Legalizing Physician-Assisted Suicide: Some Thoughts and Concerns

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Legalizing Physician-Assisted Suicide: Some Thoughts and Concerns Special A rticle Legalizing Physician-Assisted Suicide: Some Thoughts and Concerns Harold G. Koenig, M D, M HSc Durham, North Carolina Surveys show that most Americans favor the decrimi­ medicine in unpredictable ways, yet physicians are par­ nalization of phvsician-assisted suicide in certain cir­ ticipating relatively little in deliberations concerning cumstances. Several states are now considering legisla­ this issue. The problem o f suffering in persons with tion to bring this about and make the United States chronic and terminal illness cannot be ignored. C om ­ the first place in the civilized world where physician aid passionate, effective, and ethical solutions must be in dying is sanctioned. In the Netherlands, where phy­ found. As a former family physician and now geriatric sician-assisted suicide is practiced but officially remains psychiatrist, I review the pros and cons of physician-as­ illegal, 85% o f assisted suicides occur in the elderly, sisted suicide (emphasizing arguments against legaliza­ and most involve the help o f general practitioners. In tion) and encourage family physicians to debate this the United States, family physicians provide health care matter. to many older adults with chronic or terminal illness whose numbers will increase as the elderly population Key words. Suicide; aged; euthanasia; ethics; patient expands. The legalization o f physician-assisted suicide advocacy; quality' o f life. ( / Fam Fract 1993; would affect the way American physicians practice 37:171-179) Most physicians have had patients with advanced cancer, Clarification of Terms end-stage heart failure, severe chronic obstructive pulmo­ To discuss this topic intelligently, one must carefully nary disease, or other disabling and painful diseases. define one’s terms, or risk ambiguity and confusion. Many of these persons experience great physical and First, withdrawal of life support, or passive euthanasia, emotional suffering during the final few weeks or months involves the removal of tubes, respirators, or any other of their lives. In such circumstances, it is our professional, type of artificial support that may prolong life. The excess ethical, and moral duty to do everything possible to use of medical technology to extend apparently meaning­ relieve such apparently meaningless suffering. Should less life and prolong suffering, especially in cases of physicians be allowed to honor requests by terminally or terminal or near-terminal illness, is one of the factors that chronically ill patients to assist them in ending their lives? have stirred a public outcry for physician assistance in This subject has special relevance for older adults, who dying. Physician-assisted suicide occurs when a physician are most likely to be affected by terminal or chronic intentionally and willfully takes actions that help a sui­ diseases, and for family physicians who care for them. In cidal patient to end his or her life. This may involve the Netherlands, more than 85% o f euthanasia cases providing information on ways of committing suicide, occur in medically ill persons aged 50 years or over, and supplying a prescription for a lethal dose of medication, most are performed by general practitioners.1 providing a syringe filled with a lethal dose o f medica­ tion, inserting an intravenous line so that the patient can Submitted, revised, April 15, 1993. inject the drug, or providing a suicide device that the From the Departments o f Medicine and Psychiatry, Duke University Aledical Center, patient can operate (such as the “suicide machine” in­ Durham, North Carolina. Requests for reprints should be addressed to Harold G. vented bv Jack Kevorkian, MD). Active euthanasia in­ Koenig, MD, MHSc, Bax 3400, Duke University Medical Center, Durham, NC 27710. volves a physician willfully and intentionally performing 6 1993 Appleton & Lange ISSN 0094-3509 171 The Journal of Family Practice, Vol. 37, No. 2, 1993 Physician-Assisted Suicide an action that directly and immediately results in the would consider some option to end their life if they had patient’s death. Here, the physician is the actor, but acts an incurable illness and were in a great deal of pain.5 at the patient’s request. Leading and organizing the effort to legalize phvsi- Watts and Howell2 argue that there are clear philo­ cian-assisted suicide is the Hemlock Society, founded it sophical distinctions between passive forms of assisted Los Angeles in 1980 and now numbering over 40,000 suicide (providing information), more aggressive assisted members. Englishman Derek Humphry, its principal suicide (providing a lethal dose of medication or appa­ founder, was the organization’s leader and spokesman ratus to inject it), and active euthanasia (physician inject­ until 1992 when, following adverse publicity surround­ ing a lethal drug), pointing to the differing degrees of ing the suicide of his second wife,7 he stepped down as physician influence or control over the process leading to executive director. Hum phry’s most recent book, Ftnii death. Others, however, contend that legalizing any form Exit,8 marketed as a “how to do it” manual for those of physician-assisted suicide may open a door that is not wishing to commit suicide, sold over 500,000 copies easily closed. They refer to the strategy taken by advo­ within 6 months of publication. cates of euthanasia in the Netherlands, who gradually The Hemlock Society has led initiatives to legalize won widespread acceptance of active euthanasia by first assisted suicide in Washington and California that were endorsing more palatable, less offensive categories.3 only narrowly defeated (both by a 54% to 46% margin; Making distinctions between forms of assistance, while The issue, however, remains very much alive, and similar easy in theory, is difficult in practice. If one can justify measures are expected to qualify for the 1994 ballot in providing support and advice, a lethal dose of medica­ California, O regon, and W ashington.9 In a speech to the 1992 annual meeting of the Academy of Psychosomatic tion, or a suicide device to a patient who is both intent on and capable of killing himself or herself, it becomes Medicine, Humphry emphasized that he hoped that fu­ difficult to ignore the desperate pleas o f another severely ture legislation would be as carefullv considered and wel ill patient who needs assistance to die but cannot com­ reasoned as the California initiative. A number of Cali­ plete the act because of problems with swallowing, phys­ fornia psychiatrists, on the other hand, argued that Ini­ ical frailness, or a lack o f emotional fortitude. tiative 161 was “a potential disaster” because of a lack of safeguards to prevent persons with treatable mental ill­ If one can justify that it is ethical and safe for a nesses, eg, depression, from committing suicide. physician to assist the suicidal patient, then it is difficult to argue against more active interventions in more com­ plex, and perhaps more appropriate, circumstances. Phy­ sicians in the Netherlands acknowledged this obvious Proponents’ View conclusion almost a decade ago, when the Roval Dutch Medical Association (KNMG) recommended that the Almost two decades ago, philosopher James Rachels1* distinction between euthanasia and assisted suicide be argued that there was no ethical distinction between passive and active euthanasia. If one can justify not treat abolished on grounds that the intent in both cases is to bring about the patient’s death.3 For these reasons, the ing or withdrawing treatment from hopelessly ill patient arguments proposed in this article will apply to all forms to quicken death and reduce suffering, then providing of assistance in dying, including active euthanasia. them with more active assistance in ending their live should pose no moral or ethical dilemma. In a more recent article, W eir11 argues that assisted suicide is mor­ ally justifiable. Rather than harm the patient, physician- Proponents o f Assisted Suicide assisted suicide benefits him or her by relieving intolera­ ble and useless suffering, some of which may not be Between one half and two thirds of Americans todav amenable to even the most expert palliation. Assisted favor the legalization of physician-assisted suicide in cer­ suicide enhances patient autonomy and reduces fear bv tain circumstances.4’5 The public’s attitude toward as­ giving the person control over the dying process. The sisted suicide has changed during the past 15 years. In argument for physician-assisted suicide has also beer- 1975, a Gallup poll showed that 41% of respondents presented in several recent articles by Timothy Quill and believed that persons in great pain without hope of Christine Cassel in The New England Journal of Medi­ improvement had a moral right to commit suicide; in cine. 12~14 Death with dignity and control is seen as better 1990, the figure had increased to 66%.6 Similarly, a than an agonizing, prolonged, and unpredictable death survey by the Harvard School of Public Health reported Furthermore, the right to die is guaranteed in the first that 61% of all Americans would vote for an initiative and fourth amendments to the Constitution, and there­ legalizing physician-assisted suicide; 52% said they fore the right to end one’s life is seen as being as imp 172 The Journal of Family Practice, Vol. 37, No. 2,199-' Phvsician-Assisted Suicide Koenig tant as the right to life.15 Finally, assisted suicide can (former director of the federal Alcohol, Drug Abuse, and benefit society by reducing the use of scarce medical Mental Health Administration) voices considerable con­ resources on hopeless cases. The latter argument is sel­ cern within the psychiatric community about phvsician- dom stressed, since proponents believe that if assisted assisted suicide.22 I focus here on four major groups that suicide became available, it would be chosen by relatively tend to oppose physician-assisted suicide: physicians, few persons, and thus have little impact on resource bioethicists, the elderly, and religious organizations.
Recommended publications
  • The Right to End-Of-Life Palliative Care and a Dignified Death 1
    THE RIGHT TO END-OF-LIFE PALLIATIVE CARE AND A DIGNIFIED DEATH 1 CONTRIBUTION FROM UN-ECLAC FOR THE EXPERT GROUP MEETING ON “CARE AND OLDER PERSONS: LINKS TO DECENT WORK, MIGRATION AND GENDER” 5-7 December 2017 United Nations Headquarters, New York – Secretariat Building, Conference Room S -2725 1. The right to life and dignity in old age The approach of death involves a number of activities, as different practicalities pertaining to the end of life have to be organized. It is essential for these activities —which are carried out by family members, caregivers and medical personnel, among others— to meet standards that ensure appropriate living conditions until such time as clinical and biological death supervenes. Older persons are among the most vulnerable to death. Their position in the age structure of society becomes almost by default a predictor of their demise. This social construction of old age prompts a particular way of treating the elderly: “The social structures in which [older persons] are involved are oriented to the fact of their forthcoming death; their families have become increasingly independent of them; the scope of references to the ‘future’ has progressively narrowed; ‘dying’ is of considerably less consequence for others, e.g., it is not felt to be a matter which requires drastic revision of others’ life plans, as does the ‘fact’ that a young adult is dying” (Sudnow, 1967).2 Older persons are sometimes treated like cadavers even when they are, clinically and biologically, still alive. This occurs especially in cases where they are dying or suffering from terminal illnesses, although they do not necessarily have to be in this predicament to receive degrading treatment.
    [Show full text]
  • Physician-Assisted Suicide and Voluntary Euthanasia: Some Relevant Differences John Deigh
    Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology Volume 88 Article 14 Issue 3 Spring Spring 1998 Physician-Assisted Suicide and Voluntary Euthanasia: Some Relevant Differences John Deigh Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarlycommons.law.northwestern.edu/jclc Part of the Criminal Law Commons, Criminology Commons, and the Criminology and Criminal Justice Commons Recommended Citation John Deigh, Physician-Assisted Suicide and Voluntary Euthanasia: Some Relevant Differences, 88 J. Crim. L. & Criminology 1155 (Spring 1998) This Criminal Law is brought to you for free and open access by Northwestern University School of Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology by an authorized editor of Northwestern University School of Law Scholarly Commons. 0091-4169/98/8803-1155 THE JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW& CRIMINOLOGY Vol. 88, No. 3 Copyright 0 1998 by Northwestern University, School of Law Prinfd in U.SA. PHYSICIAN-ASSISTED SUICIDE AND VOLUNTARY EUTHANASIA: SOME RELEVANT DIFFERENCES JOHN DEIGH" Yale Kamisar, in a series of influential articles on physician- assisted suicide and voluntary active euthanasia, has written elo- quently in opposition to legalizing these practices.1 Today he revisits the first of these articles, his seminal 1958 article, Some Non-Religious Views Against Proposed "Mercy-Killing"Legislation. 2 In that paper Professor Kamisar used the distinction between the law on the books and the law in action to quiet concerns about the harsh consequences of a blanket prohibition on mercy kill- ing. A blanket prohibition, after all, if strictly applied, would impose criminal punishment on physicians and relatives whose complicity in bringing about the death of a patient, or loved one was justified by the dying person's desperate condition and lucid wish to die.
    [Show full text]
  • Estate Checklist for Trustees and Survivors
    LAW OFFICES OF MICHAEL E. GRAHAM 10343 HIGH STREET, SUITE ONE TRUCKEE, CALIFORNIA 96161-0116 TELEPHONE 530.587.1177 P FACSIMILE 530.587.0707 MICHAEL E. GRAHAM † [email protected] ESTATE CHECKLIST FOR TRUSTEES AND SURVIVORS 1. IMMEDIATE ASSISTANCE Family and friends may assist immediately after the death with the following: C Take turns answering the door or telephone and keep careful records of all calls. C Provide meals for the first several days. C Arrange for child care if necessary. C Make a list of immediate family, close friends, and employer or business colleagues and notify each by telephone. C Arrange for accommodations for visiting relatives and friends. C Take care of special household needs such as cleaning, lawn care, and maintenance. C Prepare a list of persons to receive acknowledgments of flowers, calls, etc., and send acknowledgments. C Prepare a list of distant persons to be notified by letter and prepare printed notices to be sent to each. 2. INITIAL CONSIDERATIONS A. CORONER’S INQUEST OR AUTOPSY Coroner's Inquest Government Code §27491 requires the coroner to inquire into and determine the cause of all violent or sudden deaths, unattended deaths, deaths resulting from criminal acts, deaths of patients in state hospitals operated by the Department of State Hospitals or the Department of Developmental Services, and deaths due to accident, injury, or other unusual causes. When a death is the result of a circumstance specified in the statute, the body cannot be disturbed or moved from its position or place of death without permission of the coroner or the coroner's appointed deputy.
    [Show full text]
  • Recommendations for End-Of-Life Care for People Experiencing Homelessness
    Adapting Your Practice Recommendations for End-of-Life Care for People Experiencing Homelessness Health Care for the Homeless Clinicians’ Network 2018 Health Care for the Homeless Clinicians’ Network Adapting Your Practice: Recommendations for End-of-Life Care for People Experiencing Homelessness was developed with support from the Bureau of Primary Health Care, Health Resources and Services Administration, U.S. Department of Health and Human Services. All material in this document is in the public domain and may be used and reprinted without special permission. Citation as to source, however, is appreciated. i ADAPTING YOUR PRACTICE: Recommendations for End-of-Life Care for People Experiencing Homelessness Health Care for the Homeless Clinicians’ Network Disclaimer This project was supported by the Health Resources and Services Administration (HRSA) of the U.S. Department of Health and Human Services (HHS) under grant number U30CS09746, a National Training and Technical Assistance Cooperative Agreement for $1,625,741, with 0% match from nongovernmental sources. This information or content and conclusions are those of the authors and should not be construed as the official position or policy of, nor should any endorsements be inferred by HRSA, HHS, or the U.S. Government. ii ADAPTING YOUR PRACTICE: Recommendations for End-of-Life Care for People Experiencing Homelessness Health Care for the Homeless Clinicians’ Network Preface Clinicians experienced in caring for individuals who are homeless routinely adapt their practice to foster better outcomes for these patients. This document was written for health-care professionals, program administrators, other staff, and students serving patients facing end of life who are homeless or at risk of homelessness.
    [Show full text]
  • How We Die in North Carolina
    How We Die in North Carolina ANNE DELLINGER n June 1998 the Wall Street Journal reported on seventy-year- old North Carolinian Claude Marion, who thought that he had prepared for death ten years ahead of time, but still did not re- Iceive the care he wanted.1 After he died, one of his daughters described the experience of acting as his advocate. Speaking of the divisions that emerged among patient, family, and physician, and eventually within the family, she said, [My father] just tried really hard to do the right thing. And he died in a very undignified way. I felt so help- less. My sister and I felt we had been to war. I don’t think there’s a good guy and a bad guy here. I think people were doing what they were taught.2 Following Mr. Marion’s emergency surgery at Wake Forest University Baptist Medical Center in Winston-Salem, he slipped in and out of conscious- ness, unable to make his wishes known. Although four successive complications repeatedly brought him close to death, the attending physician would not honor the living will, believing that Mr. Marion was not “terminal” (defined by the physician as having no chance for recovery).3 A hospital ethics council was convened, which agreed with Mr. Marion’s daughters that his condition was termi- nal. Rejecting the council’s opinion, the physician said he would continue to treat aggressively. A The Death of Socrates, painted by judge appointed Mr. Marion’s daughters his guardians. Meanwhile, Jacques Louis David in 1787, depicts though, some of their aunts and uncles took the physician’s side, the Greek philosopher about to drink and the family began arguing.
    [Show full text]
  • The Constitutional Status of Morals Legislation
    Kentucky Law Journal Volume 98 | Issue 1 Article 2 2009 The onsC titutional Status of Morals Legislation John Lawrence Hill Indiana University-Indianapolis Follow this and additional works at: https://uknowledge.uky.edu/klj Part of the Constitutional Law Commons, and the Law and Society Commons Right click to open a feedback form in a new tab to let us know how this document benefits you. Recommended Citation Hill, John Lawrence (2009) "The onC stitutional Status of Morals Legislation," Kentucky Law Journal: Vol. 98 : Iss. 1 , Article 2. Available at: https://uknowledge.uky.edu/klj/vol98/iss1/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Journals at UKnowledge. It has been accepted for inclusion in Kentucky Law Journal by an authorized editor of UKnowledge. For more information, please contact [email protected]. TKenf]iky Law Jornal VOLUME 98 2009-2010 NUMBER I ARTICLES The Constitutional Status of Morals Legislation John Lawrence Hiff TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION I. MORALS LEGISLATION AND THE HARM PRINCIPLE A. Some Difficulties with the Concept of "MoralsLegislation" B. The Near Irrelevance of the PhilosophicDebate C. The Concept of "Harm" II. DEFINING THE SCOPE OF THE PRIVACY RIGHT IN THE CONTEXT OF MORALS LEGISLATION III. MORALS LEGISLATION AND THE PROBLEMS OF RATIONAL BASIS REVIEW A. The 'RationalRelation' Test in Context B. The Concept of a Legitimate State Interest IV. MORALITY AS A LEGITIMATE STATE INTEREST: FIVE TYPES OF MORAL PURPOSE A. The Secondary or IndirectPublic Effects of PrivateActivity B. Offensive Conduct C. Preventingthe Corruptionof Moral Character D. ProtectingEssential Values andSocial Institutions E.
    [Show full text]
  • Attitude of Doctors Toward Euthanasia in Delhi, India
    Published online: 2019-04-05 Original Article AAttitudettitude ooff ddoctorsoctors ttowardoward eeuthanasiauthanasia iinn DDelhi,elhi, IIndiandia ABSTRACT Introduction: Deliberation over euthanasia has been enduring for an extended period of time. On one end, there are populaces talking for the sacrosanctity of life and on the other end, there are those, who promote individual independence. All over the world professionals from different areas have already spent mammoth period over the subject. A large number of cases around the world have explored the boundaries of current legal distinctions, drawn between legitimate and nonlegitimate instances of ending the life. The term euthanasia was derived from the Greek words “eu” and “thanatos” which means “good death” or “easy death.” It is also known as mercy killing. Euthanasia literally means putting a person to painless death especially in case of incurable suffering or when life becomes purposeless as a result of mental or physical handicap. Objective: To study the attitude of doctors toward euthanasia in Delhi. Methodology: It was a questionnaire based descriptive cross-sectional study carried out between July 2014 and December 2014. The study population included Doctors from 28 hospitals in Delhi both public and private. Equal numbers of doctors from four specialties were included in this study (50 oncologists, 50 hematologists, 50 psychiatrists, and 50 intensivists). Demographic questionnaire, as well as the Euthanasia Attitude Scale (EAS), a 30 items Likert-scale questionnaire developed by (Holloway, Hayslip and Murdock, 1995) was used to measure attitude toward Euthanasia. The scale uses both positively (16 items) and negatively (14 items) worded statements to control the effect of acquiescence.
    [Show full text]
  • Thesis Final
    In Pursuit of a Good Death: Responding to Changing Sensibilities in the Context of the Right to Die Debate A thesis submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Juridical Studies at the University of Sydney VICTORIA HILEY The Faculty of Law University of Sydney January 2008 ABSTRACT This thesis challenges a number of claims that are made in the context of the euthanasia debate: that there is only one version of the good death; that rights discourse is the most appropriate vehicle by which to secure legal recognition of a right to die; that the Netherlands is either a model for reform or the epitome of a slippery slope in its regulation of euthanasia; and that a key argument in the euthanasia debate, the sanctity of life doctrine, is a fixed, immutable concept. In this thesis I use process sociology, developed by Norbert Elias, in order to capture changing sensibilities toward death and dying in the common law jurisdictions (Australia, England, the United States of America, Canada and New Zealand) and in the Netherlands. At the same time I analyse changing attitudes among key groups whose work impacts upon the euthanasia debate namely, parliamentarians, law reform bodies, the judiciary and medical associations. My aim in adopting this approach is threefold. First of all, to examine evolving attitudes to death and dying in order to determine whether the institutions of law and medicine are responding in an adequate manner to changing sensibilities in the common law countries and in the Netherlands. Secondly, to highlight shifting balances of power within the euthanasia debate.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Relationship Between Suicide-Prevention and Suicide-Advocacy Groups
    Letter to the Editor On the Relationship Between Suicide-Prevention and Suicide-Advocacy Groups Margaret Pabst Battin Uniuersity of Utah Largely in response to contemporary medicine's advancing technological capacities to extend the process of dying to extraordinary lengths. recent years have seen the emergence of numerous advocacy groups concerned with what is often called "death with dignity." For instance. the New York-based group. Concern for Dying, distributes the Living Will as a means for individuals to secure their right to refuse unwanted, life-prolonging medical treatment. Another New York group, the Society for the Right to Die, lobbies for passage of "natural death" legislation, and has seen passage of Natural Death Acts in California and ten other U.S. states, and legislative consideration of similar bills in another twenty-seven. The Los Angeles-area group, Hemlock, led by a British writer who helped his cancer-striken wife drink a lethal potion, argues for societal recognition of assisted suicide as an option in terminal illness. Britain's Voluntary Euthanasia Society, once renamed EXIT: The Society for the Right to Die with Dignity, has published and distributed to its members a booklet of suicide methods for use by terminally ill persons; a similar book has become commercially available in France. Nor are such groups a local phenomenon; they are emerging world-wide. Although their views range from quite conservative insistence on passive refusal of treatment to radical suicide-advocacy, there are new voluntary euthanasia societies in Australia, Norway, Sweden, Japan, Denmark, New Zealand, South Africa, Holland, Germany, France, Colombia, Zimbabwe, Canada, India, and Switzerland.
    [Show full text]
  • The Chronically 111 Child and Recurring Family Grief
    The Chronically 111 Child and Recurring Family Grief Ralph C. Worthington, PhD Greenville, North Carolina Chronically ill children and their families are increasingly seen in health care prac­ tices as the incidence of infant mortality and formerly fatal childhood diseases has decreased. These children present special challenges to the physician's per­ ceived role as healer. Unlike the sequenced predictable stages of grief that fam­ ilies go through in facing terminal illness, the grief experienced by parents of the chronically ill is recurrent and cyclical. The physician who understands and can anticipate the causes and nature of this grief will be subject to less frustration in treating these children and their families and will be able to offer them more ef­ fective care. As the Joneses and their child left the office, the physi­ model of recurring grief that may help physicians antici­ cian reflected: Why are these parents, and evidently the pate, understand, and offer more effective care for families entire family, having such a difficult time accepting this of children with chronic illness. child’s chronic condition? One month I see them and they seem to have adjusted very well. Two months later and they all seem to be depressed. Another month, and they are hostile toward anyone that even looks like a doctor. THE CHRONICALLY ILL CHILD How can I get them to accept their child’s condition and make the best o f it? By now they should have worked their The past few decades have seen virtually an end to many way through this. childhood diseases.
    [Show full text]
  • Exposing Some Myths About Physician-Assisted Suicide
    Exposing Some Myths About Physician-Assisted Suicide Giles R. Scofield, J.D." I wish to express my gratitude to Professor Annette Clark and the students of the Seattle University Law Review for inviting me to participate in this symposium, and to submit my remarks for publica- tion. Although this essay reflects the essence of my remarks, I have taken the liberty of clarifying and expanding upon a few points. I. INTRODUCTION When I was asked to speak at this conference, I was at first hesitant to participate. In fact, I dreaded the prospect of speaking about the legalization of physician-assisted suicide. It's not that I have nothing to say on the issue; like everyone here, I too have something to say about it. Nor have I failed to think about this issue; on the contrary, I've had more than ample opportunity to ponder it. If I've thought about the topic enough to have something to say about it, why would I hesitate accepting this invitation? Why would I dread talking about an issue that has achieved such prominence? Basically, there are two reasons. First, we seem to have lost our ability to speak with one another about issues such as this. Instead of engaging one another in a conversation, we have substituted diatribe for dialogue and discord for discourse. The rhetoric of rights, and the simplistic thinking that such rhetoric creates and sustains, impedes our ability and even our willingness to listen to one another. The "I'm right; you're wrong" mentality that dominates these debates makes it impossible to get a word in edgewise.
    [Show full text]
  • Coroners' Records of Accidental Deaths
    Archives ofDisease in Childhood 1991; 66: 1239-1241 1239 Arch Dis Child: first published as 10.1136/adc.66.10.1239 on 1 October 1991. Downloaded from Coroners' records of accidental deaths Sara Levene Abstract the study. The four jurisdictions were Inner This study set out to provide a description of North London, Birmingham, Bedfordshire, the children involved in fatal accidents and to and Ipswich. ascertain which deaths might have been pre- All inquests opened in 1984-8 inclusive were vented and by what means. The records from analysed for children age 0-14. Cases where the a convenience sample of four coroners (juris- verdict was 'accidental death' or 'misadventure' dictions of Inner North London, Birmingham, other than medical accidents were included. In Bedfordshire, and Ipswich) of inquests addition, records where the verdict was 'unlawful opened in 1984-8 on children aged under 15 killing', 'death by natural causes', and 'open killed in accidents were reviewed for informa- verdict' were reviewed and included where tion on the deceased, the accident, and the appropriate. The following information was injuries sustained. Altogether 225 records systematically abstracted, ifavailable: (150 boys, 75 girls) were examined. Accidents * The coroner: jurisdiction, record number. to pedestrians were the commonest cause of * The deceased: name, address, sex, date of death (81 cases), and road safety engineering birth, height and weight, ethnic group. measures were the most likely means by * The family: parent's occupation, family which most fatalities might have been pre- structure. vented. The records frequently omitted * The accident: time, day, and date of information on social circumstances, family accident, accident type.
    [Show full text]