Christian Thomasius' Psychology of Prejudices

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Christian Thomasius' Psychology of Prejudices “Christian Thomasius’ Psychology of Prejudices” Seminar on “Anthropology” Sixth International Congress on Enlightenment Brussels, Belgium July 25-27, 1983 Karl J. Fink Few critics of the eighteenth century would disagree with the position given to Thomasius as “father of the German Enlightenment,” a position gained through social and academic reform, and yet few would recognize the close parallel between this intellectual awakening in Germany of the eighteenth century and the one in England of the seventeenth century.1 Although it is commonly known that Thomasius relied heavily on Locke and Hobbes for his thoughts on social reform, there is even stronger kinship to the efforts of Francis Bacon (1561-1626).2 It was in the late sixteenth century that Bacon outlined the biases inherent in the studies in the natural sciences much in the same way that Thomasius analyzed the prejudices basic to study in the emerging behavioral sciences of the eighteenth century. Indeed, the critical thoughts of these two individuals, one in the natural sciences and the other in the social sciences, are strikingly similar and, while it is not the goal of this paper to do a comparative analysis of Bacon and Thomasius, it is important at the outset to establish this parallel, for Thomasius’ critical examination of human behavior sets the stage for German studies into the anthropological 1 White, Andrew D., Seven Great Statesmen in the Warfare of Humanity with Unreason (New York: The Century Co., 1915), pp. 113-161, lists Thomasius as the “second of the three great reformers in Germany,” following Luther and preceding Lessing, p. 161, while German critics have traditionally viewed Thomasius as representative of German Enlightenment, “das Licht der neuen Geistes freiheit,” Hermann Hettner, Geschichte der deutchen Literatur (Leipzig: Paul List, 1928), p. 56. More recently critics have urged a closer look at the writings of Thomasius for their seminal value for the generation of German thinkers following in the late eighteenth century, one that would explain why he was thought of as “the prophet of a new dawn, as the spiritual father of what was best in the intellectual tradition of the German Enlightenment,” F.M. Barnard, “Thomasius’ Practical Philosophy,” Journal of the History of Ideas, 32 (1971), p.222. 2 Barnard, “Thomasius’ Practical Philosophy,” (1971), dismisses earlier scholarly opinion that Thomasius was an eclectic, arguing that “in most if not all thinkers, originality is largely a matter of degree,” p.222. nature of man.3 It is in this context that the index of British empiricism in Thomasius’ writings have significance for the development of eighteenth century theories of anthropological study. Thomasius’ views of man, language, and culture have intellectual affinity to Locke but are expressed in the spirit of Baconian reform and it is at this level of the history of the behavioral sciences that Thomasius plays a role. There is another striking parallel from the turn of the century worth noting by way of an introduction to a study of epistemological questions asked by Thomasius. Although one can find in ancient writings thoughts on the nature of man and culture, such study is generally considered an innovation beginning with Giambattista Vico’s (1668- 1744) Scienza nuova (1725), a book which in many ways touches on most fields of the social sciences, including anthropology and psychology as well as history and culture.4 Yet it is a book which followed by two or three decades Thomasius’ essays on prejudice and on a psychology of man. In fact Thomasius perceived his work in social psychology to be pioneering for by the end of the seventeenth century he had already written several lessays on the science of man and on specifically the means by which we can objectively 3 The protestant basis and the religious appeal in Bacon’s effort to objectify scientific investigation into nature, in his belief that “knowledge of God included the knowledge of self – of one’s ignorance, vanity, and corruption,” Gary Deason, The Philosophy of a Lord Chancellor: Religion, Science, and Politics in the Work of Francis Bacon (to be published), p. 242), is also central to Thomasius’ own effort to objectify knowledge about man. See also Hans M. Wolff, “Die Wiederentdeckung des servum arbitrium: Thomasius,” in: Die Weltanschauung der Deutschen Aufklärung (Bern: Francke, 1949), pp. 27-48, for close examination of the Protestant origins of Thomasius’ deep pessimism concerning the human condition and the progression to the view that the human will free of social influence can only be achieved through inner purity and individual perfection, p. 44. 4 See particularly Book I, “Establishment of Principles,” in Giambattista Vico, The New Science, T. Bergin and M. Fisch, transl., 3rd ed. (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1968), p. 27-106, which outlines the criterion of reason by which human institutions and cultures evolved and in which resides the “agreement between the vulgar wisdom of all lawgivers and the esoteric wisdom of the philosophers of greatest repute,” p. 106. For an historical survey of anthropological theories prior to Vico see Margaret T. Hodgen, Early Anthropology in the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries (University of Pennsylvania Press, 1971), pp. 17-78). 2 study human attitudes, biases, beliefs, emotions and feelings.5 The questions which this study addresses are then focused on Thomasius’ development of critical tools for the analysis of human nature, tools which he developed as a method for the study of particularly socialization processes, processes which are conditioned by authorities in cultural and cross-cultural relationships. His views, it should be pointed out, had a double impact, first on the understanding of psychological problems in the relationship of dominant and recessive cultures and, secondly, in bringing German culture a step forward in its maturation as a society independent of foreign dominance and independent in its scientific and literary achievements.6 This study deals only with the first of these two contributions, with his examination of psychological barriers to cultural development. The second, namely his contribution to the maturation of German culture, has previously been stated in broad terms of Enlightenment philosophy. Thomasius’ essay on “De Praejudiciis oder von den Vorurteilen” first appeared as a lecture in 1689 at the University of Leipzig.7 It was offered to students as an alternative to lectures in which he planned to defend himself against the accusations made by an orientalist, August Pfeiffer, accusations that he was an atheist. But the University of Leipzig did not allow him to give these lectures, and so he decided upon a series of 5 Wolf, Erik, Grosse Rechtsdenker der deutschen Geistesgeschichte, 4th ed. (Tübingen: Mohr, 1963), devotes chapter ten to Thomasius, recognizing that “Die Anthropologie des Thomsius, beschränkte sich demnoch auf eine psychologische Analyse des Menschen als Einselwesen in seinen Beziehungen zur Umwelt,” p. 399. Yet it seems Thomasius’ science of man is hardly known outside of the German scholarly tradition for recent anglo-american histories of the field do not mention early German theories of anthropology as for example in the chapter on the Enlightenment in Marvin Harris, The Rise of Anthropological Theory (New York: Crowell, 1968), pp. 8-52. 6 Wolf, Grosse Rechtsdenker (1963), felt that Thomasius’ anthropology as well as his epistemology and ethics combined to form a psychology: “Die Grundlage der Anthropologie, Erkenntnislehre und Ethik des Thomasius bildete demfolge die Psychologie,” p. 398. Max Dessoir, Geschichte der Neueren Deutschen Psychologie, 2nd ed. (Berlin: Duncker, 1902), Vol. 1, p. 59, also recognized in Thomasius’ study of man a unification of ethics and psychology. 7 Thomasius, Christian, “De praejudiciis oder von den Vorurteilen,” Die Einleitung zur Vernunftlehre, in: Aus der Frühzeit der Deutschen Aufklärung, ed. Fritz Brüggemann (Darmstadt: Wiss. Buchgesellschaft, 1972), pp. 30-42. All translations into English are by the present author. 3 lectures illuminating his particular dilemma, lectures which dealt with the interference of prejudices in social and intellectual behavior. The University’s censorship of his defense against accusations of atheism was fortunate, for the lecture on prejudices became the cornerstone of his study of human behavior in cross-cultural settings. The lecture therefore forms the basis of his role as “father of the German Enlightenment.”8 Thomasius distinguished between two kinds of prejudices, the prejudice of authority (autoritatis) and that of precipitancy (praecipitantiae), or the prejudices of appearance (Ansehen) and hastiness (Übereilung).9 Thomasisus’ primary concern was analysis of man’s deference to authority and it was this investigation into the psychology of human behavior that became a challenge to all established corners of social and political life in the early phase of Grman Enlightenment thought. Following the lectures in 1689 he twice published his thoughts on the prejudices of the human mind, once in 1691 in a short and concise version found in the last chapter of his Einleitung zu der Vernunftlehre and again in 1696 in the first chapter of Ausübung der Sittenlehre where he argued that the sources of these two prejudices are found in the corruption of the human will, which he asserted is subject to further prejudices, the prejudices of imitation (Nachahmung) and impatience (Ungeduld).10 And so Thomasius felt
Recommended publications
  • Philosophy and German Literature –
    PHILOSOPHY AND GERMAN LITERATURE – EDITED BY NICHOLAS SAUL University of Liverpool PUBLISHED BY THE PRESS SYNDICATE OF THE UNIVERSITY OF CAMBRIDGE The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge, United Kingdom CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge CBRU,UK West th Street, New York, NY -, USA Williamstown Road, Port Melbourne, VIC , Australia Ruiz de Alarc´on , Madrid, Spain Dock House, The Waterfront, Cape Town , South Africa http://www.cambridge.org C Cambridge University Press This book is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions ofrelevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction ofany part may take place without the written permission ofCambridge University Press. First published Printed in the United Kingdom at the University Press, Cambridge Typeface Baskerville Monotype /. pt. System LATEX ε [TB] A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Library of Congress Cataloguing in Publication data Philosophy and German literature – / edited by Nicholas Saul. p. cm. – (Cambridge studies in German) Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN --- . German literature – History and criticism. Literature and philosophy. Philosophy, German. I. Saul, Nicholas. II. Series. PT .M . –dc ISBN hardback Contents Contributors page viii Acknowledgements x List of abbreviations xi Introduction: German literature and philosophy Nicholas Saul Criticism and experience: philosophy and literature in the German Enlightenment John A.McCarthy The pursuit ofthe subject: literature as critic and perfecter ofphilosophy – Nicholas Saul Two realisms: German literature and philosophy – John Walker Modernism and the self – Ritchie Robertson The subjects ofcommunity: aspiration, memory,resistance – Russell A.Berman Coming to terms with the past in postwar literature and philosophy Robert C.Holub Bibliography Index vii CHAPTER ONE Criticism and experience: philosophy and literature in the German Enlightenment John A.
    [Show full text]
  • Natural Law and the Scottish Enlightenment Knud Haakonssen
    Document generated on 09/30/2021 4:14 a.m. Man and Nature L'homme et la nature Natural Law and the Scottish Enlightenment Knud Haakonssen Volume 4, 1985 URI: https://id.erudit.org/iderudit/1011836ar DOI: https://doi.org/10.7202/1011836ar See table of contents Publisher(s) Canadian Society for Eighteenth-Century Studies / Société canadienne d'étude du dix-huitième siècle ISSN 0824-3298 (print) 1927-8810 (digital) Explore this journal Cite this article Haakonssen, K. (1985). Natural Law and the Scottish Enlightenment. Man and Nature / L'homme et la nature, 4, 47–80. https://doi.org/10.7202/1011836ar Copyright © Canadian Society for Eighteenth-Century Studies / Société This document is protected by copyright law. Use of the services of Érudit canadienne d'étude du dix-huitième siècle, 1985 (including reproduction) is subject to its terms and conditions, which can be viewed online. https://apropos.erudit.org/en/users/policy-on-use/ This article is disseminated and preserved by Érudit. Érudit is a non-profit inter-university consortium of the Université de Montréal, Université Laval, and the Université du Québec à Montréal. Its mission is to promote and disseminate research. https://www.erudit.org/en/ 4. Natural Law and the Scottish Enlightenment Natural law ideas are a well known feature of both ancient and medieval thought, and it has always been a popular scholarly pastime to debate where the 'modern' school of natural law begins — a particular favourite being the question whether Hugo Grotius was the last of the scholastics or the first of the moderns. Much of this debate is fruitless, but it has nevertheless made clear that there is a range of issues over which Grotius' standpoints can be seen to set the course for the future, even though it may be possible to find more or less clear scholastic antecedents for some of them.1 And even if Grotius had been entirely unoriginal, it would still be to him that the historian of ideas would have to turn in order to understand modern natural law theory.
    [Show full text]
  • A Rhetoric of Civil Prudence Jeffrey Minson UCSD
    UC Irvine Law Review Volume 4 Issue 1 “Law As . .” II, History As Interface for the Article 18 Interdisciplinary Study of Law 3-2014 How to Speak Well of the State: A Rhetoric of Civil Prudence Jeffrey Minson UCSD Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.uci.edu/ucilr Part of the Law and Philosophy Commons, and the Law and Politics Commons Recommended Citation Jeffrey Minson, How to Speak Well of the State: A Rhetoric of Civil Prudence, 4 U.C. Irvine L. Rev. 437 (2014). Available at: https://scholarship.law.uci.edu/ucilr/vol4/iss1/18 This Article and Essay is brought to you for free and open access by UCI Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in UC Irvine Law Review by an authorized editor of UCI Law Scholarly Commons. How to Speak Well of the State: A Rhetoric of Civil Prudence Jeffrey Minson* Introduction ..................................................................................................................... 437 I. Prudentia Civilis as History ........................................................................................ 441 II. Moral Anthropology .................................................................................................. 447 III. The Civil Sovereign .................................................................................................. 452 IV. The Offices of Civil Prudence ............................................................................... 460 V. Concluding Remarks: To Graft Democracies ....................................................... 465 INTRODUCTION It is a fine thing to do well by the commonwealth, but to speak well of it is not contemptible.1 At the close of the 2012 UC Irvine “‘Law As . .’ II, History As Interface for the Interdisciplinary Study of Law” symposium, someone commented to the effect that a unifying undercurrent of the proceedings was “disgust” with the sovereign state. I took the comment as a marker of the sensus communis common to many critics of law and state.2 It is not just emoting.
    [Show full text]
  • The Law of Nations and Natural Law 1625–​1800
    chapter 6 The International Political Thought of Johann Jacob Schmauss and Johann Gottlieb Heineccius: Natural Law, Interest, History and the Balance of Power Peter Schröder 1 Introduction Hugo Grotius had been fairly optimistic that his natural law doctrine would be able to regulate the antagonistic relations between sovereign states. By looking at the arguments of Johann Jacob Schmauss (1690– 1757) and Johann Gottlieb Heineccius (1681– 1741), this chapter scrutinizes the limits of natural law regard- ing interstate relations. They used classical political or juridical concepts of international political thought – such as interest, balance of power, natural law and history – in their political and philosophical writings. Schmauss and Heineccius were both taught by Christian Thomasius1 and were part of the circle of Thomasius’s disciples at the newly founded University of Halle who shaped and continued the early Enlightenment and natural law project. But they pursued their writings and teaching in different directions. Schmauss belonged to the great eighteenth- century jurists. And yet he is almost entirely forgotten, despite the fact that some specialists have empha- sized his importance.2 Schmauss provides one of the crucial links between the University of Halle and the natural law tradition which is so closely associated with Thomasius, and the up and coming University of Göttingen, where he 1 In contrast to Schmauss and Heineccius, Thomasius has been well researched. See in particu- lar the English contributions by Ian Hunter, The Secularisation of the Confessional State: The Political Thought of Christian Thomasius (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007); Thomas Ahnert, Religion and the Origins of the German Enlightenment: Faith and the Reform of Learning in the Thought of Christian Thomasius (Rochester, NY: University of Rochester Press, 2006); and Timothy Hochstrasser, Natural Law Theories in the Early Enlightenment (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000).
    [Show full text]
  • Johan Ernst Gunnerus As a University Reformer of the Enlightenment
    Det Kongelige Norske Videnskabers Selskabs Skrifter (Kgl. Norske Vidensk. Selsk. Skr. 2011(2), 23-62) Johan Ernst Gunnerus as a University Reformer of the Enlightenment John Peter Collett John Peter Collett Professor, Forum for University History, University of Oslo, and Department of History and Classical Studies, NTNU, Trondheim Email: [email protected] Abstract In 1771 J.E. Gunnerus outlined a reform of the University of Copenhagen. The reform plan was commissioned by J.F. Struensee who at the time was the ruler of Denmark and Norway and was part of a wide reform movement aiming at a thorough modernization of the Danish states. The article summarizes parts of the university reform project and discusses them in the context of Enlightenment philosophical thinking on the nature of scientific knowledge. One by- product of the university reform proposal was a projected university in Norway. The reform proposals came to a standstill when Struensee was overthrown in 1772. Key words: J.E. Gunnerus, J.F.Struensee, Nordic Enlightenment, University reform. Introduction In the summer of 1771 Bishop Johan Ernst Gunnerus in Trondhjem received an order from the King summoning him to Copenhagen as Aspects of Johan Ernst Gunnerus' life and work. DKNVS Skrifter 2, 2011 soon as the duties of his diocese would allow him. The letter, signed by the King’s cabinet secretary, Johann Friedrich Struensee, announced that further instructions would be given him upon his arrival in the capital.1 Gunnerus arrived in Denmark in September and was received by Struensee, who was no longer a cabinet secretary.
    [Show full text]
  • Freedom, and the Principle of Sufficient Reason: Christian August Crusius’S Criticism of Optimism (1745)
    Chapter 4 Banning the Best World, God’s (Supposed) Freedom, and the Principle of Sufficient Reason: Christian August Crusius’s Criticism of Optimism (1745) Christian August Crusius is an unfamiliar name in conventional accounts of the history of modern philosophy. Yet he was a leading character of the early German Aufklärung, both because of his role as a relevant influence on Kant’s pre-critical thought, and due to the fact that he was one of the most fervent op- ponents of Leibnizian and Wolffian rationalist metaphysics in the eighteenth century. Crusius was born in 1715 near Halle and Leipzig in eastern Germany as the son of a Lutheran pastor. He studied philosophy and theology in the University of Leipzig, became professor of Philosophy at that University in 1750 and five years later professor of Theology. He died in Leipzig in 1775. His main philo- sophical works are the Dissertatio philosophica de usu et limitibus principii ra- tionis determinantis, vulgo sufficientis (Philosophical Dissertation Concerning the Use and Limits of the Principle of Determinant or Sufficient Reason) (1743), a critical examination of the Principle of Sufficient Reason; the Anweisung, vernünftig zu leben (Guide to Rational Living) (1744), his system of ethics; the Entwurf der nothwendigen Vernunftwahrheiten, wiefern sie den zufälligen ent- gegengesetzt werden (Outline of the Necessary Truths of Reason, as Opposed to Contingent Truths) (1745), his main treatise on metaphysics;1 the Weg zur Gewissheit und Zuverlässigkeit der menschlichen Erkenntniss (Path to the Certainty and Reliability of Human Knowledge) (1747), a system of logic; and the Anleitung, über natürliche Begebenheiten ordentlich und vorsichtig nachzuden- ken (Instruction on How to Reflect Correctly and Cautiously on Natural Events) (1749), his physics.2 1 An English translation of parts of this work can be found in Watkins 2009.
    [Show full text]
  • Classics Series Timeline U U Natural Law and Enlightenment
    u u N A T U R A L L A W A N D E NLIGHs e rT i e s ENMEN e d i t o r k n u d h a a k o nT s s e nCLASSI C S S ERIES TIMELINE 1540 1550 1560 1570 1580 1590 1600 1610 1620 1630 1640 1650 1660 1670 1680 1690 1700 1710 1720 1730 1740 1750 1760 1770 1780 1790 1800 1810 1820 1830 1840 David Fordyce, 1711–1751 Authors Francis Hutcheson, 1694–1746 Gershom Carmichael, 1672–1729 of the Christian Thomasius, 1655–1728 Jean Louis De Lolme, 1740–1806 Pierre Bayle, 1647–1706 Emmerich de Vattel, 1714–1767 Natural Richard Cumberland, 1632–1718 John Millar, 1735–1801 Jean Jacques Burlamaqui, 1694–1748 James Mackintosh, 1765–1832 Law Samuel Pufendorf, 1632–1694 Henry Home, Lord Kames, 1696–1782 S Hugo Grotius, 1583–1645 Johann Gottlieb Heineccius, 1681–1741 eries Francisco Suárez, 1548–1617 Nathaniel Culverwell, 1618– George Turnbull, 1698–1748 Huguenot Wars, France, 1562–1598 French Franco– War of the Revolu- ✦ St. Bartholomew’s Day Massacre, France, 1572 War of the tion ✦ Holy Roman Empire dissolved, 1806 Dutch League of Spanish ✦ Edict of Nantes, France, 1598 1789– War Succession Augsburg 1795 World Dutch Wars of Independence (Eighty Years’ War), 1568–1648 1672– 1688– 1701–1714 War ending with the Peace of Prague 1697 ending with the of the Peace of Utrecht ✦ Declaration of Rights of Man, France, 1789 ✦ Absolutism in Denmark, 1661 ending with Austrian Events ✦ Union of Utrecht, Netherlands, 1579 the Treaty of ✦ Fall of the Bastille, 1789 ✦ Independence of United Provinces proclaimed, Netherlands, 1581 Anglo–Dutch Wars, 1652–1684 ✦ Louis XVI executed, 1793 ✦ Reign of Terror, 1793–1794 ✦ Constitution of United Provinces, Netherlands, 1584 ✦ Revocation of Edict of ✦ ✦ Dutch East India Co.
    [Show full text]
  • The Authority of the German Religious Constitution: Public Law, Philosophy, and Democracy (2013) Ian Hunter
    The Authority of the German Religious Constitution: Public Law, Philosophy, and Democracy (2013) Ian Hunter Preliminaries Germany’s current religious constitution is primarily contained in Article 140 of the 1949 Grundgesetz or Basic Law, which in turn states that ‘The provisions of Articles 136, 137, 138, 139, and 141 of the German Constitution of 11 August 1919 shall be an integral part of the Basic Law’.1 Among these articles drawn from the 1919 constitution of the Weimar republic are those guaranteeing familiar rights and liberties for individuals. These include the independence of civil and political rights from religious affiliation, the enjoyment of such rights as religious privacy, access to public office independent of religious creed, and freedom from religious compulsion.2 Other articles, however, specify the corporate rights and liberties of religious confessions or associations. In addition to stipulating that there shall be no state church, these articles protect the right to form religious associations and they guarantee each such association the right to ‘regulate and administer its affairs independently within the limits of the law valid for all’.3 They also specify that those religious associations that have been corporate bodies under public law shall remain so, while new associations may apply for this status, which brings with it the right to levy taxes on the basis of civil taxation lists.4 Somewhat surprisingly from an English, French, or American perspective, the Weimar articles also stipulate that ‘Associations whose purpose is the cultivation of a philosophical ideology [Weltanschauung] shall have the same status as religious bodies’.5 1 Parliamentary Council [of the Federal Republic of Germany], The Basic Law for the Federal Republic of Germany (Wiesbaden: Foreign Office, 1971), p.
    [Show full text]
  • John Locke in the German Enlightenment: an Interpretation Klaus P
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Chapman University Digital Commons Chapman University Chapman University Digital Commons Philosophy Faculty Articles and Research Philosophy 1975 John Locke in the German Enlightenment: An Interpretation Klaus P. Fischer Chapman University Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.chapman.edu/philosophy_articles Part of the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, History of Philosophy Commons, and the Philosophy of Mind Commons Recommended Citation Fischer, Klaus P. "John Locke in the German enlightenment: an interpretation." Journal of the History of Ideas (1975): 431-446. DOI:10.2307/2708655 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy at Chapman University Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Articles and Research by an authorized administrator of Chapman University Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. John Locke in the German Enlightenment: An Interpretation Comments This article was originally published in Journal of the History of Ideas in 1975. DOI: 10.2307/2708655 Copyright University of Pennsylvania Press This article is available at Chapman University Digital Commons: http://digitalcommons.chapman.edu/philosophy_articles/1 JOHN LOCKE IN THE GERMAN ENLIGHTENMENT: AN INTERPRETATION BY KLAUSP. FISCHER I. A favorite assumptionof Anglo-Americanscholarship, endlessly repeated in textbooks and monographs,is that Locke's philosophy triumphed in every nook and cranny of Western Europe. By im- plication,it is also assumed that other philosophicsystems, especially those of Descartes and Leibniz, withered away without much op- position. The reigningphilosophy of the Enlightenment,we are told, was that of Locke and his disciples in Englandand on the Continent.
    [Show full text]
  • Brüder - Bestien - Automaten Das Tier Im Abendländischen Denken
    Manuela Linnemann (Hg.) Brüder - Bestien - Automaten Das Tier im abendländischen Denken HARALD FISCHER VERLAG Inhalt Vorbemerkung 5 Texte Empedokles 13 • Piaton. 13 • Aristoteles 15 • Cicero 17 • Ovid 21 • Seneca 23 • Plutarch 26 • Origenes 32 • Porphyrios 36 • Lactan- tius 40 • Augustinus 42 • Thomas von Aquin 43 • Leonardo da Vinci 44 • Giovanni Pico della Mirandola 46 • Erasmus von Rotter- dam 48 • Thomas Morus 49 • Giovanni Battista Gelli 50 • Michel de Montaigne 52 • Pierre Charron 57 • Francis Bacon 60 • Thomas Hobbes 61 • Pierre Gassendi 65 • Rene Descartes 67 • Jean de La Fontaine 70 • Blaise Pascal 74 • Baruch de Spinoza 76 • Samuel von Pufendorff 76 • John Locke 78 • Thomas Tryon 81 • Nicolas de Malebranche 83 • Jean M. Darmanson 86 • Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz 87 • Pierre Bayle 89 • Christian Thomasius 94 • Jean Meslier 98 • Bernard de Mandeville 99 • George Cheyne 105 • Christian Wolff 107 • Alexander Pope 109 • Voltaire 114 • Julien Offray de La Mettrie 119 • David Hume 124 • Jean-Jacques Rousseau 125 • Immanuel Kant 127 • Georg Christoph Lichten- berg 129 • Johann Gottfried Herder 130 • Jeremy Bentham 134 • Humphry Primatt 135 • Wilhelm Dietler 138 • Lauritz Smith 140 • Johann Friedrich Ludwig Volckmann 143 • Thomas Taylor 145 • 4 Inhalt Mary Wollstonecraft 147 • Johann Gottlieb Fichte 149 • Jean Paul 151 • Herman Daggett 154 • Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel 158 • Charles Fourier 763 • Jean Antoine Gleizes 164 • Lewis Gompertz 167 • Karl Christian Friedrich Krause 170 • Arthur Scho- penhauer 173 • Percy Bysshe Shelley 177 •
    [Show full text]
  • Causality and Morality in Politics
    Causality and Morality in Politics The Rise of Naturalism in Dutch Seventeenth-Century Political Thought HansW.Blom Causality and morality in politics Causality and morality in politics The rise of naturalism in Dutch seventeenth-century political thought Hans Willem Blom Rotterdam 1995 cip-gegevens koninklijke bibliotheek, den haag Blom, Hans Willem Causality and morality in politics : the rise of naturalism in Dutch seventeenth-century political thought / Hans Willem Blom. -[S.l. : s.n.] Proefschrift Universiteit Utrecht. -Met index, lit. opg. - Met samenvatting in het Nederlands. isbn 90-9007917-3 Trefw.: naturalisme in de politiek / politieke filosofie / Nederland ; politieke geschiedenis ; 17e eeuw. Typeset in Trinité (roman wide 2), typeface designed by Bram de Does. Printed by Offsetdrukkerij Ridderprint bv, Ridderkerk. Cover illustration: Atlas supporting the heavens, cast plaster model, presumably by Artus Quellien. ‘Burgerzaal’ of the Royal Palace (built 1648 till late 1660’s as town hall), Amsterdam. parentibus uxorique Reproduction by courtesy of the Stichting Koninklijk Paleis te Amsterdam Contents Preface 7 chapter i Morality and causality in politics 9 A naturalist conception of politics /10/ Passions and politics /13/ Naturalism /16/ Is–ought: some caveats /19/ History of political philosophy: distance and similarity /21/ The historical theses /25/ The core of the argument /29/ chapter ii Dutch political thought and institutions 33 Causes and intentions explaining Dutch political thought /34/ Between political strength
    [Show full text]
  • Spirituality and Philosophy in Post-Structuralist Theory
    History of European Ideas ISSN: 0191-6599 (Print) 1873-541X (Online) Journal homepage: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rhei20 Spirituality and philosophy in post-structuralist theory Ian Hunter To cite this article: Ian Hunter (2009) Spirituality and philosophy in post-structuralist theory, History of European Ideas, 35:2, 265-275, DOI: 10.1016/j.histeuroideas.2008.11.002 To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.histeuroideas.2008.11.002 Published online: 03 Jan 2012. Submit your article to this journal Article views: 147 View related articles Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=rhei20 Download by: [UQ Library] Date: 02 May 2016, At: 07:22 History of European Ideas 35 (2009) 265–275 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect History of European Ideas journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/histeuroideas Spirituality and philosophy in post-structuralist theory Ian Hunter University of Queensland, Centre for the History of European Discourses, 19 Mortlake Road, Graceville 4075, Australia ARTICLE INFO ABSTRACT Available online 27 December 2008 This paper discusses the role of a particular form of philosophical spirituality in the emergence of post-structuralist theory. Initially elaborated in the post-Kantian Keywords: metaphysics of Husserl and Heidegger, and focused in recondite acts of intellectual Spirituality self-transformation, this form of spirituality was transposed into a literary hermeneutics Philosophy that permitted its wider dissemination in the Anglo-American humanities academy. Post- Metaphysics structuralist theory is the result of this historical transformation. Theory ß 2008 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.
    [Show full text]