<<

1How Individualized Niches Arise: Defining Mechanisms of Niche

2Construction, Niche Choice and Niche Conformance

3Rose Trappes*, Behzad Nematipour*, Marie I. Kaiser*, Ulrich Krohs*, Koen J. van

4Benthem^, Ulrich R. Ernst^, Jürgen Gadau^, Peter Korsten^, Joachim Kurtz^, Holger

5Schielzeth^, Tim Schmoll^, Elina Takola^

6 7*Shared first authorship 8^Equal contribution 9 10Affiliations

11RT, MK: Department of Philosophy, Bielefeld University, Universitätsstr. 25, 33615 12Bielefeld, Germany 13BN: Center for Philosophy of Science, University of Münster, Domplatz 23, 48143 Münster, 14Germany 15UK: Department of Philosophy, University of Münster, Domplatz 23, 48143 Münster, 16Germany 17KvB: Department of Theoretical Biology, Bielefeld University, Universitätsstr. 25, 33615 18Bielefeld, Germany 19UE, JG, JK: Institute for and , University of Münster, Hüfferstraße 1, 2048149 Münster, Germany 21PK: Department of Animal Behaviour, Bielefeld University, Konsequenz 45, 33615 22Bielefeld, Germany 23TS: Department of Evolutionary Biology, Bielefeld University, Konsequenz 45, 33615 24Bielefeld, Germany 25HS, ET: Population Group, Institute of Ecology and Evolution, Friedrich Schiller 26University Jena, Dornburger Straße 159, 07743 Jena, Germany 27

28ORCiD 29RT: 0000-0002-6398-5404 30BN: - 31MIK: 0000-0002-9307-7474 32UK: - 33KvB: 0000-0002-3841-2110 34UE: 0000-0002-6330-5341 35JG: 0000-0003-1258-5379 36PK: 0000-0003-0814-9099 37JK: 0000-0002-7258-459X

1 38HS: 0000-0002-9124-2261 39TS: 0000-0003-3234-7335 40ET: 0000-0003-1268-5513 41

42Correspondence

43Rose Trappes, [email protected]

44

45Author Contribution Statement

46All authors conceived the theoretical framework. RT, BN, MK & UK created the initial draft

47and performed revisions of the manuscript. KvB, UE, JG, PK, JK, HS, TS & ET contributed

48examples and helped to revise the text and figures. All authors approved the submitted

49version.

50

51Funding

52This research was funded by the German Research Foundation (DFG) as part of the SFB

53TRR 212 (NC³) – Project number 316099922.

54

55Acknowledgements

56We would like to acknowledge Caroline Müller, Oliver Krüger, and Norbert Sachser for

57generating the initial framework of the NC3 mechanisms which we develop and present here,

58and for helpful comments during writing. Thanks are also due to all members of the CRC

59TRR-212 at the University of Münster, Bielefeld University and Jena University and to the

60philosophers of biology at Bielefeld University for their attention and constructive feedback

61on the project.

2 62How Individualized Niches Arise: Defining Mechanisms of Niche Construction, Niche

63Choice and Niche Conformance

64

65Abstract

66The debate between the extended evolutionary synthesis (EES) and the modern synthesis

67(MS) partly relies on different interpretations of niche construction. We dissect the umbrella

68term of niche construction into three separate mechanisms: niche construction (taken in a

69narrow sense), in which individuals make changes to the environment; niche choice, in which

70individuals select an environment; and niche conformance, in which individuals change their

71phenotypes. Each of these individual-level mechanisms affects an individual’s phenotype-

72environment match, its fitness, and its individualized niche, defined in terms of the

73environmental conditions under which an individual can survive and reproduce. Our

74conceptual framework distinguishes several ways in which individuals alter the selective

75regimes that they and other experience. It also places clear emphasis on individual

76differences and construes niche construction and other processes as evolved mechanisms. We

77therefore argue that our framework helps to resolve the tensions between EES and MS.

78

79Keywords: extended evolutionary synthesis, niche construction, individualized niche,

80individual differences, phenotypic plasticity

81

82Introduction

83Organisms change their environment— build dams, birds build nests,

84alter soil structure. It seems uncontentious that these organisms thereby modify their living

85conditions and the selective regime under which they live. Under dispute, however, is what

86these modificatory actions, often called niche construction, mean for evolutionary theory.

3 87One view is that through modifying the environment organisms actively influence the

88evolution of their own and other species, making organisms not just objects of, but subjects in

89evolution (Lewontin 1983, Laland et al. 2015). This view is central to the Extended

90Evolutionary Synthesis (EES). Another view interprets organisms’ modificatory actions as

91adaptations that are the outcome of earlier stages of evolution. This classical view of the

92Modern Synthesis (MS), in contrast to EES, therefore maintains organisms’ status as mere

93objects of evolutionary processes, with environmental modifications understood as a result of

94evolution by (Dawkins 1982).

95The dispute might look like a chicken and egg problem—which came first, selection or

96construction? But there is far more at stake than just where to put the focus in a sequence of

97alternating steps. EES and MS have starkly contrasting understandings of evolution and take

98different biological disciplines as relevant for evolutionary theory. EES considers organismal

99activities as dependent on modifications in developmental processes, which in turn affect

100evolution (Laland et al. 2014). It thus demands an extension of MS by, for instance,

101integrating developmental and behavioral biology. In contrast, contemporary interpretations

102of MS acknowledge developmental processes and interactions between the genotype and the

103environment, yet claim that these can be accommodated within the classical framework that

104sees genetic change as the core of evolutionary change (Wray et al. 2014).

105We believe that the alleged incompatibility of EES and MS accounts of niche construction

106can be partly resolved. We argue for recognizing the different ways in which organisms alter

107their environment and their relation to the environment as a set of evolved causal mechanisms

108that play a role in evolutionary processes. This insight derives from our interdisciplinary

109work within the Research Consortium “A Novel Synthesis of Individualisation across

110Behaviour, Ecology and Evolution: Niche Choice, Niche Conformance and Niche

111Construction (NC3)” (https://www.uni-bielefeld.de/biologie/crc212). In this paper, we

4 112undertake some conceptual clarifications that help to diminish the perceived conflict between

113EES and MS. We do so largely with a focus on animals, but we see our framework as

114applicable to plants and other taxa.

115We first point out that niche construction is carried out by individuals and that there can be

116individual differences in niche construction (section 1). We subdivide the umbrella concept

117of niche construction into three distinct mechanisms through which individuals interact with

118their environments: making changes to the environment (niche construction in the narrow

119sense), selecting an environment (niche choice), and altering their phenotype in response to

120the environment (niche conformance) (sections 2 and 3). All three mechanisms alter the

121phenotype-environment match and the individual’s fitness, thereby determining the

122ecological niche of an individual, defined as the set of environmental conditions in which an

123individual can survive and reproduce (section 4). Hence, we refer to these mechanisms as

124“niche-altering mechanisms” or “NC3 mechanisms”. Finally, we discuss which aspects of the

125debate about the evolutionary relevance of niche construction can be resolved by our

126conceptual work, which ones become empirical questions, and which ones remain as

127differences between different framings of evolution (section 5).

128

1291. Individual Differences in Niche Construction

130We can start with a classical example of niche construction: “Birds build nests” or more

131concretely, “Common buzzards (Buteo buteo) build nests with twigs from various tree

132species.” Here, niche construction might be understood at the species level, describing what

133nest-building behavior is characteristic of the species B. buteo. Yet in the end it is individual

134buzzards that build nests in the environment. In fact, niche construction activities always

135require the action of individuals (sometimes in pairs or groups) that change the environment.

5 136According to the EES, these individual activities can in turn affect the evolutionary

137trajectories of populations and species.

138The relation between individual activities and species evolution is sometimes obscured in

139definitions of niche construction. For instance, Lewontin and Levins first described niche

140construction—prior to the coining of the term—as such: “the influences its own

141evolution, by being both the object of natural selection and the creator of the conditions of

142that selection” (Lewontin and Levins 1985, p. 106). Here “the organism” is at once

143population or species—since it has its “own” evolution, and it is populations and species

144which evolve—and individual—performing activities that alter the conditions of selection.

145Later definitions of niche construction try to avoid this equivocation. For instance, Odling-

146Smee, Laland and Feldman caution that “niche construction is typically expressed by

147individual organisms, but natural selection is a process that operates within populations”

148(Odling-Smee et al. 2003, pp. 41-42). In other words, it is not the niche-constructing

149individuals themselves that evolve, but their population or species.

150Recognizing individuals as the agents of niche construction invites consideration of an often-

151overlooked aspect of niche construction: individual differences. Not all individuals in a

152population are the same, and different individuals can construct niches in different ways.

153These individual differences in niche construction are important because they can have

154evolutionary consequences.

155For instance, queens of the California Harvester Ant (Pogonomyrmex californicus) vary in

156their colony founding behavior, either tolerating other queens or killing them (Rissing et al.

1572000, Clark and Fewell 2014). This individual difference leads to fundamentally different

158social structures with either multiple unrelated queens or a single queen (Overson et al.

1592014). The proportion of multiple and single queen societies varies substantially between

6 160subpopulations (Overson et al. 2016). It seems that colony density, degree of territoriality or

161aggression and availability (Haney and Fewell 2018) are crucial components of the

162selective environment that favors either one or the other type of niche construction.

163Being clear that we are talking about individual activities invites us to focus on a particular

164sort of niche, namely the individualized niche. The idea that individuals have their own,

165individualized niches has been proposed following the recognition of ecological

166specialization within populations (Roughgarden 1972, Bolnick et al. 2003, Dall et al. 2012,

167Violle et al. 2012). The population niche concerns the conditions under which a population as

168a whole persists; it does not take into account that some individuals might be better off under

169conditions that are less favorable for others. In contrast, the individualized niche concerns

170how the requirements and dispositions of an individual relate to its environment. Individuals

171that differ from each other will be confronted, in the very same environment, with different

172impact or effects of the environmental conditions, consume different resources, have different

173interactions with conspecifics, and so on, and these interactions can have different fitness

174effects. We summarize our definitions of species and individualized niches in BOX 1 and

175explain them in detail in section 4.2.

7 BOX 1. The of an individual The ecological niche of a species is the set of environmental conditions under which it exists and can maintain itself (implying non-negative population growth rates in the long run).

We define the fundamental individualized niche as the range of environmental conditions under which a specific individual with a given set of traits could possibly live and reproduce.

We define the realized individualized niche as the environmental conditions under which a specific individual does actually live and reproduce. The realized niche is thus the subset of the fundamental niche realized in the actual environment in which an individual lives.

We emphasize the dynamic nature of individualized niches. A fundamental individualized niche can change by the individual’s activities that alter its physiological or behavioral phenotypes or developmental pathways. A realized individualized niche can change by activities that alter the experienced environment of an individual, and by environmental changes. 176

177Individual organisms engage in many sorts of activities altering their individualized niches.

178Most of the classical examples of niche construction involve organisms actively making

179changes to their environments, rather than, for instance, changing the environmental

180conditions they live in by relocation. This makes sense, because we intuitively understand

181niche construction in analogy to human construction of artifacts like buildings or roads

182(Archetti 2015).

183However, many niche construction theorists understand niche construction more broadly.

184Odling-Smee, Laland and Feldman (2003) include relocating as an instance of niche

185construction. Others include phenotypic alteration that changes how an environment is

186experienced as a kind of niche construction (Lewontin and Levins 1985, Aaby and Ramsey

1872019). The use of “niche construction” to cover such diverse phenomena can be confusing,

188especially given that paradigmatic examples continue to revolve around making changes to

189the environment.

8 190We therefore restrict the concept of niche construction to what we see as its intuitive scope:

191organisms making changes to their environment. To refer to other ways in which individuals

192interact with their environment and thereby alter their niches, we employ two additional

193terms: niche choice occurs when individuals select an environment, and niche conformance

194occurs when individuals alter their phenotype in response to the environment (see also

195Edelaar and Bolnick 2019). Collectively, we refer to niche construction, niche choice, and

196niche conformance as niche-altering mechanisms, or “NC3 mechanisms”.

197

1982. Introducing the NC3 Mechanisms

199NC3 mechanisms consist of entities and activities that are spatially, temporally and

200hierarchically organized in specific ways, and produce a phenomenon. This accords with

201definitions of mechanisms as put forward in philosophy of science (Bechtel and Richardson

2021993, Glennan 1996, 2017, Machamer et al. 2000, Craver and Darden 2013). The activities

203that individuals carry out lead to a specific outcome: a change in the phenotype-environment

204match and in the individual’s fitness, and an individualized niche (section 4). Referring to

205niche construction, niche choice and niche conformance as three mechanisms highlights that

206we seek to understand the causal process of how match, fitness and individualized niches

207change.

208NC3 mechanisms share a general structure. Usually, they are organized around a focal

209individual. The focal individual, sometimes in cooperation with other individuals, is engaged

210in a focal activity. The philosophical term ‘activity’ is similar to the term ‘behavior’ in that it

211also includes changes such as reducing locomotion or going to sleep. In other words,

212activities are what organisms do. Activities can involve one or more entities; entities involved

213in an activity can be active, performing the activity, or they can be passive, having the

9 214activity done to them (Machamer et al. 2000, Illari and Williamson 2013, Kaiser 2018). For

215example, blood parasites are actively involved in the activity ‘infecting’, whereas buzzard

216chicks as hosts have a passive role in this activity. Similarly, beavers are actively involved in

217the activity ‘cutting trees’, whereas trees are passively involved in this activity. For the NC3

218mechanisms, the focal individual is actively involved in the focal activities.

219The different NC3 mechanism are discerned by the respective focal activity. In the case of

220niche construction, the focal activity is to make changes to the environment, in niche choice

221the focal activity is to select an environment and in niche conformance the focal activity is to

222change the phenotype in response to the environment (Figure 1). These focal activities are

223quite abstract; in descriptions of concrete NC3 mechanisms they are replaced by more specific

224activities involving the focal individual, other organisms and abiotic factors (Kaiser and

225Trappes forthcoming). In the example of harvester ants, for instance, the niche construction

226activities involve aggressive or tolerant interactions as well as performing certain colony

227founding tasks.

228

229Figure 1. NC3 mechanisms. (a) Three individuals, A, B and C are in the same environment.

230Each individual uses a different NC3 mechanism to change its phenotype-environment match.

231(b) Each NC3 mechanism involves a different focal activity. Focal individuals A, B and C can

10 232make changes to the environment, select the environment, or adjust the phenotype in

233response to the environment. (b) is modified from Kaiser and Trappes (in press).

234

235The outcome of NC3 mechanisms, the phenomenon they produce, can also be characterized

236on a general level. NC3 mechanisms change the match between the focal individual’s

237phenotype and its environment, as well as the individual’s fitness, understood as the number

238of offspring produced or its contribution to the gene pool of future generations (more in

239section 4.1). Consequently, NC3 mechanisms also change an individual’s niche, taken

240preliminarily as the set of environmental parameter values under which it survives and

241reproduces (BOX 1). This is why we refer to the three focal activities (‘making changes to’

242environment, ‘selecting’ environment, and ‘changing’ phenotype in response to the

243environment) as niche-altering activities. It is important to note that the NC3 mechanisms

244refer not to a choice of, conformance to or construction of the niche but rather to a choice of,

245conformance to or construction of the environment, which in turn affects the niche.

246BOX 2 summarizes the general structure of NC3 mechanisms. The general structure together

247with the distinction of the three focal activities gives rise to definitions for the three NC3

248mechanisms.

11 BOX 2. The Focal Activities of NC3 Mechanisms In NC3 mechanisms, a focal individual is actively involved in a focal activity, which leads to a change of the phenotype-environment match, a fitness change, and a change of the individualized niche. Niche Construction is the mechanism by which an individual makes changes to its environment, resulting in a change of the individual’s phenotype-environment match, fitness and individualized niche.

Niche Choice is the mechanism by which an individual selects an environment, resulting in a change of the individual’s phenotype-environment match, fitness and individualized niche.

Niche Conformance is the mechanism by which an individual changes its phenotype, resulting in a change of the individual’s phenotype-environment match, fitness and individualized niche. 249

250

251The NC3 mechanisms do not always appear separately. Often, two or even all three

252mechanisms will occur simultaneously or in sequence. For instance, a buzzard building a nest

253is certainly a case of niche construction, but buzzards often need to relocate to a suitable

254habitat and choose a tree in which to build their nest, so that niche choice precedes niche

255construction.

256In addition, the very general nature of the NC3 mechanism definitions in combination with

257the fact that mechanisms can occur together means that classification can be ambiguous in

258some cases. For instance, an organism making changes to the environment (niche

259construction) typically involves certain behavioral or other phenotypic changes, as occurs in

260niche conformance. Similarly, choosing a specific social group (niche choice) will also

261induce changes in the social dynamics of that group, as occurs in niche construction. Each

262case must therefore be considered carefully in light of the mechanisms at play, and there may

263be borderline cases that are difficult to categorize.

12 264In the next section we analyze the three focal activities in more detail and provide some

265examples. Later, we tackle the other elements of the definitions: the way individual activities

266lead to changes in organism-environment match and fitness, and their effects on

267individualized niches (section 4).

268

2693. Three Types of Niche-Altering Activities

2703.1 Rebuilding the Environment: Niche Construction

271Mechanisms of niche construction are characterized by the focal individual actively making

272changes to its environment. The classic examples of niche construction cited earlier—beavers

273building dams, birds building nests, and worms altering soil structure—involve focal

274individuals altering the properties of their abiotic environment. However, individuals can also

275make changes to their biotic environment through interactions with organisms from other

276species or with conspecifics.

277A special case is when individuals change their social environment, for instance by altering

278the way conspecifics behave by interacting with them. For example, in cooperatively

279breeding meerkats (Suricata suricatta), dominant females show increased aggression towards

280pregnant subordinate females, resulting in their temporary eviction from the social group.

281Being evicted induces severe stress in the subordinates, causing spontaneous abortions. In

282this way, dominant females suppress competitors’ reproduction, thereby monopolizing

283reproduction in the group (Young et al. 2006).

284An interaction with other organisms or the abiotic environment must satisfy two conditions to

285count as the focal activity in niche construction. First, there must be a change in the

286environment and not just a change in which environment the individual relates to, which

287would be choice. Second, the focal individual must have an active role (see above, Section 2).

13 288This excludes changes in the environment in which an individual is only passively involved,

289such as changes in a non-human organism’s environment produced by human activities such

290as farming or anthropogenic . On the other hand, activities such as defecation

291or trampling can count as niche construction since the focal individual is actively engaging in

292activities that change their environment, as long as the focal individual’s phenotype-

293environment match and fitness also change as a result. These two conditions are captured in

294our definition (BOX 2) by the phrase ‘makes changes to its environment.’

295

2963.2 Selecting the Environment: Niche Choice

297The second NC3 mechanism is niche choice, in which the focal individual selects the

298environment with which it interacts. In cases of niche choice individuals change how they

299interact with different parts of the environment, rather than changing their phenotype (niche

300conformance) or making changes to the environment (niche construction).

301A paradigmatic type of niche choice is an individual moving to a different . Sometimes

302this is a temporary or context dependent choice. For instance, in azure sand grasshoppers

303(Sphingonotus azurescens), darker individuals prefer darker underground, whereas

304individuals with lighter colors prefer lighter underground. Interestingly, manipulation of

305individuals’ color (with dark or light paint) led to changes in preferences such that dark-

306painted individuals preferred darker underground, independent of their original, natural

307coloration (Camacho et al. 2020). An example of a more permanent niche choice is territory

308establishment. For instance, movement data from juvenile black grouse (Tetrao tetrix)

309showed that, following natal dispersal during the first year, most individuals remained in the

310areas where they spent their first winter (Caizergues and Ellison 2002).

14 311Niche choice does not necessarily involve physical relocation but can include selective

312interactions with parts of the environment, especially through choice of resources or social

313groups. An illustrative example of individual differences in the choice of the social

314environment is provided by work on cliff swallows (Petrochelidon pyrrhonota), a colonial

315bird, where individuals have heritable preferences for breeding in smaller or larger groups

316(Brown and Brown 2000). Another example is the California harvester ants referred to in

317section 1, where queens choose whether to found a nest together with other queens.

318In most cases of niche choice, the focal individual changes its location, resource use or

319interactions with its (social) environment. But what about an individual choosing to not

320change anything? We think that these cases should be counted as niche choice if the

321individual was able to explore different options of changing its relation to the environment.

322Even if this exploration does not result in a change of the individual-environment relation, it

323does involve individuals actively approving their present environments. It might be difficult

324to discern such cases empirically from cases where an individual does not make a choice

325(because it does not explore different environmental options). However, there is a conceptual

326delineation of the cases. It is an interesting empirical question whether maintaining the same

327relation to the environment is or is not the result of engaging in a choice procedure.

328

3293.3 Adjusting the Phenotype: Niche Conformance

330The third NC3 mechanism is niche conformance, which involves focal individuals changing

331their phenotypes in response to environmental conditions. Niche conformance involves

332phenotypic plasticity, which is the capacity of an organism to develop distinct phenotypes in

333response to environmental variation (Pigliucci 2001, 2005). Accordingly, the focal activity of

15 334changing the phenotype that characterizes niche conformance (BOX 2) can also be described

335as adjusting the phenotype in response to certain environmental conditions.

336Yet niche conformance involves more than just the focal activity. Unlike phenotypic

337plasticity, niche conformance also includes how phenotypic adjustment leads to changes in

338the phenotype-environment match, fitness, and the individualized niche of the focal

339individual (section 4). In particular, by stressing inter-individual variation of organisms in

340their plastic responses, so-called individual-by-environment interactions (Nussey et al. 2007),

341it directly leads to an expectation that the resulting niches are individualized (section 4.2).

342Niche conformance may accommodate any kind of trait (morphological, physiological,

343behavioral or life history) and can be applied to irreversible developmental changes during an

344individual’s lifetime (non-labile traits) as well as to reversible changes in response to the

345current environment (labile traits). An example for a non-labile, morphological trait is the

346expression of inducible defenses like spines and helmets by water fleas (e.g., Daphnia

347cucullata) during development in response to anticipated variation in risk (Laforsch

348and Tollrian 2004). An example for a labile, life-history trait is the timing of reproduction in

349many temperate bird species where individual females track between-year variation in spring

350temperatures in order to match supply and demand in nestling food (Charmantier et al. 2008).

351Another example is provided by Macrostomum hystrix, a flatworm, in which individuals are

352facultative selfers that reproduce through outcrossing when a mating partner is available, but

353self-fertilize if no partner has been available for a certain amount of time (Ramm et al. 2012).

16 3544. NC3 Mechanisms Affect Phenotype-Environment Match, Fitness, and the

355Individualized Niche

3564.1 Phenotype-Environment Match and Fitness

357Each of the NC3 mechanisms brings about a change in the phenotype-environment match and

358in fitness. The notion of match that we use is evaluative, referring to how well an organism’s

359phenotype matches to its environment. Match is often measured by reproductive success. In

360this case, match and fitness are positively correlated. Match can also be measured using other

361measures such as food uptake rate, body condition, efficiency of locomotion, or effectiveness

362of coloration (e.g., , aposematic warning colors). Non-fitness measures of match

363may still lead to a correlation between match and fitness, since an improvement of factors

364like body condition or effective will often increase an organism’s fitness.

365It might seem natural to think that NC3 mechanisms would not just affect but also improve

366match and fitness of the focal individual. We decided not to restrict the definitions of the NC3

367mechanisms to cases which improve match and increase fitness. There are two main reasons

368for this decision.

369First, requiring that NC3 mechanisms increase fitness would mean that a specific mechanism

370would not count as an NC3 mechanism when, due to some intervening factor, the overall

371outcome is less advantageous for the focal individual. Second, we define fitness as absolute

372fitness in line with Hutchinson’s population level growth rate (Section 4.2). However, at the

373level of individuals even a decrease in absolute fitness could nevertheless be beneficial in

374evolutionary terms if it increases relative fitness. This would be the case if for instance

375conspecifics suffer more from the operation of an NC3 mechanism than the focal individual.

376Thus, the fitness effects of NC3 mechanisms may depend on the specific environment, in

377particular on social conditions. Fluctuating conditions can thus lead to a change of the sign of

17 378the fitness outcome. It is for such reasons that we believe NC3 mechanisms should also allow

379for instances of an activity decreasing individual fitness or other measures of match. Such

380cases can be particularly relevant to study, since they can illuminate why individuals engage

381in apparently non-adaptive activities. In general, however, we expect that evolved NC3

382mechanisms will tend to increase individuals’ (absolute and relative) fitness (Odling-Smee et

383al. 2003, p. 48), since the mechanisms would otherwise have been selected against. This

384assumption is reflected in many empirical studies that investigate the adaptive value of NC3

385mechanisms.

386

3874.2 Individualized Niches

388So far, we have addressed individual activities and their consequences for match and fitness.

389The last element of the NC3 mechanisms is their effect on individualized niches. We

390understand the individualized niche as the individual-level counterpart of the Hutchinsonian

391population niche (Hutchinson 1957, Holt 2009). Re-defining Hutchinson’s concept at the

392individual level requires several modifications.

393First, Hutchinson defines the niche in terms of the environmental conditions under which a

394population could persist indefinitely, a condition that needs some modification to be

395transferable to the case of individuals with limited life spans. We define the limits of the

396individualized niche in terms of individual realized fitness equal to or greater than what is

397necessary for the individual to replace itself in future generations (i.e., each individual

398leaving one reproducing offspring). In addition, in the context of the NC3 mechanisms, we are

399interested in how exposure to different environmental parameters can change fitness above

400the minimum required for replacement. We thus need to consider gradual fitness values for

401different subsections of the niche, as Hutchinson proposed for population niches (Hutchinson

18 4021957). The individualized niche is the mapping, or function, of fitness over sets of

403environmental parameters.

404Second, to accommodate changes of niche relations within a lifetime, the quality of match

405needs to be evaluated with respect to a given situation or short period of time. Realized

406fitness, being a lifetime outcome, is not the appropriate parameter. Instead, fitness proxies

407such as individual (ontogenetic) growth rate, survival across life stages, territory possession,

408mating rates and fertilization success can serve as indicators of the quality of a combination

409of niche parameter values for an individual at a given time.

410Third, we need to distinguish between the fundamental niche as a set of possibilities and the

411realized niche as the actualization of one of these possibilities (BOX 1). We define a

412fundamental individualized niche as the environmental conditions under which an individual

413could possibly live and reproduce. An individualized realization of a niche is in turn the

414subset or region of the fundamental niche realized by the environmental conditions under

415which the individual actually survives and reproduces. We call this a realized individualized

416niche, even though this does not exactly mirror Hutchinson’s concept of a realized niche. In

417the next section, we discuss how the NC3 mechanisms change individualized niches and how

418they affect fundamental and realized individualized niches differently.

419

4204.3 NC3 Mechanisms Alter Individualized Niches

421Individuals conform to, choose or construct the environment rather than the niche. Yet these

422activities do result in changes of the individualized niche (Figure 2).

19 423

424Figure 2. NC3 mechanisms produce changes in the individualized niche. Simplified

425individualized niches, showing two possible phenotypes and their values for a fitness or

426match (e.g., growth rate, fertilization success, performance) along a single niche dimension

427(e.g., temperature, food ). (a) Niche construction: an individual with phenotype P

428in environment 1 makes changes to its environment so that it becomes environment 2,

429thereby increasing the individual’s fitness. (b) Niche choice: an individual with phenotype P

430in environment 1 selects environment 3, thereby increasing its fitness. (c) Niche

431conformance: an individual with phenotype P in environment 1 adjusts to phenotype Q,

432thereby increasing its fitness within environment 1.

433

434Niche construction can produce a change in the values of environmental factors such as

435temperature, humidity, resource availability, or population density. The set of these values is

436equivalent to a certain point or region in the fundamental individualized niche. Since niche

437construction affects which set of niche parameters is realized in the environment of the

438individual, niche construction changes the realized individualized niche.

20 439As niche construction changes the selective regime, it might also lead to an evolutionary

440response. If phenotypic variation is at least partly heritable, then natural selection may change

441the phenotypes of future individuals; phenotypic change through natural selection could in

442turn alter the fundamental individualized niches of future individuals. For example, most bird

443species construct elaborate nests where eggs are incubated and chicks raised until fledging

444(Hansell 2000, Mainwaring et al. 2014). Variation in nest construction among breeding

445individuals or pairs influences the nest’s insulating properties and thereby the

446microenvironment experienced by the parents and their offspring (Mainwaring 2017), which

447can facilitate natural selection on phenotypes, potentially leading to evolutionary changes in

448both nest-building and temperature tolerance (again, assuming such phenotypic variation is

449heritable).

450The consequences of niche choice for the realized individualized niche are the same as for

451niche construction, but they are brought about by selecting a different environment instead of

452modifying the existing environment (Figure 2). Individual differences in choice driven by

453factors such as physiology, morphology or social dynamics can lead to individuals realizing

454different niches. For instance, in the invasive racer goby (Babka gymnotrachelus),

455intraspecific interactions drive dispersal, as subordinate individuals tend to move greater

456distances in search of resources and less hostile social environments (Grabowska et al. 2019).

457Niche conformance changes the individual’s phenotype. A different phenotype means that the

458organism can, for instance, tolerate different conditions or perform better on different

459resources. This in turn means that the individual will have changed its fitness value given one

460and the same set of niche parameter values. In addition, there may be different sets of

461environmental conditions under which the individual can survive and reproduce. In both

462instances, the fundamental individualized niche changes, either in which sets of niche

21 463parameter values it includes or in the shape of the fitness function across the ecological

464dimensions of the niche.

465Interestingly, when niche choice or construction induce niche conformance, a change in the

466realized individualized niche (by choice or construction) can eventuate in a change in the

467fundamental individualized niche. For example, individual oystercatchers specializing on

468either soft or hard prey types grow different bill shapes that facilitate efficient processing of

469their specific prey of choice (van de Pol et al. 2010). In this case, birds specializing on a

470particular resource (niche choice) adjust their phenotype (niche conformance) and thereby

471alter not only their realized but also, by altering their performance on different resources and

472thus the fitness function over the resources, their fundamental individualized niche.

473

4745. NC3 Mechanisms and Evolutionary Syntheses

475We began with the conflict between MS and EES. The evolutionary relevance of niche

476construction (in the wide sense, including all three NC3 mechanisms) forms a core point of

477difference between these schools. Our conception of the NC3 mechanisms as ecological and

478evolutionary mechanisms combines aspects from both schools and thus allows for a full

479acknowledgment of niche construction, as discussed in EES, without being in conflict with

480MS.

481Our take on the NC3 mechanisms accords largely with MS. Like proponents of MS, we think

482it is important to assess fitness consequences as they are relevant to long-term evolutionary

483process. We further assume that NC3 mechanisms have an evolutionary history and are

484suitably analyzed as adaptations to environmental conditions in the past (which may or may

485not correspond to current conditions).

22 486We nevertheless initiate a change in perspective, amending the population centered view of

487MS by focusing on individual activities, individual-level mechanisms and the individualized

488niche. We thereby take up the initiative from EES to analyze evolutionary processes on the

489level of individual activities, acknowledging their status as subjects that have an active role in

490evolution. Our focus on mechanisms that comprise a focal individual and its focal activity

491stresses the importance of individuals’ activities (including developmental processes) as

492modulators of the selective regime under which individuals live. We allow for novel activities

493arising by developmental processes that do not have a history of adaptation and may still be

494relevant to phenotype-environment matches, as it is put forward in EES (West-Eberhard

4952003).

496Both MS and EES are therefore embraced by our approach without internal conflict. We

497believe that this shows that the divide between MS and EES is not in all regards

498insurmountable. But our change in perspective does not propose a general answer to the

499question of whether organisms are subjects rather than mere objects of evolution. Instead, it

500invites solving this question empirically rather than dogmatically. Whether an individual’s

501activity drives evolution in a new direction does not depend on subscribing to a theoretical

502framework. It is rather something that can and should be studied empirically.

503We do not deny that crucial differences between MS and EES remain. The general focus of

504EES on the subject status of organisms in evolution will hardly be reconcilable with the gene-

505centered view of MS, even when MS can incorporate the subject view in empirically well-

506supported cases. On the other hand, the role of fitness in MS and the MS perspective on the

507fitness principle (Krohs 2006) are incompatible with the aim of EES to investigate

508evolutionary mechanisms without preconceptions about the way in which they drive

509evolution. There may be good reasons why the debate between MS and EES proponents is

23 510sometimes heated. Part of the debate can nevertheless be transformed into a constructive

511exchange and even partially resolved.

5126. Conclusions

513Organisms modify their niches in a number of different ways. We distinguish three different

514mechanisms by which individuals alter their niches: niche construction, niche choice, and

515niche conformance. The three mechanisms are distinguished by the focal activity performed

516by the focal individual. In niche construction the individual makes changes to the

517environment, in niche choice it selects an environment, and in niche conformance it adjusts

518its phenotype in response to the environment. All of the NC3 mechanisms change individuals’

519phenotype-environment match and their fitness. Because many NC3 mechanisms have

520evolved and persisted through natural selection, we expect them to generally improve

521phenotype-environment match and fitness.

522One interesting feature of NC3 mechanisms is the way they alter individualized niches. Niche

523construction and niche choice affect the realized niche, altering which possibilities of the

524fundamental individualized niche are realized in the environment the individual experiences.

525In contrast, niche conformance affects the fundamental niche, either changing the conditions

526under which the individual can survive and reproduce or affecting the individual’s

527performance on a given range of conditions. Because they are individual-level mechanisms

528which produce individualized niches, NC3 mechanisms highlight the potential for individual

529differences to affect how organisms alter their niches.

530Our framework recognizes the insights of EES that individuals are subjects of evolution,

531affecting the selective pressures to which they are exposed and the resources and information

532available for generating new behavioral variation. In addition, it accommodates approaches

24 533from MS by providing new material for understanding the evolution of niche-altering

534individual activities through natural selection.

535

536References 537Aaby BH, Ramsey G. 2019. Three Kinds of Niche Construction. The British Journal for the 538 Philosophy of Science online first: axz054.

539Archetti E. 2015. Three Kinds of Constructionism: The Role of Metaphor in the Debate over 540 Niche Constructionism. Biological Theory 10: 103–115.

541Bechtel W, Richardson RC. 1993. Discovering Complexity. Princeton University Press.

542Bolnick DI, Svanbäck R, Fordyce JA, Yang LH, Davis JM, Hulsey CD, Forister ML. 2003. 543 The Ecology of Individuals: Incidence and Implications of Individual Specialization. 544 The American Naturalist 161: 1–28.

545Brown CR, Brown MB. 2000. Heritable basis for choice of group size in a colonial bird. 546 Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 97: 14825–14830.

547Caizergues A, Ellison LN. 2002. Natal dispersal and its consequences in Black Grouse Tetrao 548 tetrix. Ibis 144: 478–487.

549Camacho C, Sanabria-Fernández A, Baños-Villalba A, Edelaar P. 2020. Experimental 550 evidence that matching habitat choice drives local adaptation in a wild population. 551 Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 287: 20200721.

552Charmantier A, McCleery RH, Cole LR, Perrins C, Kruuk LEB, Sheldon BC. 2008. Adaptive 553 Phenotypic Plasticity in Response to Climate Change in a Wild Bird Population. 554 Science 320: 800–803.

555Clark RM, Fewell JH. 2014. Social dynamics drive selection in cooperative associations of 556 ant queens. 25: 117–123.

557Craver CF, Darden L. 2013. In Search of Mechanisms. University of Chicago Press.

558Dall SRX, Bell AM, Bolnick DI, Ratnieks FLW. 2012. An of individual 559 differences. Ecology Letters 15: 1189–1198.

560Dawkins R. 1982. The Extended Phenotype. Freeman Press.

561Edelaar P, Bolnick DI. 2019. Appreciating the Multiple Processes Increasing Individual or 562 Population Fitness. Trends in Ecology & Evolution 34: 435–446.

563Glennan SS. 1996. Mechanisms and the nature of causation. Erkenntnis 44: 49–71.

564Glennan SS. 2017. The New Mechanical Philosophy. Oxford University Press.

25 565Grabowska J, Zięba G, Przybylski M, Smith C. 2019. The role of intraspecific in 566 the dispersal of an invasive fish. Freshwater Biology 64: 933–941.

567Haney BR, Fewell JH. 2018. Ecological drivers and reproductive consequences of non-kin 568 cooperation by ant queens. Oecologia 187: 643–655.

569Hansell M. 2000. Bird nests and construction behaviour. Cambridge University Press.

570Holt RD. 2009. Bringing the Hutchinsonian niche into the 21st century: Ecological and 571 evolutionary perspectives. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the 572 United States of America 106: 19659–19665.

573Hutchinson GE. 1957. Concluding Remarks. Cold Spring Harbour Symposia on Quantitative 574 Biology 22: 415–427.

575Illari P, Williamson J. 2013. In Defence of Activities. Journal for General Philosophy of 576 Science 44: 69–83.

577Kaiser MI. 2018. The Components and Boundaries of Mechanisms. Pages 116–130 in 578 Glennan SS and Illari P, eds. Routledge Handbook of Mechanisms and Mechanical 579 Philosophy. Routledge.

580Kaiser MI, Trappes R. forthcoming. Individual-level Mechanisms in Ecology and Evolution. 581 in Love AC, Baxter J, Bausman W, Lean O, and Waters CK, eds. From Biological 582 Practice to Scientific Metaphysics, vol. 23. University of Minnesota Press.

583Krohs U. 2006. The changeful fate of a groundbreaking insight: the Darwinian fitness 584 principle caught in different webs of belief. Yearbook for European Culture of 585 Science 2: 107–124.

586Laforsch C, Tollrian R. 2004. Inducible Defenses in Multipredator Environments: 587 Cyclomorphosis in Daphnia cucullata. Ecology 85: 2302–2311.

588Laland KN, Uller T, Feldman M, Sterelny K, Müller GB, Moczek A, Jablonka E, Odling- 589 Smee J. 2014. Does evolutionary theory need a rethink? Point: Yes, urgently. Nature 590 514: 161–164.

591Laland KN, Uller T, Feldman MW, Sterelny K, Müller GB, Moczek A, Jablonka E, Odling- 592 Smee J. 2015. The extended evolutionary synthesis: its structure, assumptions and 593 predictions. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 282: 20151019.

594Lewontin RC. 1983. The organism as the subject and object of evolution. Scientia 77: 63–82.

595Lewontin RC, Levins R. 1985. Biology under the influence: dialectical essays on ecology, 596 agriculture, and health. Harvard University Press.

597Machamer P, Darden L, Craver CF. 2000. Thinking about Mechanisms. Philosophy of 598 Science 67: 1–25.

599Mainwaring MC. 2017. Causes and Consequences of Intraspecific Variation in Nesting 600 Behaviors: Insights from Blue Tits and Great Tits. Frontiers in Ecology and Evolution 601 5: 39.

26 602Mainwaring MC, Hartley IR, Lambrechts MM, Deeming DC. 2014. The design and function 603 of birds’ nests. Ecology and Evolution 4: 3909–3928.

604Nussey DH, Wilson AJ, Brommer JE. 2007. The evolutionary ecology of individual 605 phenotypic plasticity in wild populations. Journal of Evolutionary Biology 20: 831– 606 844.

607Odling-Smee FJ, Laland KN, Feldman MW. 2003. Niche construction: the neglected process 608 in evolution. Princeton University Press.

609Overson R, Fewell J, Gadau J. 2016. Distribution and origin of intraspecific social variation 610 in the California harvester ant Pogonomyrmex californicus. Insectes Sociaux 63: 531– 611 541.

612Overson R, Gadau J, Clark RM, Pratt SC, Fewell JH. 2014. Behavioral transitions with the 613 evolution of cooperative nest founding by harvester ant queens. Behavioral Ecology 614 and Sociobiology 68: 21–30.

615Pigliucci M. 2001. Phenotypic Plasticity. Johns Hopkins University Press.

616Pigliucci M. 2005. Evolution of phenotypic plasticity: where are we going now? Trends in 617 Ecology & Evolution 20: 481–486.

618van de Pol M, Brouwer L, Ens BJ, Oosterbeek K, Tinbergen JM. 2010. Fluctuating selection 619 and the maintenance of individual and sex-specific diet specialization in free-living 620 oystercatchers. Evolution 64: 836–851.

621Ramm SA, Vizoso DB, Schärer L. 2012. Occurrence, costs and heritability of delayed selfing 622 in a free-living flatworm. Journal of Evolutionary Biology 25: 2559–2568.

623Rissing SW, Johnson RA, Martin JW. 2000. Colony Founding Behavior of Some Desert 624 Ants: Geographic Variation in Metrosis. Psyche: A Journal of Entomology 103: 95– 625 101.

626Roughgarden J. 1972. Evolution of Niche Width. The American Naturalist 106: 683–718.

627Violle C, Enquist BJ, McGill BJ, Jiang L, Albert CH, Hulshof C, Jung V, Messier J. 2012. 628 The return of the variance: intraspecific variability in ecology. Trends in 629 Ecology & Evolution 27: 244–252.

630West-Eberhard MJ. 2003. Developmental plasticity and evolution. Oxford University Press.

631Wray GA, Hoekstra HE, Futuyma DJ, Lenski RE, Mackay TFC, Schluter D, Strassmann JE. 632 2014. Does evolutionary theory need a rethink? Counterpoint: No, all is well. Nature 633 514: 161–164.

634Young AJ, Carlson AA, Monfort SL, Russell AF, Bennett NC, Clutton-Brock T. 2006. Stress 635 and the suppression of subordinate reproduction in cooperatively breeding meerkats. 636 Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 637 103: 12005–12010.

638

27