Grossi, G. (2014). a Module Is a Module Is a Module: Evolution of Modularity In

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Grossi, G. (2014). a Module Is a Module Is a Module: Evolution of Modularity In Running head: A MODULE IS A MODULE Published as: Grossi, G. (2014). A Module is a module is a module: Evolution of modularity in Evolutionary Psychology. Dialectical Anthropology, DOI: 10.1007/s10624-014-9355-0. A Module is a Module is a Module: Evolution of Modularity in Evolutionary Psychology Giordana Grossi State University of New York at New Paltz Address and correspondence Giordana Grossi Department of Psychology, SUNY New Paltz 600 Hawk Drive, New Paltz, NY 12561 ph: (845) 257-2674 fax: (845) 257-3474 email: [email protected] Acknowledgments: Many thanks to Alison Nash, Suzanne Kelly, Gowri Parameswaran, and two anonymous reviewers for their thoughtful comments and suggestions on an earlier version of this manuscript. 1 Abstract The concept of modularity has been central in behavioral and neural sciences since the publication of Fodor’s The Modularity of Mind (1983). Fodor strived to explain the functional architecture of the mind based on the distinction between modular and central systems. Modular systems were deemed to have certain architectural features, such as automaticity, encapsulation, and domain-specificity. Evolutionary psychologists have adopted the concept to characterize purportedly evolved human adaptations. In an influential paper, Barrett and Kurzban (2006) proposed a definition of modules purely in terms of functional specialization. It is here argued that such strategy marks a shift in Evolutionary Psychology’s theoretical emphasis, as it trivializes the investigation of proximate causes in evolutionary theorizing; furthermore, it leaves the door open to too much flexibility on what counts as evidence for purportedly evolved modules. 2 History and definition of modularity Modularity is a central concept in the cognitive and neural sciences. Generally speaking, modularity is the idea that the mind and the brain are organized in systems that are specialized to process specific types of information and that are functionally independent (Coltheart, 1999). The concept became predominant in psychology after the publication of Fodor’s The Modularity of Mind (1983). Fodor’s (1983) hypothesis about the functional architecture of the mind was proposed to explain the types of psychological mechanisms underlying the different facts of mental life (e.g., sensation, perception, volition, and learning). In his account, the architecture of the mind is divided into modular and central systems. Modular systems include perceptual (or input) and linguistic mechanisms, whereas central systems pertain to decision-making systems, knowledge, and beliefs. The latter systems were deemed not to be modular and cut across a variety of cognitive domains. Without clearly defining the term “module,” Fodor associated modular systems with specific characteristics, such as automaticity, informational encapsulation, and domain-specificity: - Automaticity: A system was conceptualized as automatic if its mechanisms are to be “obligatorily applied” (p. 53), such as those involved in spoken word recognition in native speakers of a language: even when participants are asked to focus on low-level (acoustic-phonetic) characteristics of speech, it is impossible to turn off word recognition mechanisms. 3 - Informational encapsulation: A system was deemed to be encapsulated if it is less permeable to background information, contextual factors, or beliefs than other systems. Fodor illustrated this property by discussing the mechanisms responsible for visual illusions. In the Müller-Lyer illusion, the line flanked by two arrow tails looks longer than the line flanked by two arrowheads. This perception persists even after the viewer is informed that the two lines are identical in length. - Domain-specificity: Modules are specialized, in the sense that only a restricted class of stimuli has access to them. For example, the input systems involved in recognizing speech are different from the auditory systems involved in the recognition of non- speech sounds (Fodor, 1983). Modular systems tend to have other related characteristics, such as being hardwired (i.e., “associated with specific, localized, and elaborately structured neural systems,” p. 37) and innate (i.e., they “develop according to specific, endogenously determined patterns under the impact of environmental releasers”, p. 100). According to Fodor, modules needed not share all these characteristics; furthermore, modularity is a matter of degree. Fodor’s speculative view of the mind, born within philosophy, prompted a considerable amount of research and discussion among cognitive psychologists and neuroscientists. Much of the empirical research focused on determining how perceptual and linguistic systems function and whether they exhibit characteristics such as encapsulation, automaticity, and domain-specificity. Empirical findings revealed a complex picture in which not even perceptual systems turned out to exhibit some of the 4 defining characteristics of modularity. For example, some charged that input systems do not exhibit strict encapsulation because their functioning is modulated by attention (e.g., Wojciulik, Kanwisher, & Driver, 1998) or higher-level cognitive processes (Farah, 1994). Furthermore, behavioral studies had already shown that perceptual mechanisms are modulated by contextual factors and information from other sensory modalities. For example, in the McGurk effect (McGurk & MacDonald, 1976), the auditory perception of a syllable (e.g., /ba/) changes when the syllable is visually presented with the face of a person pronouncing another sound (e.g., /ga/): in this case, participants hear /da/. These and other empirical results led to a more refined understanding of how the brain is organized and functions, as I will discuss later. Evolutionary Psychology1 and modularity In the late 1980s, the concept of modularity was borrowed by a group of evolutionary psychologists (e.g., John Tooby, Leda Cosmides, Steven Pinker, David Buss) and reframed in terms of evolved adaptations. In their view, the human mind is comprised of numerous specialized modules (or “mini-computers”) that have evolved under selective pressure to solve recurrent problems in humans’ ancestral past (Cosmides & Tooby, 1997, p. 11). Therefore, the Evolutionary Psychology (EP henceforth) version of modules rests on the assumptions that they are supported by dedicated neural circuits, shaped by natural selection, and genetically specified (Pinker, 1997, p. 21). Examples of 1 The term “Evolutionary Psychology” will be used in this paper to denote the thought of an influential group of researchers including, among others, Leda Cosmides, John Tooby, David Buss, and Steven Pinker. It is not to be confused with “evolutionary psychology” as the general field of inquiry. Please see the Introduction to this issue for more information. 5 modules include face recognition, tool-use, fear, social-exchange, kin-oriented motivation, child-care, social-inference, sexual-attraction, friendship, grammar acquisition, and theory of mind (Tooby & Cosmides, 1992, p. 113). A number of assumptions are made regarding these modules. For example, they are domain-specific, that is, “relatively well-engineered for solving ancestral adaptive problems” (Cosmides & Tooby, 1994, p. 88). This assumption relies on the claim that such problems cannot be solved by domain-general mechanisms. Evolutionary psychologists argue that different problems require sensitivity to different types of information and different solutions. For example, selecting food and selecting a mate typically lead to different solutions; therefore, they rely on different, and specialized, mechanisms (Confer et al., 2010). Another assumption is that the number of specialized modules has increased in humans, compared to other primates and mammals, and this increase ensures humans’ flexible and complex behavior. In this context, modules are “pre-specified” structures, as they contain information about the world: “The more a system initially "knows" about the world and its persistent characteristics, and the more evolutionarily proven "skills" it starts out with, the more it can learn, the more problems it can solve, the more it can accomplish.” (Tooby & Cosmides, 1992, p. 113) Evolutionary psychologists’ focus is on a computational, or functional, analysis of behavior, based on Marr’s distinction between levels of description (Cosmides & Tooby, 2003; Tooby & Cosmides, 1994). In his influential book Vision (1982/2010), Marr 6 posited that informational systems can be analyzed at three different levels of description: computational, or functional (what a system does and why; the problem that the system solves); algorithmic/representational (how a system does what it does, what representations and processes it uses), and implementational (how a system is neurally/physically implemented). Marr considered the three levels of description “rather loosely related” (2010, p. 25) and constrained by different issues (independence among levels)2. For this reason, for some phenomena, there might be no unitary theory connecting all three levels. By privileging a computational analysis of behavior, evolutionary psychologists adopt reverse engineering to identify traits that have been advantageous (in terms of reproductive fitness) during human evolution in “ancestral times”. These “design features” are identified based on hypotheses concerning the problems faced by our ancestors and speculations about the ancestral environments in which they lived. Design features, which characterize evolved
Recommended publications
  • The Folk Psychology of Souls
    BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (2006) 29, 453–498 Printed in the United States of America The folk psychology of souls Jesse M. Bering Institute of Cognition and Culture, Queen’s University Belfast, Belfast BT7 1NN, United Kingdom. [email protected] qub.ac.uk/icc http://www.qub.ac.uk/schools/InstituteofCognitionCulture/Staff/ JesseMBering/ Abstract: The present article examines how people’s belief in an afterlife, as well as closely related supernatural beliefs, may open an empirical backdoor to our understanding of the evolution of human social cognition. Recent findings and logic from the cognitive sciences contribute to a novel theory of existential psychology, one that is grounded in the tenets of Darwinian natural selection. Many of the predominant questions of existential psychology strike at the heart of cognitive science. They involve: causal attribution (why is mortal behavior represented as being causally related to one’s afterlife? how are dead agents envisaged as communicating messages to the living?), moral judgment (why are certain social behaviors, i.e., transgressions, believed to have ultimate repercussions after death or to reap the punishment of disgruntled ancestors?), theory of mind (how can we know what it is “like” to be dead? what social-cognitive strategies do people use to reason about the minds of the dead?), concept acquisition (how does a common-sense dualism interact with a formalized socio-religious indoctrination in childhood? how are supernatural properties of the dead conceptualized by young minds?), and teleological reasoning (why do people so often see their lives as being designed for a purpose that must be accomplished before they perish? how do various life events affect people’s interpretation of this purpose?), among others.
    [Show full text]
  • An Adaptationist Framework for Personality Science
    European Journal of Personality, Eur. J. Pers. (2020) Published online in Wiley Online Library (wileyonlinelibrary.com) DOI: 10.1002/per.2292 An Adaptationist Framework for Personality Science AARON W. LUKASZEWSKI1*, DAVID M.G. LEWIS2, PATRICK K. DURKEE3, AARON N. SELL4, DANIEL SZNYCER5 and DAVID M. BUSS3 1Department of Psychology, California State University, Fullerton, CA USA 2School of Psychology and Exercise Science, Murdoch University, Perth, WA Australia 3Department of Psychology, University of Texas at Austin, Austin, TX USA 4Psychology and Criminology Department, Heidelberg University, Tiffin, OH USA 5Department of Psychology, University of Montreal, Montreal, QC Canada Abstract: The field of personality psychology aspires to construct an overarching theory of human nature and indi- vidual differences: one that specifies the psychological mechanisms that underpin both universal and variable aspects of thought, emotion, and behaviour. Here, we argue that the adaptationist toolkit of evolutionary psychology provides a powerful meta-theory for characterizing the psychological mechanisms that give rise to within-person, between- person, and cross-cultural variations. We first outline a mechanism-centred adaptationist framework for personality science, which makes a clear ontological distinction between (i) psychological mechanisms designed to generate be- havioural decisions and (ii) heuristic trait concepts that function to perceive, describe, and influence others behaviour and reputation in everyday life. We illustrate the utility
    [Show full text]
  • A Critical Review of Three Theories for Music's Origin a Thesis Presented
    A Critical Review of Three Theories for Music’s Origin A thesis presented to the faculty of the College of Arts and Sciences of Ohio University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree Master of Arts Kevin W. Kondik March 2010 © 2010 Kevin W. Kondik. All Rights Reserved. 2 This thesis titled A Critical Review of Three Theories for Music’s Origin by KEVIN W. KONDIK has been approved for the Department of Philosophy and the College of Arts and Sciences by Arthur Zucker Associate Professor of Philosophy Benjamin M. Ogles Dean, College of Arts and Sciences 3 ABSTRACT KONDIK, KEVIN, W.,, M.A., March 2010, Philosophy A Critical Review of Three Theories for Music’s Origin (82 pp.) Director of Thesis: Arthur Zucker This thesis compares three theories which debate whether or not the trait of music is constitutive of a biological adaptation. Steven Pinker advances a view that music cannot be an adaptation because making or responding to music utilizes faculties which evolved for other reasons. On the next view, Geoffrey Miller claims that music is a sexually selected trait which evolved primarily to seduce potential mates. Finally, Ian Cross argues that music can be seen as an extension of juvenile behaviors into adulthood and has efficacy in the consolidation of bonds within a group. I conclude that all three theories are insufficient as an explanation of why music evolved in the hominid lineage. The main reasons why these theories all fail is they all rely upon a speculative historical reconstructions and imprecise definitions of music.
    [Show full text]
  • Evolutionary Psychology and Emotions: a Species-Typical Computational Design
    THEORIA ET HISTORIA SCIENTIARUM, VOL. XVI Ed. Nicolaus Copernicus University 2019 DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.12775/ths.2019.002 Domenica Bruni Department of Ancient and Modern Civilizations University of Messina [email protected] Evolutionary Psychology and Emotions: A Species-Typical Computational Design Abstract. Evolutionary psychology is a major naturalistic approach to knowledge. It begins from a fundamental observation: the human brain is the product of natural selection trying to solve adaptive problems faced by our hunter-gatherer ancestors. In this paper, I describe this approach and focus on the emotions, an important aspect of mental life. Emotions, I argue, are a superordinate program that evolved to coordinate the activity of other programs in the solution of typical adaptive problems. Keywords: evolutionary psychology; mind; emotions; natural selection; superordinate program; cognition. Introduction The aim of this essay is twofold: to describe evolutionary psychology (EP), one of the main naturalistic approaches to knowledge in today’s cultural panorama, and to examine the emotions as an applicative field of EP. EP is an ambitious research program (Symons, 1987; Cosmides & Tooby, 1992; Tooby & Cosmides, 1992; Buss, 1995; Pinker, 1997; Adenzato & Meini, 2006; Bruni, 2017) aimed at contributing to the naturalization of the human sciences. According to EP, human cognitive architecture can be understood using the principles of evolutionary biology. All our natural capacities— language, vision, sexual attraction, fear, aggression, moral judgments— are possible thanks to a complex information system produced by natural 30 Domenica Bruni selection, that is, the human brain. Identifying natural selection as a unifying empirical and theoretical construct of the human sciences, EP turns its attention to the brain as a biological system responsible for heterogeneous cognitive skills and tries to furnish models for these skills’ functioning and phylogenetic history.
    [Show full text]
  • Reconceptualizing Evolutionary Psychology
    REVIEW ARTICLE published: 12 August 2014 doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00867 From computers to cultivation: reconceptualizing evolutionary psychology Louise Barrett1*, Thomas V. Pollet 2 and Gert Stulp 3 1 Department of Psychology, University of Lethbridge, Lethbridge, AB, Canada 2 Department of Social and Organizational Psychology, VU University Amsterdam, Amsterdam, Netherlands 3 Department of Population Health, London School of Hygiene and Tropical Medicine, London, UK Edited by: Does evolutionary theorizing have a role in psychology? This is a more contentious issue Danielle Sulikowski, Charles Sturt than one might imagine, given that, as evolved creatures, the answer must surely be University, Australia yes. The contested nature of evolutionary psychology lies not in our status as evolved Reviewed by: beings, but in the extent to which evolutionary ideas add value to studies of human Ben Colagiuri, University of New South Wales, Australia behavior, and the rigor with which these ideas are tested. This, in turn, is linked to the Karola Stotz, Macquarie University, framework in which particular evolutionary ideas are situated. While the framing of the Australia current research topic places the brain-as-computer metaphor in opposition to evolutionary *Correspondence: psychology, the most prominent school of thought in this field (born out of cognitive Louise Barrett, Department of psychology, and often known as the Santa Barbara school) is entirely wedded to the Psychology, University of Lethbridge, 4401 University Drive West, computational theory of mind as an explanatory framework. Its unique aspect is to argue Lethbridge, AB T1K 3M4, Canada that the mind consists of a large number of functionally specialized (i.e., domain-specific) e-mail: [email protected] computational mechanisms, or modules (the massive modularity hypothesis).
    [Show full text]
  • States in Mind Anthony C. Lopez, Rose Mcdermott, and Michael
    States in Mind States in Mind Anthony C. Lopez, Rose McDermott, and Evolution, Coalitional Psychology, and Michael Bang International Politics Petersen One of the most com- monly studied puzzles in international politics is the recurrence of coalitional competition and aggression between political groups such as states. Indeed, this pattern constitutes an enduring and central feature of all politics. Yet de- spite the tragic endurance of this leitmotif throughout history, its manifestation varies through time and space. Some wars are fought for honor or revenge, whereas others are ignited for mere opportunism or as a consequence of vari- ous misperceptions, whatever their source. We argue that evolutionary theory provides a theoretical framework that can explain both the stubborn endur- ance and dynamic diversity of coalitional behavior. Debate on the relevance of “human nature” and biological factors for explaining political behavior is not new.1 Yet the comprehensive value of evo- lutionary theory for explaining important aspects of international politics has not been adequately explicated. As we discuss below, this has in part been a consequence of general skepticism about the validity and scope of evolution- ary theory for explaining political behavior. We argue, however, that evolu- tionary psychology can generate falsiªable ex ante predictions that are of central interest to the study of international politics, and we offer several hy- potheses derived from this model to illustrate the depth of this approach. Evo- lutionary psychologists have already generated a large body of work that suggests that the human brain contains webs of psychological mechanisms, or adaptations, each designed to operate in domains relevant to modern politics, and which emerged as a product of natural selection.
    [Show full text]
  • Psychological Adaptation to Human Sperm Competition
    Evolution and Human Behavior 23 (2002) 123–138 Psychological adaptation to human sperm competition Todd K. Shackelforda,*, Gregory J. LeBlanca, Viviana A. Weekes-Shackelforda, April L. Bleske-Rechekb, Harald A. Eulerc, Sabine Hoierc aDivision of Psychology, Florida Atlantic University, 2912 College Avenue, Davie, FL 33314, USA bVanderbilt University, Nashville, TN, USA cUniversity of Kassel, Kassel, Germany Received 21 December 1999; received in revised form 23 February 2000; accepted 6 September 2001 Abstract Sperm competition occurs when the sperm of two or more males simultaneously occupy the reproductive tract of a female and compete to fertilize an egg. We used a questionnaire to investigate psychological responses to the risk of sperm competition for 194 men in committed, sexual relationships in the United States and in Germany. As predicted, a man who spends a greater (relative to a man who spends a lesser) proportion of time apart from his partner since the couple’s last copulation reported (a) that his partner is more attractive, (b) that other men find his partner more attractive, (c) greater interest in copulating with his partner, and (d) that his partner is more sexually interested in him. All effects were independent of total time since the couple’s last copulation and the man’s relationship satisfaction. Discussion addresses two failed predictions and directions for future work. D 2002 Elsevier Science Inc. All rights reserved. Keywords: Sperm competition; Evolutionary psychology; Human sexuality 1. Introduction Sperm competition occurs when the sperm of two or more males simultaneously occupy the reproductive tract of a female and compete to fertilize an egg (Baker & Bellis, 1995; * Corresponding author.
    [Show full text]
  • The Psychological Foundations of Culture Generation -Of Culture
    From: The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary psychology The Psychological Foundations of Culture generation -of culture J. Barkow, L. Cosmides, JOHNTOOBY AND LEDA COSMIDES 1992. New York: Oxford INTRODUCTION: THE UNITY OF SCIENCE One of the strengths of scientific inquiry is that it can progress with any mixture of empiri- cism, intuition, and formal theory that suits the convenience of the investigator. Many sci- ences develop for a time as exercises in description and empirical generalization. Only later do they acquire reasoned connectionswithin themselves and with other branches of knowl- edge. Many things were scientifically known of human anatomy and the motions ofthe plan- ets before they were scientifically explained. -GEORGE WILLIAMS, Adaptation and Natural Selection Disciplines such as astronomy, chemistry, physics, geology, and biology have devel- oped a robust combination of logical coherence, causal description, explanatory power, and testability, and have become examples of how reliable and deeply satisfy- ing human knowledge can become. Their extraordinary florescence throughout this century has resulted in far more than just individual progress within each field. These disciplines are becoming integrated into an increasingly seamless system of intercon- nected knowledge and remain nominally separated more out of educational conve- nience and institutional inertia than because of any genuine ruptures in the underlying unity of the achieved knowledge. In fact, this development is only an acceleration of the process of conceptual unification that has been building in science since the Renaissance. For example, Galileo and Newton broke down the then rigid (and now forgotten) division between the celestial and the terrestrial-two domains that for- merly had been considered metaphysically separate-showing that the same processes and principles applied to both.
    [Show full text]
  • The Spandrels of Santa Barbara? a New Perspective on the Peri-Ovulation Paradigm
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Stirling Online Research Repository The spandrels of Santa Barbara? A new perspective on the peri-ovulation paradigm Running title: Evolution of menstrual cycle-related perception Jan Havlíček1,2*, Kelly D. Cobey3,4, Louise Barrett5, Kateřina Klapilová1,2, and S. Craig Roberts3 1Charles University, Prague, Czech Republic 2National Institute of Mental Health, Klecany, Czech Republic 3School of Natural Sciences, University of Stirling, UK 4Laboratory of Experimental and Comparative Ethology (LEEC), University of Paris 13, France 5University of Lethbridge, Alberta, Canada *Author for correspondence: Jan Havlíček, Faculty of Science, Charles University; Viničná 7, 128 44 Prague 2, Czech Republic. Phone: +420 221 95 1853; E-mail [email protected] Abstract Numerous recent studies document peri-ovulatory increases in women’s physical attractiveness and in their preferences for certain male traits, which appear to be linked to cyclical fluctuation in levels of ovarian hormones. Changes in physical traits are subtle, leading to the widespread conclusion that cues of ovulation are adaptively concealed. It has been argued that concealment enables women to pursue a mixed-mating strategy characterized by pair-bonding with opportunistic extra-pair copulation with high quality mates when conception is possible. Men’s preferences for peri-ovulatory cues and women’s cyclical preference shifts are thus also argued to reflect distinct psychological adaptations. Here, we re-interpret the evidence for each of these putative adaptations and argue that cyclic changes need not result from incomplete concealment of ovulatory status. We also emphasize that ovarian hormone levels underpin between-individual differences in both women’s attractiveness and their mate preferences, which influence the sexes’ mate choice decisions.
    [Show full text]
  • The Role of Evolutionary Explanations in Psychology
    A Natural History of Mind The role of Evolutionary explanations in psychology By Russi! Durrant A thesis submitted in fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in psychology. Department ofPsychology The University of Canterbury 1998 Acknowledgements I should like to thank firstly my two supervisors Brian Haig and Jim Pollard, for their relaxed supervisory styles and their encouraging and thoughtful comments on my work. I should also like to thank all those who contributed in various ways to the completion of this project. My especial thanks to Jo, Alice, Chris, Simon, Jonnyand James. Finally, my thanks to Sco and Pat for putting everything in perspective. Contents Introduction 1 (1) Explanation, theory appraisal and the growth of science: A realist perspective 7 The aims ofscience 8 A Realist approach to science 12 Anti-realism 14 The challenge from empiricism 15 The challenge from relativism 16 The challenge from the history ofscience 18 Realism defended 19 The status of non-observables 19 The role ofsuper-empirical values 20 A closer look at the theory dependence ofobservation 22 Rescuing truth: an optimistic reappraisal of the history ofscience 25 Theory appraisal and the role of global research programmes in science 27 Scientific research programmes 29 Features ofglobal research programmes in science 35 Internal characteristics 35 External characteristics 39 Theory appraisal in science 42 Relationships between theories 50 The nature of scientific explanation 51 The received view 51 Problems with the received
    [Show full text]
  • The Concept of Adaptation : Interdisciplinary Scope and Involvement in Climate Change
    S.A.P.I.EN.S Surveys and Perspectives Integrating Environment and Society 3.1 | 2010 Vol.3 / n°1 The concept of adaptation : interdisciplinary scope and involvement in climate change Guillaume Simonet Eric Duchemin (éd.) Édition électronique URL : http://journals.openedition.org/sapiens/997 ISSN : 1993-3819 Éditeur Institut Veolia Référence électronique Guillaume Simonet, « The concept of adaptation : interdisciplinary scope and involvement in climate change », S.A.P.I.EN.S [En ligne], 3.1 | 2010, mis en ligne le 19 juillet 2010, consulté le 23 octobre 2020. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/sapiens/997 Licence Creative Commons S . EN 10 . I 20 . 1 P . ISSUE Disambiguation A . 3 The concept of adaptation: S interdisciplinary scope and VOLUME involvement in climate change Guillaume Simonet Chaire d’études sur les écosystèmes urbains, Institut des sciences de l’environnement, Université du Québec à Montréal, C.P. 8888, Succ. Centre-ville – Montréal (Qc) Canada H3C 3P8; Laboratoire dynamiques sociales et recomposition des espaces, Paris Ouest-Nanterre, LADYSS, Bat K, 200 av. de la République, 92001 Nanterre Cedex. Ouranos, 550 Sherbrooke Ouest, 19e étage, Tour Ouest, Montréal (Québec) - Canada, H3A1B9 This paper is a revised version of an article originally published in French by Natures, Sciences, Sociétés (Simonet, 2009). Correspondence to: [email protected] Adaptation refers to both a process and its outcome, leading to many interpretations and much debate. The origin of this semantic duality is related to the epistemological rupture that occurred during the 19 th century when it collided with the emerging Theory of Evolution and established Creationism. The temporal scale of Evolution is an abstract concept that is outside the realm of immediate human perception, which makes the adaptation debate all the more complex.
    [Show full text]
  • Elements of Change 1. Evolutionary Psychology
    ELEMENTS OF CHANGE 1. EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY 1.1. Scope Evolutionary Psychology (EP) is an approach in the social and natural sciences that examines psychological traits such as memory, perception, and language from a modern evolutionary perspective. It seeks to identify which human psychological traits are evolved adaptations that is, the functional products of natural selection or sexual selection. Adaptationist thinking about physiological mechanisms, such as the heart, lungs, and immune system, is common in evolutionary biology. Some evolutionary psychologists apply the same thinking to psychology, arguing that the mind has a modular structure similar to that of the body, with different modular adaptations serving different functions. Evolutionary psychologists argue that much of human behavior is the output of psychological adaptations that evolved to solve recurrent problems in human ancestral environments. The adaptationist approach is steadily increasing as an influence in the general field of psychology. Evolutionary psychologists suggest that EP is not simply a subdiscipline of psychology, but that evolutionary theory can provide a foundational, metatheoretical framework that integrates the entire field of psychology, in the same way it has for biology. Evolutionary psychologists hold that behaviors or traits that occur universally in all cultures are good candidates for evolutionary adaptations. The theories and findings of EP have applications in many fields, including economics, environment, health, law, management, psychiatry, politics, and literature. Controversies concerning EP involve questions of testability, cognitive and evolutionary assumptions (such as modular functioning of the brain, and large uncertainty about the ancestral environment), importance of non-genetic and non-adaptive explanations, as well as political and ethical issues due to interpretations of research results.
    [Show full text]