3.7. Existential Presuppositions 47 63

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

3.7. Existential Presuppositions 47 63 OSU WPL 21 .1-90 (1976) The Myth of Semantic Presupposition Steven E. Boer and William G. Lycan OSU Department of Philosophy Contents Page 1 . Introduction: "Presupposition" 2 2 . Our Program 5 2 .1 . Two Fallacies 5 2 . 2 . Analytical Tools 9 2 . 2 .l. Entailment 9 2 . 2 . 2. Theoretical Implication ll 2 . 2 . 3. "Act-implication" 11 2 . 2 . 4 . Converse.tione.l Implicature 12 2 . 3 . Responsibility 13 3. Case Studies 14 3.1. Nonrestrictive Relative Clauses 14 3.2. Cleft Constructions 21 3.3. Factive Verbs 23 3.4. Implicative Verbs 33 3.5 . Counterfactives 40 3.6. Orders and Questions 42 3.7. Existential Presuppositions 47 3 .8. Countet·factual Conditionals 5L 4. Sources of the M}'th 60 4.1. Old Friends 60 4 .1 .1 . Assertion and Contradiction 60 4.1.2. External vs. Internal Negation 62 4.1. 3. Necessitation 63 4.2. Truth- valuelessness and Infeli·citousness 63 5. Relative Granunaticality 70 5 .1. Factual Presumptions and Logical Form 70 5.2 . Alternative Analyses 75 5. 3. The Awfu1ness of (Relative) Deviance 78 5.4 . Narrow Grammatice.lity and Broad Grammaticality 80 Footnotes 85 References 87 l The Myth of Semantic P1•esuµi,,,,;itiou Steven E. Boer William G. Lycan The notion of "presupposition" has caJ..>1.ured th" fancy of many linguists, and appeals to "presuppositions" are widely regarded as carrying explanatory force in linguistic theory. Our aim in this study is to criticize, from a standpoint congenial (tuough by no means specific) to Generative Semantics and the Pe,.rormative Analysis, the popula.r thesis that there are "semantic" presuppositions, i.e. that certain sorts of s entences have peculiar quasi-logical impli cations which are distinct from ordinary entailm1:nts aud yet closely akin to them, in that the falsity of the alleged implicata results in appre- ciable semantic consequences anent the seuten.:e:~ in question. A methodological. corollary of this thesis iu thut linguists who regard grammar for a natural language as operating or, a kind of' "natural logic" must complicate their semantic theories by -u,., :1dditio11 of more or less complex formal apparatus to account for th" dl~tinctively sernAntic oddities which are alleged to result wlteu "vn,!:upposi,ions" fail.I We shall argue (i) that the thesis is fals1:, (H) thut cvnsequently the methodological corollary is without sui•,•Jrt., ' a!td (iii) that alJ.eged cases of semantic presupposition do not <'Vt'u l\>rm a natural kind, in that where discernible "implications" do obt;,,..u1 , they turn out to be relations of distinct and largely unrelated :;ort.s (thus, we shall urge that such cases not be subsumed under a siugh· tlteor..tical term) . We shall accordingly offer piecemeal alternativ.., explanations of the intuitions in question, and go on to provitl.., what we believe to be an illuminating diagnosis of the fallacies ou which th<: notion of semantic presupposition rests. l. Introduction: "Presupposition" Most linguistic semanticists (and mau, philosophers of language) seem to agree that the notion of "presuvpv~ltlun" is both rich in intuitive content (and thus available as ,..u imµort.aut; source of data for syntax and semantics) and crucial for 0,U' understanding and theori- zing about the meanings of utterances (auu ll.Jus th-,oreticalJ.y important in syntax and semantics). A reader of tile ] it;f;>rat<U"e comes away with the impression that we have a vast stocll.p.il- of r.:latively hard data concerning the presuppoilitions of sente1w..,:,;, !Jut that we have yet to get quite as clear about what 11 presuppo:s.u,c" is u:; vurist metatheoreti- cians would like; nevertheless, the intuitiv,• IJvtlon that we have will do well enough to go on with, and we may <:out.im«:: to appeal to data concerning presupposition in framing syntactic uuu semantic arguments on diverse topics. 2 3 Here are some examples of pairs of sentences the like of which have been here and there adduced under the rubric of "presupposition" (as distinct from entailment): (1) a. Sam rea.lizes that Irv is a Martian. b . Irv is a Martian. (2) a . Fred regretted leaving home. b. Fred left home. (3) a . Bring me the avocado in the brown paper bag, b . There is an avocado in a brown paper bag. (4) a. Few girls are coming. b . Some girls are coming. (5) a . If Irv were a Martian, I'd be running away from here. b. Irv is not a Martian. (6) a . Have you stopped beating your wife? b. You have beaten your wife. (T) a . I hope I can disprove Godel's Theorem. b. It is possible to disprove Godel's Theorem. (8) a . I promise to bring back your toilet- seat. b . I intend to bring back your toilet-seat. (9) a . Fred, who -was fat, could not run. b . Fred was fat. (10) a. Camille is pretending to be sick. b . Camille is not sick. (11) a. John managed to get out of the phone booth. b . John tried to get out of the phone booth. (12) a. She was poor but she was honest. b. Being poor tends to preclude being honest. (13) a. If you touch me again, I'll scream. b . I f you don ' t touch me again, I wn' t scream. (14) a. Melvin is a bachelor. b. Melvin is an adult. It ~y perhaps be clear that the i'irst membe1· of each of these pair s somehow "suggests" or "implies" its fe).low. What is not at all clear (and would be naive to asswne) is that there is a single distinctive and important relation which is instantiated by a.ll these pairs. In fact, as we shal l see, the differences betveen the pairs are more interesting tban the similarities. To co111plicate the matter further, the literature contains a richly varied panoply of nonequivalent definitions or introductions of the term presuppose and its cognates, e.nd it is clear that not one but many distinct theor etical notions are in play as well. There are many more such notions than have been pointed out to date, though they may be grouped fairly easily into a few larger categories. And it is clear (though we shall not be able to docwnent the first and third of these points here) that (i) the differences between tbese various notions have tacitly been traded on, sometimes with substantive (but spurious) results; that (ii) when the proper distinctions have been made, most of the resulting notions will be seen to be relatively clear and manageable, though some (including the core concept of "semantic" presupposition) will be found to be vacuous and/or theoretically useless; lllld that 4 (iii) when the differences have been attended to~ out not before~ signif'icant progress ~y- be made on the relevant theoretical isaues., such a.s the q_uestion of' transitivity and the much-touted '\rrojection problemu.3 Some recent theorists have at la.st begun dissecting the monolith in crude but helpful ~ays . It is b7 now more or less standard to distinguish semantic from pragmatic :presuppositions (Sta.l:naker 1972; Keenan 1971; KarltWlen J.913; Thomason 1973; Atlas 1975; a.nd others}. That is, it is pointed out that there are a.t least two such notions that a.re J.)erha.ps not quite the s-a.me. But even this rough d.ifi'ere.nce is rarely taken seriously in the literature--thus Karttunen (1973), having pointed out the distinct ion., vrit es~ For the time being~ let. U$ simply a.:sslll:il.e that. -we understand what is meRD.t by a presupposition n the ~ase of simple senten~es .. a.nd turn our attention to Ill.Ore complex cases. • . • we may- ev-en forget about the distinction between semantic and pra~tic presuppositions. What is seid a.bout one kind o-f presupposition will apply to the other as veil (I hope). (p. l7l) These t\lo remarks will startle a. reader vho ha.s taken a careful 1ook at our list o:f sentence pa.ii:s or he.s taken note of the ~ssorted dlif"ini- tions or presuppositioo that have been ofrered in the literature. Let us list a fer.. of' these defi.nitions: (15) a. s1 Eresu:pposesi s2 ~ df s1 entails s2 and s1 1 s denTal entai s 82. Horn 1969; Morgan 1969} b. s1 p.resu~oses2 S2 = di' If S1 "makes literal sense~ th~n S2 is true. (Keen&.n 1971) Si presupposes3 s2 = dr If Si is true1 then 82 is true; and i.f S1 is false~ then S,2 is true {i.e. i~ S2 is not t~ue, then Si is neither true nor f'a.lse) , (Alterne..tively: Si aeces sitates S2 and. S1 1E denial necessitates S2 . ) (Strawson 1950; Keenan l971; Lakoff' l972; Kart unen 19711:J)). d. s1 presu;egis~s4 s2 ~ d~ A speaker utte~s s1 Sz is t:rue. felicitously only if that speaker believes S2. someone present believes 82- it is at least pretended that S2 is true . etc. (Heringer l972), And a close conpe.nion~ (J.6) s1 1 invite:s the in::ference ofu S2 = df" Given certain he.ckg~o-und beliefs that ve have, we ~ould have some ,ra.rrant f'or as.slJI!ling that if someone J utters Sl> he wi11 a.c a.s if he is •,dlli.ng o be regarded. as 5 having connnitted himself by uttering s1 to the truth of s2 . (Geis and Zwicky 1971)5 The semantic/pragmatic distinction cuts a.cross this representative set of definitions in a rough but noticeable way.
Recommended publications
  • Presupposition As Investigator Certainty in a Police Interrogation: the Case of Lorenzo Montoya’S False Confession
    Presupposition as investigator certainty in a police interrogation: The case of Lorenzo Montoya’s false confession Author: Philip Gaines This is a postprint of an article that originally appeared in Discourse & Society on July 2018. The final version can be found at https://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0957926518754417. Gaines, Philip. "Presupposition as investigator certainty in a police interrogation: The case of Lorenzo Montoya's false confession." Discourse & Society 29, no. 4 (July 2018): 399-419. DOI:10.1177/0957926518754417. Made available through Montana State University’s ScholarWorks scholarworks.montana.edu Presupposition as investigator certainty in a police interrogation: The case of Lorenzo Montoya’s false confession Philip Gaines Montana State University, USA Abstract This article presents an analysis of the use by police investigators of presupposition-bearing questions (PBQs) in interrogation as a process for communicating certainty of guilt. Among the techniques of interrogational maximization employed by police is the communication to the suspect of the interrogators’ certainty of the suspect’s guilt. While social science research notes that such communication of certainty is given directly, for example by statements that they ‘know’ the suspect is guilty or by direct accusations such as ‘you did it’, this analysis shows that certainty of guilt can also be communicated by presuppositions embedded in interrogation questions. Discourse analysis of the complete transcript of the interrogation of a 14-year-old suspect reveals further that through the use of 177 PBQs, interrogators are able to accrue inadvertent admissions to three crucial global ‘facts’ about the suspect’s involvement in the crime – each of which is composed of multiple subsidiary ‘facts’.
    [Show full text]
  • Entailment, Presupposition, and Implicature in the Work of Ernest Hemingway and Tim O'brien
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses Graduate School 1994 The tS ylistic Mechanics of Implicitness: Entailment, Presupposition, and Implicature in the Work of Ernest Hemingway and Tim O'Brien. Donna Glee Williams Louisiana State University and Agricultural & Mechanical College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_disstheses Recommended Citation Williams, Donna Glee, "The tS ylistic Mechanics of Implicitness: Entailment, Presupposition, and Implicature in the Work of Ernest Hemingway and Tim O'Brien." (1994). LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses. 5768. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_disstheses/5768 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses by an authorized administrator of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. INFORMATION TO USERS This manuscript has been reproduced from the microfilm master. UMI films the text directly from the original or copy submitted. Thus, some thesis and dissertation copies are in typewriter face, while others may be from any type of computer printer. The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. Broken or indistinct print, colored or poor quality illustrations and photographs, print bleedthrough,m asubstandard r gins, and improper alignment can adversely affect reproduction. In the unlikely event that the author did not send UMI a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if unauthorized copyright material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. Oversize materials (e.g., maps, drawings, charts) are reproduced by sectioning the original, beginning at the upper left-hand comer and continuing from left to right in equal sections with small overlaps.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is Presupposition Accommodation?
    Draft version from July 2000 What is Presupposition Accommodation? Kai von Fintel MIT In his paper “What is a Context of Utterance?”, Christopher Gauker (1998) argues that the phenomenon of informative presuppositions is incompatible with the “pragmatic” view of presuppositions as involving requirements on the common ground, the body of shared assumptions of the participants in a conversation. This is a surprising claim since most proponents of this view have in fact dealt with informative presuppositions by appealing to a process called presupposition accommodation. Gauker’s attack shows the need to clarify the nature of this process. Introduction: The Common Ground Theory of Presuppositions Here is a stylized version of the picture of information-gathering discourse developed by Stalnaker.1 The common ground of a conversation at a particular time is the set of propositions that the participants in that conversation at that time mutually assume to be taken for granted and not subject to (further) discussion. The common ground describes a set of worlds, the context set, which are those worlds in which all of the propositions in the common ground are true. The context set is the set of worlds that for all that is currently assumed to be taken for granted, could be the actual world. 1 Stalnaker (1972, 1973, 1974, 1978, 1988, 1998). Other important work in this tradition includes Karttunen (1974), Lewis (1979), Heim (1982, 1983, 1992), and Thomason (1990). When uttered assertively, sentences are meant to update the common ground. If the sentence is accepted by the participants, the proposition it expresses is added to the common ground.
    [Show full text]
  • An Analysis of Presupposition Triggers in Hilary Clinton's First
    International Journal of English Linguistics; Vol. 6, No. 5; 2016 ISSN 1923-869X E-ISSN 1923-8703 Published by Canadian Center of Science and Education An Analysis of Presupposition Triggers in Hilary Clinton’s First Campaign Speech Ruiqing Liang1 & Yabin Liu1 1 School of Foreign Studies, Jinan University, Guangzhou, China Correspondence: Yabin Liu, School of Foreign Studies, Jinan University, Guangzhou, China. E-mail: [email protected] Received: July 19, 2016 Accepted: August 9, 2016 Online Published: September 23, 2016 doi:10.5539/ijel.v6n5p68 URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.5539/ijel.v6n5p68 This paper is supported by “the Fundamental Research Funds for the Central Universities” (grant no.: 15JNYH007) and “the National Social Science Foundation of China” (grant no.:12BYY119). Abstract Presupposition triggers play a vital role in verbal communication. Based on Hilary Clinton’s first campaign speech, this paper intends to analyze the presupposition triggers at both lexical and syntactic levels, for the purpose of figuring out how Hilary succeeds in achieving her political intentions through the use of presupposition triggers, hoping to contribute to the composition and understanding of political speeches. Keywords: presupposition triggers, presupposition, Hilary Clinton, political speech 1. Introduction Presupposition, first put forward by German philosopher Gottlob Frege in 1892, was originally studied in philosophy of language and later introduced to the field of linguistics. As the study of presupposition continues, it has been found that presuppositions are typically generated by the use of lexical items or linguistic constructions. These lexical items and linguistic constructions are called presupposition triggers (Levinson, 1983; Huang, 2007). Presupposition has long been used as a property of language to mold the audience’s ideology.
    [Show full text]
  • Presupposition: a Semantic Or Pragmatic Phenomenon?
    Arab World English Journal (AWEJ) Volume. 8 Number. 3 September, 2017 Pp. 46 -59 DOI: https://dx.doi.org/10.24093/awej/vol8no3.4 Presupposition: A Semantic or Pragmatic Phenomenon? Mostafa OUALIF Department of English Studies Faculty of Letters and Humanities Ben M’sik, Casablanca Hassan II University, Casablanca, Morocco Abstract There has been debate among linguists with regards to the semantic view and the pragmatic view of presupposition. Some scholars believe that presupposition is purely semantic and others believe that it is purely pragmatic. The present paper contributes to the ongoing debate and exposes the different ways presupposition was approached by linguists. The paper also tries to attend to (i) what semantics is and what pragmatics is in a unified theory of meaning and (ii) the possibility to outline a semantic account of presupposition without having recourse to pragmatics and vice versa. The paper advocates Gazdar’s analysis, a pragmatic analysis, as the safest grounds on which a working grammar of presupposition could be outlined. It shows how semantic accounts are inadequate to deal with the projection problem. Finally, the paper states explicitly that the increasingly puzzling theoretical status of presupposition seems to confirm the philosophical contention that not any fact can be translated into words. Key words: entailment, pragmatics, presupposition, projection problem, semantic theory Cite as: OUALIF, M. (2017). Presupposition: A Semantic or Pragmatic Phenomenon? Arab World English Journal, 8 (3). DOI: https://dx.doi.org/10.24093/awej/vol8no3.4 46 Arab World English Journal (AWEJ) Volume 8. Number. 3 September 2017 Presupposition: A Semantic or Pragmatic Phenomenon? OUALIF I.
    [Show full text]
  • Presupposition and Dissociation in Discourse: a Corpus Study
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by AIR Universita degli studi di Milano Argumentation (2007) 21:361–378 Ó Springer 2007 DOI 10.1007/s10503-007-9058-7 Presupposition and Dissociation in Discourse: A Corpus Study CHIARA DEGANO Department of Contemporary Languages and Cultures Universita` degli Studi di Milano p.zza Indro Montanelli 1, Sesto San Giovanni Milan 20099 Italy E-mail: [email protected] ABSTRACT: This paper aims at combining different theoretical and methodological approaches for the analysis of discourse, focusing in particular on argumentative struc- tures. At a first level an attempt is made to include argumentation in critical discourse analysis in order to extend the analysis of interaction between ‘‘structures of discourse’’ and ‘‘structures of ideologies’’ to higher levels of language description. At a second level the study will integrate the qualitative approaches of critical discourse analysis and argumentation theory with the quantitative tools of corpus linguistics, so that the analysis can be carried out on a representative amount of texts and in a more systematic way. Even though corpus linguistics tends to be focused on meanings localized at the level of words, while argumentative structures stretch out through longer units of text, an integration can be attempted by circumscribing the enquiry to those aspects of argumentation which are signalled by indicators, and are therefore electronically retrievable. In particular, this paper investigates the use of dissociation and presupposition in a corpus of newspaper articles published in the run up to the war on Iraq. Both structures respond to retriev- ability criteria while being powerful instruments to convey ideologically oriented messages.
    [Show full text]
  • Presupposition and Context Sensitivity
    MILA mila_12068 Dispatch: September 18, 2014 Journal: MILA Journal Name Manuscript No. B Author Received: No of pages: 16 TS: priya.s 1 2 3 Presupposition and Context Sensitivity 4 5 ERNIE LEPORE AND ADAM SENNET 6 7 Abstract: We argue there is a clash between the standard treatments of context sen- sitivity and presupposition triggering. We use this criticism to motivate a defense of an 8 often-discarded view about how to represent context sensitivity, according to which there 9 are more lexically implicit items in logical form than has been appreciated. 10 11 12 Introduction 13 14 This article is about a clash between the orthodox treatments of two phenomena— 15 the context sensitivity of sentences such as in (1) and presupposition triggering, as 16 in (2).1 17 18 (1) Tipper isn’t ready. 19 (2) Tipper quit smoking. 20 With respect to the former phenomenon, most competent English speakers hold 21 that a felicitous utterance of (1) will communicate a proposition of the form that 22 Tipper isn’t ready for X (where X is whatever Tipper isn’t ready for). What gets 23 communicated varies as a matter of context. With respect to the latter, we observe 24 that anyone who asserts (2) triggers the presupposition that she once smoked. 25 We will argue that all the currently favored (competing) treatments of context 26 sensitivity are incompatible with the current orthodoxy about presupposition trig- 27 gering. In consequence, we will urge a reconsideration of a much-maligned view 28 29 30 The authors would like to thank El Grupo de Acción Filosófica, SPAWN 2012, and University of 31 Calgary who heard presentations of this paper and offered helpful suggestions.
    [Show full text]
  • Heidegger and the Modes of World-Disclosure Author(S): Sandra Lee Bartky Reviewed Work(S): Source: Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol
    International Phenomenological Society Heidegger and the Modes of World-Disclosure Author(s): Sandra Lee Bartky Reviewed work(s): Source: Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 40, No. 2 (Dec., 1979), pp. 212-236 Published by: International Phenomenological Society Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2106318 . Accessed: 23/10/2012 10:56 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. International Phenomenological Society is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. http://www.jstor.org HEIDEGGER AND THE MODES OF WORLD-DISCLOSURE "Every great thinker thinks only a single thought," says Heideg- ger in Was Heisst Denken?' This extraordinary assertion may not be true of other thinkers but it is without doubt true of him. The thought of Being (das Sein) is Heidegger's one thought: his later philosophy is a sustained examination of the meaning of Being, of its history, of how it has currently abandoned us and of the ways in which we can once again draw near to it. But the thought of Being, as Heidegger thinks it, is a very complex thought indeed. Being, which is to be understood as primordial "event," (Ereignis) as the ultimate ground of what happens, takes two forms: there occurs what I shall call a "horizontal" Being-event and a "vertical" Being-event.
    [Show full text]
  • Presuppositions in Moral Education Discourse: Developing an Analytic Framework and Applying It to Moral Education Traditions
    University of Central Florida STARS Electronic Theses and Dissertations, 2004-2019 2005 Presuppositions In Moral Education Discourse: Developing An Analytic Framework And Applying It To Moral Education Traditions Maria Sciaino University of Central Florida Part of the Curriculum and Instruction Commons Find similar works at: https://stars.library.ucf.edu/etd University of Central Florida Libraries http://library.ucf.edu This Doctoral Dissertation (Open Access) is brought to you for free and open access by STARS. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations, 2004-2019 by an authorized administrator of STARS. For more information, please contact [email protected]. STARS Citation Sciaino, Maria, "Presuppositions In Moral Education Discourse: Developing An Analytic Framework And Applying It To Moral Education Traditions" (2005). Electronic Theses and Dissertations, 2004-2019. 390. https://stars.library.ucf.edu/etd/390 PRESUPPOSITIONS IN MORAL EDUCATION DISCOURSE: DEVELOPING AN ANALYTIC FRAMEWORK AND APPLYING IT TO SEVERAL MORAL EDUCATION TRADITIONS by MARIA A. SCIAINO B.A. Stetson University, 1985 M. Ed. Stetson University, 1990 A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Education in the Department of Curriculum and Instruction in the College of Education at the University of Central Florida Orlando, Florida Spring Term 2005 © 2005 Maria Sciaino ii ABSTRACT Moral education is ever more important in our schools today, but the various moral education traditions make it difficult to decide which tradition best serves our purpose and population. This dissertation develops and uses an original analytic framework to narrow the choices of moral education curricula. The analytic framework introduced presuppositions that expounded upon one’s center of value or source of moral authority, the nature of people and their capacity for rational thought, the nature of society, the time orientation of tradition, and the resulting morality in action.
    [Show full text]
  • A Lexical Approach to Presupposition and Meaning
    A Lexical Approach to Presupposition and Meaning Von der Philosophisch-Historischen Fakult¨at der Universit¨at Stuttgart zur Erlangung der W¨urde eines Doktors der Philosophie (Dr. phil.) genehmigte Abhandlung Vorgelegt von Charles Woei-Jye Yee aus Taipei, Taiwan Hauptberichter: Prof. Dr. h.c. Hans Kamp Mitberichter: Prof. Dr. Klaus von Heusinger Tag der m¨undlichen Pr¨ufung: 20. Dezember 2010 Institut f¨ur Maschinelle Sprachverarbeitung der Universit¨at Stuttgart 2011 Acknowledgements It’s been a long journey and I have gone through a great deal of personal transforma- tion throughout- knowledge, the ability to think critically, all that good stuff- plus a few more pounds under my belt, making that transformation literally complete. I find comfort in knowing that I have done this. But I couldn’t have done it without the fol- lowing people from IMS: Agnes Bende-Farkas, Christian Hying, Arndt Riester, Antje Roßdeutscher, Guisy Rota, and Tolgrim Solstad. You guys and gals really helped me out when I needed it. Thank you! I especially want to thank Klaus von Heusinger for his kind words and guidance. Klaus gave me some excellent feedbacks which helped me see certain aspects of the issue that I would have otherwise overlooked on my own. I would also like to thank several people who have given me great insights either through their wonderful work, or through personal discussions on the few occa- sions when we crossed path: David Beaver, Patrick Blackburn, Johan Bos, Kees van Deemter, Josef van Genabith, Bart Geurts, Ruth Kempson, Emiel Krahmer, Massimo Poesio, Uwe Reyle, Craige Roberts, Rob van der Sandt, Renata Vieira, Hank Zeevat- I admire your works, and they have influenced me tremendously.
    [Show full text]
  • Presuppositions of Science
    Invited Articles PENSAR EN MOVIMIENTO: Revista de Ciencias del Ejercicio y la Salud ISSN 1659-4436 Vol. 15, No.1, pp. 1- 16 Closing on June 30, 2017 PRESUPPOSITIONS OF (HUMAN MOVEMENT) SCIENCE1 LAS PRESUPOSICIONES DE LA CIENCIA (DEL MOVIMIENTO HUMANO) AS PRESSUPOSIÇÕES DA CIÊNCIA (DO MOVIMENTO HUMANO) René van Woudenberg [email protected] Department of Philosophy, Vrije Universititeit, Amsterdam, The Netherlands Original submission: 30/01/2017; resubmitted: 24/03/2017; accepted: 28/03/2017; published: 18/05/2017. Doi: 10.15517/pensarmov.v15i1.27846 ABSTRACT Van Woudenberg, R. (2017). Presuppositions of (human movement) science. PENSAR EN MOVIMIENTO: Revista de Ciencias del Ejercicio y la Salud, 14(2), 1-16. This paper argues that science, human movement science included, proceeds from many presuppositions. First, it explains what sorts of things presuppositions are. Next, it argues that science proceeds from metaphysical, epistemic, and normative presuppositions. The argument entails that neither scientism nor Naturalism is a presupposition of science. Keywords: Philosophy; philosophy of science; epistemology; metaphysics; naturalism; scientism; philosophical analysis RESUMEN Van Woudenberg, R. (2017). Las presuposiciones de la ciencia (del movimiento humano). PENSAR EN MOVIMIENTO: Revista de Ciencias del Ejercicio y la Salud, 14(2), 1-16. Esta ponencia argumenta que la ciencia, incluyendo la ciencia del movimiento humano, procede a partir de muchas presuposiciones. Primero explica qué clase de cosa son las presuposiciones. Luego arguye que la ciencia procede a partir de presuposiciones metafísicas, epistémicas y normativas. Este argumento implica que ni el cientificismo ni el naturalismo son una presuposición de la ciencia. 1 Original submission in English.
    [Show full text]
  • Political Dominance in Kenyan Parliamentary Debates Between 1992 and 2010
    Journal of Education and Practice www.iiste.org ISSN 2222-1735 (Paper) ISSN 2222-288X (Online) Vol.7, No.24, 2016 The Use of Presupposition in the Creation of Socio- Political Dominance in Kenyan Parliamentary Debates between 1992 and 2010 Christine Atieno Peter 1* Prof Mwenda Mukuthuria 2 Prof Peter Muriungi 3 1.Chuka University, P.O. Box 109, Chuka, Kenya 2.Masai Mara University, Narok, Kenya 3.Chuka University, Chuka, Kenya Abstract Presupposition, a linguistic element can be employed in utterances. When this is done it enhances the comprehension of what is being communicated. This aspect of language that is implicit assumption of an utterance is a strategy that may be used to express a speaker’s socio- political dominance. The truth of what is said is taken for granted and can be manipulated by the speaker to have devastating effects on an individual or the society at large. This study examined presupposition as a strategy of language used by Kenyan members of parliament during debates to create socio- political dominance. The objective was: To analyse the usage of presupposition in language used by parliamentarians to create socio- political dominance in Kenyan parliamentary debates. Various sources of literature have been reviewed in the following areas: ideology, discourse strategies, the power in language, parliamentary proceedings and political dominance. The study used descriptive research design. By using purposive sampling, the data was collected from the Hansard dating from 1992 to 2010. Data was analysed using Foucauldian Discourse Analysis (FDA). This theory looks at how the society is moulded by language that shows various power relationships.
    [Show full text]