and describe causative mechanisms, not to praise or blame them. Its pur- pose is to attain control, practical or intellectual, of a set of phenomena, and not to establish any particular doctrines concerning those phe- nomena. Because the assumption that causative mechanisms are operative in a field of phenomena is the sine qua non of research in that field, the extension of the scientific method has often been opposed by adherents of the current demonology wishing to preserve for their favorite spirits their full prerogative. Now that the existence of man's interior demon, last and dearest of his tribe, his free will, is questioned by those who wish to apply the scientific method to the study of human behavior, controversy not unexpectedly becomes rife. On the question of free will two points of view emerge clearly, the determinigtic and the libertarian.
    [Show full text]
  • A Reflection on How Scientific Theories Reflect the Empirical World— Do There Exist Scientific Theories That Precisely Explain How All Physical Objects Work?1
    A Reflection on How Scientific Theories Reflect the Empirical World— Do There Exist Scientific Theories that Precisely Explain How All Physical Objects Work?1 Yuen Wai Kiu Mathematics, New Asia College Introduction Laymen, including those having received some science education in high school, may perceive our world as being well described by scientific theories. Although some theories in biology still provoke controversies, like the problem of free will, or Darwin’s theory of evolution; Newton’s three laws of mechanics may receive nearly no doubt when describing the phenomena in our physical world. In this paper, we would like to study scientific theories that are considered to be the most precise, like the three laws of mechanics; and 1 The original title was “Do all physical objects in the universe, such as planets, trees, fishes and humans as shown in the advertisement, work like machines? Does it mean that there are precise mechanisms to explain how all physical objects work?” I have always been wondering if I have misinterpreted the question, for the word machines makes me thought of reductionism. Here, I shall modify the title to what I actually mean in this paper. 142 與自然對話 In Dialogue with Nature to examine if they really are. We shall also focus on theories in a general manner, to study if we are ever possible to obtain theories that precisely explain how all physical objects work. The Nature of Scientific Theories To answer the question, “Do There Exist Scientific Theories That Precisely Explain How All Physical Objects Work?”, we have to first understand the meaning and the nature of Scientific Theories and precision of which is respected to the explanation of how physical objects work.
    [Show full text]
  • The Relationship Between the Aristotelian, Newtonian and Holistic Scientific Paradigms and Selected British Detective Fiction 1980 - 2010
    THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THE ARISTOTELIAN, NEWTONIAN AND HOLISTIC SCIENTIFIC PARADIGMS AND SELECTED BRITISH DETECTIVE FICTION 1980 - 2010 HILARY ANNE GOLDSMITH A thesis submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements of the University of Greenwich for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy July 2010 i ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I would like to acknowledge the help and support I have received throughout my studies from the academic staff at the University of Greenwich, especially that of my supervisors. I would especially like to acknowledge the unerring support and encouragement I have received from Professor Susan Rowland, my first supervisor. iii ABSTRACT This thesis examines the changing relationship between key elements of the Aristotelian, Newtonian and holistic scientific paradigms and contemporary detective fiction. The work of scholars including N. Katherine Hayles, Martha A. Turner has applied Thomas S. Kuhn’s notion of scientific paradigms to literary works, especially those of the Victorian period. There seemed to be an absence, however, of research of a similar academic standard exploring the relationship between scientific worldviews and detective fiction. Extending their scholarship, this thesis seeks to open up debate in what was perceived to be an under-represented area of literary study. The thesis begins by identifying the main precepts of the three paradigms. It then offers a chronological overview of the developing relationship between these precepts and detective fiction from Sir Arthur Conan Doyle’s The Sign of Four (1890) to P.D.James’s The Black Tower (1975). The present state of this interaction is assessed through a detailed analysis of representative examples of the detective fiction of Reginald Hill, Barbara Nadel, and Quintin Jardine written between 1980 and 2010.
    [Show full text]
  • The Concept of Physical Law
    The concept of physical law Second edition Norman Swartz, Professor Emeritus Simon Fraser University Burnaby, British Columbia V5A 1S6 Canada Copyright © 2003 http://www.sfu.ca/philosophy/physical-law Legal Notice Copyright © Norman Swartz, 2003 ISBN 0-9730084-2-3 (e-version) ISBN 0-9730084-3-1 (CD-ROM) Although The Concept of Physical Law, Second Edition (the “Book”) is being made available for download on the World Wide Web (WWW) it is not in the public domain. The author, Norman Swartz, holds and retains full copyright. All persons wishing to download a copy of this Book, or parts thereof, for their own personal use, are hereby given permission to do so. Similarly, all teachers and schools (e.g. colleges and universities) are given permission to reproduce copies of this Book, or parts, for sale to their students provided that the selling price does not exceed the actual cost of reproduction, that is, neither this Book nor any of its parts may be sold for profit. Any commercial sale of this Book, or its parts, is strictly and explicitly forbidden. Electronic text (e-text), such as this Book, lends itself easily to cut-and-paste. That is, it is easy for persons to cut out parts of this Book and to place those parts into other works. If or when this is done, the excerpts must be credited to this author, Norman Swartz. Failure to do so constitutes infringement of copyright and the theft of intellectual property. Would-be plagiarists are cautioned that it is an easy matter to trace any unauthorized quotations from this Book.
    [Show full text]