Transfinite Ordinals and Their Notations

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Transfinite Ordinals and Their Notations Transnite Ordinals and Their Notations For The Uninitiated Version Hilbert Levitz Department of Computer Science Florida State University levitzcsfsuedu Into duction This is supp osed to b e a primer to give you a feel for the sub ject fast Youre not exp ected to understand immediately why everything that is as serted is true but theres enough there so you could ll in the gaps if you wanted to The theory of transnite ordinals is a part of set theory While the concept is tied up with the completed innite and high cardinalities well emphasize more constructive asp ects of the theory There have b een appli cations of constructive treatments of ordinals to recursive function theory and pro of theory Pretty much everything we need to know ab out ordinals follows from the following three prop erties of the class of all ordinals O Just how the exis tence of such a class can b e shown well regard as a matter of mathematical foundations Basic Prop erties of the System of Ordinal Numb ers O has a well ordering which will b e denoted by Any well ordered set whatso ever is order isomorphic to a unique initial segment of O The ordinal determining the segment is called the ordinal of the set This makes the system of ordinals in some sense the mother of all well ordered sets Any set of memb ers of O has a strict upp er b ound and therefore by well ordering a least upp er b ound in O Warning The collection of all ordinals itself is not a set Youll get hit with a famous paradox if you treat it like one Subcollections of initial segments of the ordinals are sets and these are all we use As a consequence of the well ordering we see easily that i One can do arguments by induction over the ordinals or over any initial segment of them if we use the form of the induction principle Recall that for natural numb ers we also have induction in the n to n form but that fails as so on as one has an ob ject greater than every natural numb er Induction in the form frequently go es under the fancy name transnite induction ii We let denote the smallest ordinal Every ordinal has an immedi ate successor so by taking rep eated successors of zero we generate all the natural numb ers as an initial segment of the system of ordinals Not all non zero ordinals have an immediate predecessor Those without an immediate predecessor are called limit ordinals The smallest numb er to follow all the natural numb ers is denoted by and it is a limit ordinal Each limit ordinal is the least upp er b ound supremum of the set of smaller ordinals iii On account of the well ordering we can dene by recursion op erations of addition multiplication and exp onentiation The only added feature over recursion on natural numb ers is that we need to sp ecify what to do at limit ordinals x x 0 0 x y x y x y sup x y when y is a limit ordinal y y x 0 xy xy x xy sup xy when y is limit ordinal y y 0 x 0 y y x x x y y x sup x when y is a limit ordinal y y It turns out that a Addition and Multiplication are asso ciative Neither is commutative Multiplication distributes from the left over addition that is xy z xy xz Right distributivity fails but we do have the inequality x y z xz y z b Addition multiplication and exp onentiation are with trivial excep tions i Continuous strictly increasing function of the right argument ii Weakly monotone increasing functions of the left argument Cantor Normal Form The theorem of ordinary numb er theory that justies writing any non zero numb er to a numb er base like base or base applies to transnite ordinals as well Theorem Any nonzero ordinal can b e written uniquely as a p olynomial to any base greater than with descending exp onents and co ecients less than the base The co ecients are written to the right of the base Such a representation is called a Cantor normal form Its common to use as the base the numb er in which case the co e cients are natural numb ers thus a typical normal form lo oks like 1 2 k n n n 1 2 k where 1 2 k The rule for comparing two normal forms to see which represents the bigger ordinal is as follows One rst lo oks to see which has the highest leading exp onent if they are the same then you lo ok to see which has the highest leading co ecient etc Such a metho d could go into an innite regress on account of the fact shown in the next section that some ordinals can equal their own leading exp onent x Numb ers of the form determine initial segments closed under addi x dertermine initial segments of the ordinals tion and numb ers of the form closed under multiplication Denition of the ordinal 0 The limit of the sequence was named by Cantor We can see that its a solution of the the 0 x equation x by the following simple argument Consider the recursively dened sequence i a o a n ii a n+1 then a l im a n n l im a l im a l im n+1 n x Another way to say that a numb er is a solution of x is to say that x its a xed p oint of the function is the smallest ordinal bigger than that determines an initial 0 segment closed under ordinal addition multiplication and exp onentiation From this it follows that you cant denote it just using symb ols plus times and exp onentiation One can show using Cantor Normal Form that anything smaller can b e so represented Actually a similar argument can b e used to show additional xed p oints and they run clear through the ordinals They can b e arranged in a transnite sequence as 0 1 2 Computation With Ordinals On Real Computers We describ e b elow a system of formal terms T as follows i The symb ol a is an element of T ii If x and y are elements of T then so is the formal term f x y Our intention here is that a denote the ordinal numb er The meaning of the function symb ol f here we shall leave mysterious Recursive Denition of an ordering on T i a f x y for all terms x and y ii f x y f u v i one of the following holds a x u and y v b x u and y f u v c u x and f x y v or f x y v This ordering is easily shown to b e linear It turns out to b e a well ordering whose ordinal is It is known that it cant b e proven to b e a 0 well ordering in rst order numb er theory yet any initial segment can b e Gentzen Each term can b e regarded as a notation for an ordinal less than To 0 demonstrate that we are dealing with ob jects that can b e manipulated by computer we give b elow a PROLOG program for telling of two terms u and v whether u v l essa f U V l essf X Y f U V X U l essY V l essf X Y f U V l essX U l essY f U V l essf X Y f U V l essU X f X Y V l essf X Y f U V l essU X l essf X Y V Now if u and v are are formal terms of T the query lessuv will cause he machine to return the answer yes if the ordinal denoted by u is less than the ordinal denoted by v and no otherwise Connections to the Multiset Orderings of Term Rewriting Theory i The set of natural numb ers ordered by the multiset ordering has ordinal In fact in such a case the multiset fm m m g with m m 1 2 1 2 k m corresp onds to the ordinal k m m m 1 2 k ii If we p ermit multisets of multisets of multisets etc of natural numb ers the ordinal is 0 In fact in such a case the multiset fM M M g where M 1 2 1 k M M are multisets corresp onds to the ordinal 2 k or dM or dM or dM 1 2 k Problem of Skolem Nothing to do with logic really but just ab out every one whos made a contribution works in logic Consider the set of formal terms S dened inductively b elow i The symb ols and X are in S v ii If u and v are in S then so are u v uv and u Each term determines in a natural way a function of one variable on p ositive natural numb ers Consider the ordering of the functions f g i f x g x for suciently large x Questions Is it a linear ordering Yes Richardson Is it a well ordering Yes Ehrenfeucht using Kruskals Theorem If yes to the ab ove whats the ordinal Unknown Skolem showed is a lower b ound Levitz showed that the rst critical 0 epsilon numb er is an upp er b ound The rst critical epsilon numb er is x dened as follows Arrange the solutions of x in order and call them etc Then the rst critical epsilon numb er is the smallest 0 1 2 memb er of the sequence equal to own subscript Levitz Van den Dries and Dahn have partial results supp orting the conjecture that the actual ordinal is 0 The Least Uncountable Ordinal It is a theorem of general set theory that there are uncountable sets and a further theorem that any set can b e well ordered Let denote the smallest ordinal that is the ordinal of an uncountable set The initial segment determined by has the following prop erties I If then are only countably many ordinals less than II Every countable set of ordinals less than has a strict upp er b ound less than It turns out that any well ordered set with these prop erties is order isomorphic to the initial segment determined by More precisely if W is a well ordered set each of whose memb ers has only countably many smaller memb ers in W and each countable subset of W has a strict upp er b ound in W then W is order isomorphix to the initial segment determined Normal Functions and Ordinal Notations This is not intended to give a rigorous denition of a system of ordi nal notations but rather to help develop some insight and intuition for a commonly used one x That cute little argument used to show that has xed p oints can b e abstracted to show that if a sequence of successive iterations of a continuous function approaches a limit then that limit
Recommended publications
  • Even Ordinals and the Kunen Inconsistency∗
    Even ordinals and the Kunen inconsistency∗ Gabriel Goldberg Evans Hall University Drive Berkeley, CA 94720 July 23, 2021 Abstract This paper contributes to the theory of large cardinals beyond the Kunen inconsistency, or choiceless large cardinal axioms, in the context where the Axiom of Choice is not assumed. The first part of the paper investigates a periodicity phenomenon: assuming choiceless large cardinal axioms, the properties of the cumulative hierarchy turn out to alternate between even and odd ranks. The second part of the paper explores the structure of ultrafilters under choiceless large cardinal axioms, exploiting the fact that these axioms imply a weak form of the author's Ultrapower Axiom [1]. The third and final part of the paper examines the consistency strength of choiceless large cardinals, including a proof that assuming DC, the existence of an elementary embedding j : Vλ+3 ! Vλ+3 implies the consistency of ZFC + I0. embedding j : Vλ+3 ! Vλ+3 implies that every subset of Vλ+1 has a sharp. We show that the existence of an elementary embedding from Vλ+2 to Vλ+2 is equiconsistent with the existence of an elementary embedding from L(Vλ+2) to L(Vλ+2) with critical point below λ. We show that assuming DC, the existence of an elementary embedding j : Vλ+3 ! Vλ+3 implies the consistency of ZFC + I0. By a recent result of Schlutzenberg [2], an elementary embedding from Vλ+2 to Vλ+2 does not suffice. 1 Introduction Assuming the Axiom of Choice, the large cardinal hierarchy comes to an abrupt halt in the vicinity of an !-huge cardinal.
    [Show full text]
  • Handout from Today's Lecture
    MA532 Lecture Timothy Kohl Boston University April 23, 2020 Timothy Kohl (Boston University) MA532 Lecture April 23, 2020 1 / 26 Cardinal Arithmetic Recall that one may define addition and multiplication of ordinals α = ot(A, A) β = ot(B, B ) α + β and α · β by constructing order relations on A ∪ B and B × A. For cardinal numbers the foundations are somewhat similar, but also somewhat simpler since one need not refer to orderings. Definition For sets A, B where |A| = α and |B| = β then α + β = |(A × {0}) ∪ (B × {1})|. Timothy Kohl (Boston University) MA532 Lecture April 23, 2020 2 / 26 The curious part of the definition is the two sets A × {0} and B × {1} which can be viewed as subsets of the direct product (A ∪ B) × {0, 1} which basically allows us to add |A| and |B|, in particular since, in the usual formula for the size of the union of two sets |A ∪ B| = |A| + |B| − |A ∩ B| which in this case is bypassed since, by construction, (A × {0}) ∩ (B × {1})= ∅ regardless of the nature of A ∩ B. Timothy Kohl (Boston University) MA532 Lecture April 23, 2020 3 / 26 Definition For sets A, B where |A| = α and |B| = β then α · β = |A × B|. One immediate consequence of these definitions is the following. Proposition If m, n are finite ordinals, then as cardinals one has |m| + |n| = |m + n|, (where the addition on the right is ordinal addition in ω) meaning that ordinal addition and cardinal addition agree. Proof. The simplest proof of this is to define a bijection f : (m × {0}) ∪ (n × {1}) → m + n by f (hr, 0i)= r for r ∈ m and f (hs, 1i)= m + s for s ∈ n.
    [Show full text]
  • Well-Orderings, Ordinals and Well-Founded Relations. an Ancient
    Well-orderings, ordinals and well-founded relations. An ancient principle of arithmetic, that if there is a non-negative integer with some property then there is a least such, is useful in two ways: as a source of proofs, which are then said to be \by induction" and as as a source of definitions, then said to be \by recursion." An early use of induction is in Euclid's proof that every integer > 2 is a product of primes, (where we take \prime" to mean \having no divisors other than itself and 1"): if some number is not, then let n¯ be the least counter-example. If not itself prime, it can be written as a product m1m2 of two strictly smaller numbers each > 2; but then each of those is a product of primes, by the minimality of n¯; putting those two products together expresses n¯ as a product of primes. Contradiction ! An example of definition by recursion: we set 0! = 1; (n + 1)! = n! × (n + 1): A function defined for all non-negative integers is thereby uniquely specified; in detail, we consider an attempt to be a function, defined on a finite initial segment of the non-negative integers, which agrees with the given definition as far as it goes; if some integer is not in the domain of any attempt, there will be a least such; it cannot be 0; if it is n + 1, the recursion equation tells us how to extend an attempt defined at n to one defined at n + 1. So no such failure exists; we check that if f and g are two attempts and both f(n) and g(n) are defined, then f(n) = g(n), by considering the least n where that might fail, and again reaching a contradiction; and so, there being no disagreement between any two attempts, the union of all attempts will be a well-defined function, which is familiar to us as the factorial function.
    [Show full text]
  • The Set of All Countable Ordinals: an Inquiry Into Its Construction, Properties, and a Proof Concerning Hereditary Subcompactness
    W&M ScholarWorks Undergraduate Honors Theses Theses, Dissertations, & Master Projects 5-2009 The Set of All Countable Ordinals: An Inquiry into Its Construction, Properties, and a Proof Concerning Hereditary Subcompactness Jacob Hill College of William and Mary Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.wm.edu/honorstheses Part of the Mathematics Commons Recommended Citation Hill, Jacob, "The Set of All Countable Ordinals: An Inquiry into Its Construction, Properties, and a Proof Concerning Hereditary Subcompactness" (2009). Undergraduate Honors Theses. Paper 255. https://scholarworks.wm.edu/honorstheses/255 This Honors Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses, Dissertations, & Master Projects at W&M ScholarWorks. It has been accepted for inclusion in Undergraduate Honors Theses by an authorized administrator of W&M ScholarWorks. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Set of All Countable Ordinals: An Inquiry into Its Construction, Properties, and a Proof Concerning Hereditary Subcompactness A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirement for the degree of Bachelor of Science with Honors in Mathematics from the College of William and Mary in Virginia, by Jacob Hill Accepted for ____________________________ (Honors, High Honors, or Highest Honors) _______________________________________ Director, Professor David Lutzer _________________________________________ Professor Vladimir Bolotnikov _________________________________________ Professor George Rublein _________________________________________
    [Show full text]
  • A Translation Of" Die Normalfunktionen Und Das Problem
    1 Normal Functions and the Problem of the Distinguished Sequences of Ordinal Numbers A Translation of “Die Normalfunktionen und das Problem der ausgezeichneten Folgen von Ordnungszahlen” by Heinz Bachmann Vierteljahrsschrift der Naturforschenden Gesellschaft in Zurich (www.ngzh.ch) 1950(2), 115–147, MR 0036806 www.ngzh.ch/archiv/1950 95/95 2/95 14.pdf Translator’s note: Translated by Martin Dowd, with the assistance of Google translate, translate.google.com. Permission to post this translation has been granted by the editors of the journal. A typographical error in the original has been corrected, § 1 Introduction 1. In this essay we always move within the theory of Cantor’s ordinal numbers. We use the following notation: 1) Subtraction of ordinal numbers: If x and y are ordinals with y ≤ x, let x − y be the ordinal one gets by subtracting y from the front of x, so that y +(x − y)= x . 2) Multiplication of ordinals: For any ordinal numbers x and y the product x · y equals x added to itself y times. 3) The numbering of the number classes: The natural numbers including zero form the first number class, the countably infinite order types the second number class, etc.; for k ≥ 2 Ωk−2 is the initial ordinal of the kth number class. We also use the usual designations arXiv:1903.04609v1 [math.LO] 8 Mar 2019 ω0 = ω ω1 = Ω 4) The operation of the limit formation: Given a set of ordinal numbers, the smallest ordinal number x, for which y ≤ x for all ordinal numbers y of this set, is the limit of this set of ordinals.
    [Show full text]
  • Transfinite Induction
    Transfinite Induction G. Eric Moorhouse, University of Wyoming Notes for ACNT Seminar, 20 Jan 2009 Abstract Let X ⊂ R3 be the complement of a single point. We prove, by transfinite induction, that X can be partitioned into lines. This result is intended as an introduction to transfinite induction. 1 Cardinality Let A and B be sets. We write |A| = |B| (in words, A and B have the same cardinality) if there exists a bijection A → B; |A| à |B| if there exists an injection (a one-to-one map) A → B; |A| < |B| if |A| à |B| but there is no bijection from A to B. The Cantor-Bernstein-Schroeder Theorem asserts that if |A| à |B| and |B| à |A|, then |A| = |B|. (The proof is elementary but requires some thought.) So we may reasonably speak of the cardinality of a set, as a measure of its size, and compare any two sets according to their cardinalities. The cardinality of Z is denoted ℵ0. Every set A having |A| à ℵ0 is called countable; in this case either A is finite, or |A|=ℵ0 (countably infinite). Examples of countably infinite sets include {positive integers},2Z ={even integers}, and Q. Cantor showed that R is uncountable; we denote |R| = 2ℵ0. This cardinality, which we call the cardinality of the continuum, strictly exceeds ℵ0; it is also the cardinality of Rn for every positive integer n. In this context it is almost obligatory to mention the Continuum Hypothe- ℵ sis (CH), which is the assertion that there is no set A satisfying ℵ0 < |A| < 2 0.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Necessary Use of Abstract Set Theory
    ADVANCES IN MATHEMATICS 41, 209-280 (1981) On the Necessary Use of Abstract Set Theory HARVEY FRIEDMAN* Department of Mathematics, Ohio State University, Columbus, Ohio 43210 In this paper we present some independence results from the Zermelo-Frankel axioms of set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC) which differ from earlier such independence results in three major respects. Firstly, these new propositions that are shown to be independent of ZFC (i.e., neither provable nor refutable from ZFC) form mathematically natural assertions about Bore1 functions of several variables from the Hilbert cube I” into the unit interval, or back into the Hilbert cube. As such, they are of a level of abstraction significantly below that of the earlier independence results. Secondly, these propositions are not only independent of ZFC, but also of ZFC together with the axiom of constructibility (V = L). The only earlier examples of intelligible statements independent of ZFC + V= L either express properties of formal systems such as ZFC (e.g., the consistency of ZFC), or assert the existence of very large cardinalities (e.g., inaccessible cardinals). The great bulk of independence results from ZFCLthe ones that involve standard mathematical concepts and constructions-are about sets of limited cardinality (most commonly, that of at most the continuum), and are obtained using the forcing method introduced by Paul J. Cohen (see [2]). It is now known in virtually every such case, that these independence results are eliminated if V= L is added to ZFC. Finally, some of our propositions can be proved in the theory of classes, as formalized by the Morse-Kelley class theory with the axiom of choice for sets (MKC), but not in ZFC.
    [Show full text]
  • Ordinal Rankings on Measures Annihilating Thin Sets
    TRANSACTIONS OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 310, Number 2, December 1988 ORDINAL RANKINGS ON MEASURES ANNIHILATING THIN SETS ALEXANDER S. KECHRIS AND RUSSELL LYONS ABSTRACT. We assign a countable ordinal number to each probability mea- sure which annihilates all H-sets. The descriptive-set theoretic structure of this assignment allows us to show that this class of measures is coanalytic non-Borel. In addition, it allows us to quantify the failure of Rajchman's con- jecture. Similar results are obtained for measures annihilating Dirichlet sets. A closet subset E of the unit circle T = R/Z is called an H-set if there exists a sequence {n^} of positive integers tending to oo and an interval (i.e., a nonempty open arc) 7 C T such that for all k and all x € E, n^x ^ I. These sets play a fundamental role as examples of sets of uniqueness for trigonometric series [KL; Z, Chapters IX, XII]. A (Borel) probability measure fj, on T is called a Rajchman measure if fi(n) —*0 as \n\ —>oo, where jx(n) = fTe(—nx)dn(x), e(x) = e2wix. We denote by R the class of such measures. These measures have also been very important to the study of sets of uniqueness. In particular, every Rajchman measure annihilates every set of uniqueness, hence every H-set. After establishing these relationships [Rl, R2], Rajchman conjectured that, in fact, the only measures which annihilate all //"-sets are those in R. This, however, is false [LI, L2, L3, L5]. Here, we shall quantify how distant Rajchman's conjecture is from the truth.
    [Show full text]
  • SET THEORY for CATEGORY THEORY 3 the Category Is Well-Powered, Meaning That Each Object Has Only a Set of Iso- Morphism Classes of Subobjects
    SET THEORY FOR CATEGORY THEORY MICHAEL A. SHULMAN Abstract. Questions of set-theoretic size play an essential role in category theory, especially the distinction between sets and proper classes (or small sets and large sets). There are many different ways to formalize this, and which choice is made can have noticeable effects on what categorical constructions are permissible. In this expository paper we summarize and compare a num- ber of such “set-theoretic foundations for category theory,” and describe their implications for the everyday use of category theory. We assume the reader has some basic knowledge of category theory, but little or no prior experience with formal logic or set theory. 1. Introduction Since its earliest days, category theory has had to deal with set-theoretic ques- tions. This is because unlike in most fields of mathematics outside of set theory, questions of size play an essential role in category theory. A good example is Freyd’s Special Adjoint Functor Theorem: a functor from a complete, locally small, and well-powered category with a cogenerating set to a locally small category has a left adjoint if and only if it preserves small limits. This is always one of the first results I quote when people ask me “are there any real theorems in category theory?” So it is all the more striking that it involves in an essential way notions like ‘locally small’, ‘small limits’, and ‘cogenerating set’ which refer explicitly to the difference between sets and proper classes (or between small sets and large sets). Despite this, in my experience there is a certain amount of confusion among users and students of category theory about its foundations, and in particular about what constructions on large categories are or are not possible.
    [Show full text]
  • How Set Theory Impinges on Logic
    1 Jesús Mosterín HOW SET THEORY IMPINGES ON LOGIC The set-theoretical universe Reality often cannot be grasped and understood in its unfathomable richness and mind-blowing complexity. Think only of the trivial case of the shape of the Earth. Every time the wind blows, a bird flies, a tree drops a leave, every time it rains, a car moves or we get a haircut, the form of the Earth changes. No available or conceivable geometry can describe the ever changing form of the surface of our planet. Sometimes the best we can do is to apply the method of theoretical science: to pick up a mathematical structure from the set-theoretical universe, a structure that has some formal similarities with some features of the real world situation we are interested in, and to use that structure as a model of that parcel of the world. In the case of the Earth, the structure can be an Euclidean sphere, or a sphere flattened at the poles, or an ellipsoid, but of course these structures do not represent the car and the hair, and so are realistic only up to a point. The largest part of scientific activity results in data, in contributions to history (in a broad sense). Only exceptionally does scientific activity result in abstract schemata, in formulas, in theories. In history there is truth and falsity, but we are not sure whether it makes sense to apply these same categories to an abstract theory. We pick up a mathematical structure and construct a theory. We still have to determine its scope of application or validity, the range of its realizations.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Set Theory
    AN INTRODUCTION TO SET THEORY Professor William A. R. Weiss November 21, 2014 2 Contents 0 Introduction 7 1 LOST 11 2 FOUND 23 3 The Axioms of Set Theory 29 4 The Natural Numbers 37 5 The Ordinal Numbers 47 6 Relations and Orderings 59 7 Cardinality 69 8 What's So Real About The Real Numbers? 79 9 Ultrafilters Are Useful 87 3 4 CONTENTS 10 The Universe 97 11 Reflection 103 12 Elementary Submodels 123 13 Constructibility 139 14 Appendices 155 .1 The Axioms of ZFC . 155 .2 Tentative Axioms . 156 CONTENTS 5 Preface These notes for a graduate course in set theory are on their way to be- coming a book. They originated as handwritten notes in a course at the University of Toronto given by Prof. William Weiss. Cynthia Church pro- duced the first electronic copy in December 2002. James Talmage Adams produced a major revision in February 2005. The manuscript has seen many changes since then, often due to generous comments by students, each of whom I here thank. Chapters 1 to 11 are now close to final form. Chapters 12 and 13 are quite readable, but should not be considered as a final draft. One more chapter will be added. 6 CONTENTS Chapter 0 Introduction Set Theory is the true study of infinity. This alone assures the subject of a place prominent in human culture. But even more, Set Theory is the milieu in which mathematics takes place today. As such, it is expected to provide a firm foundation for all the rest of mathematics.
    [Show full text]
  • Ranked Structures and Arithmetic Transfinite Recursion
    RANKED STRUCTURES AND ARITHMETIC TRANSFINITE RECURSION NOAM GREENBERG AND ANTONIO MONTALBAN´ Abstract. ATR0 is the natural subsystem of second order arithmetic in which one can develop a decent theory of ordinals ([Sim99]). We investigate classes of structures which are in a sense the “well-founded part” of a larger, sim- pler class, for example, superatomic Boolean algebras (within the class of all Boolean algebras). The other classes we study are: well-founded trees, reduced Abelian p-groups, and countable, compact topological spaces. Using com- putable reductions between these classes, we show that Arithmetic Transfinite Recursion is the natural system for working with them: natural statements (such as comparability of structures in the class) are equivalent to ATR0. The reductions themselves are also objects of interest. 1. Introduction Classification of mathematical objects is often achieved by finding invariants for a class of objects - a method of representing the equivalence classes of some notion of sameness (such as isomorphism, elementary equivalence, bi-embeddability) by simple objects (such as natural numbers or ordinals). A related logical issue is the question of complexity: if the invariants exist, how complicated must they be; when does complexity of the class make the existence of invariants impossible; and how much information is implied by the statement that invariants of certain type exist. To mention a far from exhaustive list of examples: in descriptive set theory, Hjorth and Kechris ([HK95]) investigated the complexity of the existence of Ulm-type classification (and of the invariants themselves) in terms of the Borel and projective hierarchy; see also Camerlo and Gao ([CG01]) and Gao ([Gao04]).
    [Show full text]