Cardinality Equivalent Sets Definition: We Say That Two Sets Are Equivalent (Sometimes Called Equipotent), Denoted by a ~ B Iff There Exists a Bijection F: a → B

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Cardinality Equivalent Sets Definition: We Say That Two Sets Are Equivalent (Sometimes Called Equipotent), Denoted by a ~ B Iff There Exists a Bijection F: a → B Cardinality Equivalent Sets Definition: We say that two sets are equivalent (sometimes called equipotent), denoted by A ~ B iff there exists a bijection f: A → B. This is an equivalence relation on the class of all sets: A ~ A for all sets A. (I : A → A is a bijection for all sets A) A If A ~ B then B ~ A. (If f:A → B is a bijection, f -1:B → A is also) If A ~ B and B ~ C then A ~ C. (If f:A → B is a bijection and g:B → C is a bijection, then g⊙f: A → C is a bijection) The equivalence classes under this relation are called cardinalities. Finite Sets We define some special sets of natural numbers: ℕ ℕ ℕ ℕ = {1} = {1,2} = {1,2,3}, ..., = {1,2,...,m} 1 2 3 m These sets are sometimes called initial segments. Definition: A set A is finite iff A = ∅ or A ~ ℕ for some m ∈ℕ. m A set is infinite iff it is not finite. We say that ∅ is of cardinality 0. If A ~ ℕ we say that A is of cardinality m. m ℕ This makes sense since A and are in the same equivalence m class, i.e., "are of the same cardinality". Finite Cardinalities When two finite sets are of the same cardinality, say of cardinality k, then by definition, there is a bijection between them, and from each of them onto ℕ . k Since a bijection sets up a one-to-one pairing of the elements in the domain and codomain, it is easy to see that all the sets of cardinality k, must have the same number of elements, namely k. Indeed, for any set that has k elements we can set up a bijection between that set and ℕ . So, for finite sets, all the sets in the k same cardinality have the same number of elements. This is why we often refer to a cardinality as a cardinal number. ℕ Since the definition of an infinite set is a "negation", we should expect that most proofs about them will use contradiction methods. Theorem: ℕ is an infinite set. Pf: BWOC assume that ℕ is a finite set. ℕ ℕ Then there exists a bijection f: → for some k. k Let n = f(1) + f(2) + ... + f(k) + 1. Then n is a natural number (being the sum of natural numbers) and n > f(i) for any i. So n is in the codomain of f, but since it can not equal any f(i), it is not in the Rng(f). So, f is not onto →← Denumerable Sets Definition: A set is denumerable iff it is of the same cardinality as ℕ. (Also known as countably infinite.) The cardinality of the denumerable sets is denoted ℵ which is read 0 as "aleph naught" or "aleph null". (ℵ is the first letter of the Hebrew alphabet.) One may be tempted to say, in analogy with finite sets, that all denumerable sets have the same number of elements, or all denumerable sets have ℵ elements. As our next example will 0 show, you probably should avoid this temptation. ℕ~2ℕ Let 2ℕ denote the set of all even natural numbers. Theorem: 2ℕ is denumerable. Pf: To prove this we must find a bijection f: ℕ → 2ℕ. Our candidate will be f(x) = 2x with domain ℕ. This f is one-to-one: Suppose f(x) = f(y). Then 2x = 2y, so x=y. This f is onto: Let y be an arbitrary element of the codomain 2ℕ Since y is an even natural number, y = 2k for some k in ℕ. Thus, f(k) = 2k = y, and f is onto. f is a bijection, and so, ℕ~2ℕ i.e., 2ℕ is denumerable. So, the number of even natural numbers is the same as the number of all natural numbers ????? So, what gives? On the one hand, our intuition tells us that this last statement can't be correct. Every even natural number is in ℕ, but ℕ also has odd natural numbers ... so ℕ must have more elements than 2ℕ ! But, the bijection between these sets, pairs up the elements exactly, so there are just as many elements in one set as in the other! Something has to give ... these are contradictory results. Realize that intuition is built up from experience. Our direct experience with sets is limited to finite sets ... so our intuition is usually ok for these. But we have no direct experience with infinite sets (for instance, you've never counted the elements in one), and our intuition leads us astray when it comes to infinite sets! Denumerable + 1 = Denumerable Theorem: If A is denumerable and x ∉ A then A ∪ {x} is denumerable. Pf: Since A is denumerable there exists a bijection g: ℕ → A. Now define f: ℕ → A ∪ {x} by: f(1) = x f(2) = g(1) f(3) = g(2) .... and in general f(n) = g(n-1) for n > 1. f is one-to-one since no two images of f can be the same (no two images of g are the same, and none of them is x) f is onto because g is onto A and x is certainly in Rng(f). So, f is a bijection. Listable Sets? This is a Cherowitzo special definition – you will not find this anywhere in the literature. A denumerable set is one whose elements can written in a list (an infinite list) where all the elements appear somewhere and no element appears twice. If you can create such a list of elements of the set, then you can define a function whose arguments are the elements of the set and whose values are the positions in the list where the elements appear. This function is a bijection between the set and ℕ ... thus proving that the set is denumerable. Thus, you can prove that a set is denumerable by creating this list. So, maybe, denumerable sets should be called listable sets. Union of Denumerable Sets Theorem: If A and B are disjoint denumerable sets then A ∪ B is denumerable. Pf: Since A is denumerable we can list its elements as: a , a , a , ... 1 2 3 Since B is denumerable we can also list its elements as: b , b , b , .... 1 2 3 We can now form a list of the elements of A ∪ B this way: a , b , a , b , a , b , ..... 1 1 2 2 3 3 Clearly, every element of A ∪ B appears exactly once on this list, so A ∪ B is denumerable. More formally, we can define the bijection f from A ∪ B onto ℕ by: − = = 2k 1 when x a k f x { = } . 2k when x bk ℤ is denumerable We can apply the theorems we have just proved to obtain this result. First, notice that -ℕ is denumerable. (Consider f(x) = -x ). Since 0 ∉ ℕ we have that A = ℕ ∪ {0} is denumerable. Then ℤ = ℕ ∪ {0} ∪ -ℕ = A ∪ -ℕ is denumerable. ℚ is denumerable From the last chapter we know that ℕ×ℕ is denumerable since the function f: ℕ×ℕℕ given by f(n,m) = 2n-1(2m – 1) is a bijection. Theorem: If A and B are denumerable sets, then A×B is denumerable. Pf: Since A and B are denumerable, there exist bijections f:Aℕ and g:Bℕ. Now consider the function h:A×Bℕ×ℕ given by h(a,b) = (f(a), g(b)). We show that h is a bijection. Suppose that h(a,b) = h(c,d) ⇒ (f(a),g(b)) = (f(c),g(d)) ⇒ f(a) = f(c) and g(b) = g(d). Since f is an injection a = c, and since g is an injection b = d. Now, let (c,d) be an arbitrary element of ℕ×ℕ. Since f is onto, there is an a ∈ ℕ with f(a) = c, and since g is onto there is a b ∈ ℕ with g(b) = d. So, h(a,b) = (f(a),g(b)) = (c,d), so h is a bijection. The composition of h with f above shows that A×B is denumerable. ℚ is denumerable Since ℤ is denumerable, the last theorem shows that ℤ×ℤ is denumerable. Theorem: Any infinite subset of a denumerable set is denumerable. Pf: Since the original set is denumerable, its elements can be put into a list. By passing through this list and removing any element which is not in the subset, we obtain a list of the elements of the subset. By identifying each fraction p/q with the ordered pair (p,q) in ℤ×ℤ we see that the set of fractions is denumerable. By identifying each rational number with the fraction in reduced form that represents it, we see that ℚ is denumerable. Countable Sets Definition: A countable set is a set which is either finite or denumerable. In most theorems involving denumerable sets the term denumerable can be replaced by countable. Proofs involve extending the proofs for denumerable sets by checking the cases when one or more of the sets involved are finite. Thus: Theorem: If A is countable and x ∉ A then A ∪ {x} is countable. Theorem: If A and B are disjoint countable sets then A ∪ B is countable. Theorem: If A and B are countable sets, then A×B is countable. Theorem: Any subset of a countable set is countable. Countable Union Theorem: Let A be a countable family of countable sets. Then ∪A is countable. This theorem while plausible can not be proved from the generally accepted axioms of set theory (Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms).
Recommended publications
  • Set Theory, by Thomas Jech, Academic Press, New York, 1978, Xii + 621 Pp., '$53.00
    BOOK REVIEWS 775 BULLETIN (New Series) OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 3, Number 1, July 1980 © 1980 American Mathematical Society 0002-9904/80/0000-0 319/$01.75 Set theory, by Thomas Jech, Academic Press, New York, 1978, xii + 621 pp., '$53.00. "General set theory is pretty trivial stuff really" (Halmos; see [H, p. vi]). At least, with the hindsight afforded by Cantor, Zermelo, and others, it is pretty trivial to do the following. First, write down a list of axioms about sets and membership, enunciating some "obviously true" set-theoretic principles; the most popular Hst today is called ZFC (the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms with the axiom of Choice). Next, explain how, from ZFC, one may derive all of conventional mathematics, including the general theory of transfinite cardi­ nals and ordinals. This "trivial" part of set theory is well covered in standard texts, such as [E] or [H]. Jech's book is an introduction to the "nontrivial" part. Now, nontrivial set theory may be roughly divided into two general areas. The first area, classical set theory, is a direct outgrowth of Cantor's work. Cantor set down the basic properties of cardinal numbers. In particular, he showed that if K is a cardinal number, then 2", or exp(/c), is a cardinal strictly larger than K (if A is a set of size K, 2* is the cardinality of the family of all subsets of A). Now starting with a cardinal K, we may form larger cardinals exp(ic), exp2(ic) = exp(exp(fc)), exp3(ic) = exp(exp2(ic)), and in fact this may be continued through the transfinite to form expa(»c) for every ordinal number a.
    [Show full text]
  • Mathematics 144 Set Theory Fall 2012 Version
    MATHEMATICS 144 SET THEORY FALL 2012 VERSION Table of Contents I. General considerations.……………………………………………………………………………………………………….1 1. Overview of the course…………………………………………………………………………………………………1 2. Historical background and motivation………………………………………………………….………………4 3. Selected problems………………………………………………………………………………………………………13 I I. Basic concepts. ………………………………………………………………………………………………………………….15 1. Topics from logic…………………………………………………………………………………………………………16 2. Notation and first steps………………………………………………………………………………………………26 3. Simple examples…………………………………………………………………………………………………………30 I I I. Constructions in set theory.………………………………………………………………………………..……….34 1. Boolean algebra operations.……………………………………………………………………………………….34 2. Ordered pairs and Cartesian products……………………………………………………………………… ….40 3. Larger constructions………………………………………………………………………………………………..….42 4. A convenient assumption………………………………………………………………………………………… ….45 I V. Relations and functions ……………………………………………………………………………………………….49 1.Binary relations………………………………………………………………………………………………………… ….49 2. Partial and linear orderings……………………………..………………………………………………… ………… 56 3. Functions…………………………………………………………………………………………………………… ….…….. 61 4. Composite and inverse function.…………………………………………………………………………… …….. 70 5. Constructions involving functions ………………………………………………………………………… ……… 77 6. Order types……………………………………………………………………………………………………… …………… 80 i V. Number systems and set theory …………………………………………………………………………………. 84 1. The Natural Numbers and Integers…………………………………………………………………………….83 2. Finite induction
    [Show full text]
  • Algebra I Chapter 1. Basic Facts from Set Theory 1.1 Glossary of Abbreviations
    Notes: c F.P. Greenleaf, 2000-2014 v43-s14sets.tex (version 1/1/2014) Algebra I Chapter 1. Basic Facts from Set Theory 1.1 Glossary of abbreviations. Below we list some standard math symbols that will be used as shorthand abbreviations throughout this course. means “for all; for every” • ∀ means “there exists (at least one)” • ∃ ! means “there exists exactly one” • ∃ s.t. means “such that” • = means “implies” • ⇒ means “if and only if” • ⇐⇒ x A means “the point x belongs to a set A;” x / A means “x is not in A” • ∈ ∈ N denotes the set of natural numbers (counting numbers) 1, 2, 3, • · · · Z denotes the set of all integers (positive, negative or zero) • Q denotes the set of rational numbers • R denotes the set of real numbers • C denotes the set of complex numbers • x A : P (x) If A is a set, this denotes the subset of elements x in A such that •statement { ∈ P (x)} is true. As examples of the last notation for specifying subsets: x R : x2 +1 2 = ( , 1] [1, ) { ∈ ≥ } −∞ − ∪ ∞ x R : x2 +1=0 = { ∈ } ∅ z C : z2 +1=0 = +i, i where i = √ 1 { ∈ } { − } − 1.2 Basic facts from set theory. Next we review the basic definitions and notations of set theory, which will be used throughout our discussions of algebra. denotes the empty set, the set with nothing in it • ∅ x A means that the point x belongs to a set A, or that x is an element of A. • ∈ A B means A is a subset of B – i.e.
    [Show full text]
  • Is Uncountable the Open Interval (0, 1)
    Section 2.4:R is uncountable (0, 1) is uncountable This assertion and its proof date back to the 1890’s and to Georg Cantor. The proof is often referred to as “Cantor’s diagonal argument” and applies in more general contexts than we will see in these notes. Our goal in this section is to show that the setR of real numbers is uncountable or non-denumerable; this means that its elements cannot be listed, or cannot be put in bijective correspondence with the natural numbers. We saw at the end of Section 2.3 that R has the same cardinality as the interval ( π , π ), or the interval ( 1, 1), or the interval (0, 1). We will − 2 2 − show that the open interval (0, 1) is uncountable. Georg Cantor : born in St Petersburg (1845), died in Halle (1918) Theorem 42 The open interval (0, 1) is not a countable set. Dr Rachel Quinlan MA180/MA186/MA190 Calculus R is uncountable 143 / 222 Dr Rachel Quinlan MA180/MA186/MA190 Calculus R is uncountable 144 / 222 The open interval (0, 1) is not a countable set A hypothetical bijective correspondence Our goal is to show that the interval (0, 1) cannot be put in bijective correspondence with the setN of natural numbers. Our strategy is to We recall precisely what this set is. show that no attempt at constructing a bijective correspondence between It consists of all real numbers that are greater than zero and less these two sets can ever be complete; it can never involve all the real than 1, or equivalently of all the points on the number line that are numbers in the interval (0, 1) no matter how it is devised.
    [Show full text]
  • 641 1. P. Erdös and A. H. Stone, Some Remarks on Almost Periodic
    1946] DENSITY CHARACTERS 641 BIBLIOGRAPHY 1. P. Erdös and A. H. Stone, Some remarks on almost periodic transformations, Bull. Amer. Math. Soc. vol. 51 (1945) pp. 126-130. 2. W. H. Gottschalk, Powers of homeomorphisms with almost periodic propertiesf Bull. Amer. Math. Soc. vol. 50 (1944) pp. 222-227. UNIVERSITY OF PENNSYLVANIA AND UNIVERSITY OF VIRGINIA A REMARK ON DENSITY CHARACTERS EDWIN HEWITT1 Let X be an arbitrary topological space satisfying the TVseparation axiom [l, Chap. 1, §4, p. 58].2 We recall the following definition [3, p. 329]. DEFINITION 1. The least cardinal number of a dense subset of the space X is said to be the density character of X. It is denoted by the symbol %{X). We denote the cardinal number of a set A by | A |. Pospisil has pointed out [4] that if X is a Hausdorff space, then (1) |X| g 22SW. This inequality is easily established. Let D be a dense subset of the Hausdorff space X such that \D\ =S(-X'). For an arbitrary point pÇ^X and an arbitrary complete neighborhood system Vp at p, let Vp be the family of all sets UC\D, where U^VP. Thus to every point of X, a certain family of subsets of D is assigned. Since X is a Haus­ dorff space, VpT^Vq whenever p j*£q, and the correspondence assigning each point p to the family <DP is one-to-one. Since X is in one-to-one correspondence with a sub-hierarchy of the hierarchy of all families of subsets of D, the inequality (1) follows.
    [Show full text]
  • Ergodicity and Metric Transitivity
    Chapter 25 Ergodicity and Metric Transitivity Section 25.1 explains the ideas of ergodicity (roughly, there is only one invariant set of positive measure) and metric transivity (roughly, the system has a positive probability of going from any- where to anywhere), and why they are (almost) the same. Section 25.2 gives some examples of ergodic systems. Section 25.3 deduces some consequences of ergodicity, most im- portantly that time averages have deterministic limits ( 25.3.1), and an asymptotic approach to independence between even§ts at widely separated times ( 25.3.2), admittedly in a very weak sense. § 25.1 Metric Transitivity Definition 341 (Ergodic Systems, Processes, Measures and Transfor- mations) A dynamical system Ξ, , µ, T is ergodic, or an ergodic system or an ergodic process when µ(C) = 0 orXµ(C) = 1 for every T -invariant set C. µ is called a T -ergodic measure, and T is called a µ-ergodic transformation, or just an ergodic measure and ergodic transformation, respectively. Remark: Most authorities require a µ-ergodic transformation to also be measure-preserving for µ. But (Corollary 54) measure-preserving transforma- tions are necessarily stationary, and we want to minimize our stationarity as- sumptions. So what most books call “ergodic”, we have to qualify as “stationary and ergodic”. (Conversely, when other people talk about processes being “sta- tionary and ergodic”, they mean “stationary with only one ergodic component”; but of that, more later. Definition 342 (Metric Transitivity) A dynamical system is metrically tran- sitive, metrically indecomposable, or irreducible when, for any two sets A, B n ∈ , if µ(A), µ(B) > 0, there exists an n such that µ(T − A B) > 0.
    [Show full text]
  • POINT-COFINITE COVERS in the LAVER MODEL 1. Background Let
    PROCEEDINGS OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 138, Number 9, September 2010, Pages 3313–3321 S 0002-9939(10)10407-9 Article electronically published on April 30, 2010 POINT-COFINITE COVERS IN THE LAVER MODEL ARNOLD W. MILLER AND BOAZ TSABAN (Communicated by Julia Knight) Abstract. Let S1(Γ, Γ) be the statement: For each sequence of point-cofinite open covers, one can pick one element from each cover and obtain a point- cofinite cover. b is the minimal cardinality of a set of reals not satisfying S1(Γ, Γ). We prove the following assertions: (1) If there is an unbounded tower, then there are sets of reals of cardinality b satisfying S1(Γ, Γ). (2) It is consistent that all sets of reals satisfying S1(Γ, Γ) have cardinality smaller than b. These results can also be formulated as dealing with Arhangel’ski˘ı’s property α2 for spaces of continuous real-valued functions. The main technical result is that in Laver’s model, each set of reals of cardinality b has an unbounded Borel image in the Baire space ωω. 1. Background Let P be a nontrivial property of sets of reals. The critical cardinality of P , denoted non(P ), is the minimal cardinality of a set of reals not satisfying P .A natural question is whether there is a set of reals of cardinality at least non(P ), which satisfies P , i.e., a nontrivial example. We consider the following property. Let X be a set of reals. U is a point-cofinite cover of X if U is infinite, and for each x ∈ X, {U ∈U: x ∈ U} is a cofinite subset of U.1 Having X fixed in the background, let Γ be the family of all point- cofinite open covers of X.
    [Show full text]
  • Cardinality of Sets
    Cardinality of Sets MAT231 Transition to Higher Mathematics Fall 2014 MAT231 (Transition to Higher Math) Cardinality of Sets Fall 2014 1 / 15 Outline 1 Sets with Equal Cardinality 2 Countable and Uncountable Sets MAT231 (Transition to Higher Math) Cardinality of Sets Fall 2014 2 / 15 Sets with Equal Cardinality Definition Two sets A and B have the same cardinality, written jAj = jBj, if there exists a bijective function f : A ! B. If no such bijective function exists, then the sets have unequal cardinalities, that is, jAj 6= jBj. Another way to say this is that jAj = jBj if there is a one-to-one correspondence between the elements of A and the elements of B. For example, to show that the set A = f1; 2; 3; 4g and the set B = {♠; ~; }; |g have the same cardinality it is sufficient to construct a bijective function between them. 1 2 3 4 ♠ ~ } | MAT231 (Transition to Higher Math) Cardinality of Sets Fall 2014 3 / 15 Sets with Equal Cardinality Consider the following: This definition does not involve the number of elements in the sets. It works equally well for finite and infinite sets. Any bijection between the sets is sufficient. MAT231 (Transition to Higher Math) Cardinality of Sets Fall 2014 4 / 15 The set Z contains all the numbers in N as well as numbers not in N. So maybe Z is larger than N... On the other hand, both sets are infinite, so maybe Z is the same size as N... This is just the sort of ambiguity we want to avoid, so we appeal to the definition of \same cardinality." The answer to our question boils down to \Can we find a bijection between N and Z?" Does jNj = jZj? True or false: Z is larger than N.
    [Show full text]
  • A TEXTBOOK of TOPOLOGY Lltld
    SEIFERT AND THRELFALL: A TEXTBOOK OF TOPOLOGY lltld SEI FER T: 7'0PO 1.OG 1' 0 I.' 3- Dl M E N SI 0 N A I. FIRERED SPACES This is a volume in PURE AND APPLIED MATHEMATICS A Series of Monographs and Textbooks Editors: SAMUELEILENBERG AND HYMANBASS A list of recent titles in this series appears at the end of this volunie. SEIFERT AND THRELFALL: A TEXTBOOK OF TOPOLOGY H. SEIFERT and W. THRELFALL Translated by Michael A. Goldman und S E I FE R T: TOPOLOGY OF 3-DIMENSIONAL FIBERED SPACES H. SEIFERT Translated by Wolfgang Heil Edited by Joan S. Birman and Julian Eisner @ 1980 ACADEMIC PRESS A Subsidiary of Harcourr Brace Jovanovich, Publishers NEW YORK LONDON TORONTO SYDNEY SAN FRANCISCO COPYRIGHT@ 1980, BY ACADEMICPRESS, INC. ALL RIGHTS RESERVED. NO PART OF THIS PUBLICATION MAY BE REPRODUCED OR TRANSMITTED IN ANY FORM OR BY ANY MEANS, ELECTRONIC OR MECHANICAL, INCLUDING PHOTOCOPY, RECORDING, OR ANY INFORMATION STORAGE AND RETRIEVAL SYSTEM, WITHOUT PERMISSION IN WRITING FROM THE PUBLISHER. ACADEMIC PRESS, INC. 11 1 Fifth Avenue, New York. New York 10003 United Kingdom Edition published by ACADEMIC PRESS, INC. (LONDON) LTD. 24/28 Oval Road, London NWI 7DX Mit Genehmigung des Verlager B. G. Teubner, Stuttgart, veranstaltete, akin autorisierte englische Ubersetzung, der deutschen Originalausgdbe. Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Seifert, Herbert, 1897- Seifert and Threlfall: A textbook of topology. Seifert: Topology of 3-dimensional fibered spaces. (Pure and applied mathematics, a series of mono- graphs and textbooks ; ) Translation of Lehrbuch der Topologic. Bibliography: p. Includes index. 1.
    [Show full text]
  • The Hardness of the Hidden Subset Sum Problem and Its Cryptographic Implications
    The Hardness of the Hidden Subset Sum Problem and Its Cryptographic Implications Phong Nguyen and Jacques Stern Ecole´ Normale Sup´erieure Laboratoire d’Informatique 45 rue d’Ulm, 75230 Paris Cedex 05 France fPhong.Nguyen,[email protected] http://www.dmi.ens.fr/~fpnguyen,sterng/ Abstract. At Eurocrypt’98, Boyko, Peinado and Venkatesan presented simple and very fast methods for generating randomly distributed pairs of the form (x; gx mod p) using precomputation. The security of these methods relied on the potential hardness of a new problem, the so-called hidden subset sum problem. Surprisingly, apart from exhaustive search, no algorithm to solve this problem was known. In this paper, we exhibit a security criterion for the hidden subset sum problem, and discuss its implications on the practicability of the precomputation schemes. Our results are twofold. On the one hand, we present an efficient lattice-based attack which is expected to succeed if and only if the parameters satisfy a particular condition that we make explicit. Experiments have validated the theoretical analysis, and show the limitations of the precomputa- tion methods. For instance, any realistic smart-card implementation of Schnorr’s identification scheme using these precomputations methods is either vulnerable to the attack, or less efficient than with traditional pre- computation methods. On the other hand, we show that, when another condition is satisfied, the pseudo-random generator based on the hidden subset sum problem is strong in some precise sense which includes at- tacks via lattice reduction. Namely, using the discrete Fourier transform, we prove that the distribution of the generator’s output is indistinguish- able from the uniform distribution.
    [Show full text]
  • Cardinal Invariants Concerning Functions Whose Sum Is Almost Continuous Krzysztof Ciesielski West Virginia University, [email protected]
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by The Research Repository @ WVU (West Virginia University) Faculty Scholarship 1995 Cardinal Invariants Concerning Functions Whose Sum Is Almost Continuous Krzysztof Ciesielski West Virginia University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://researchrepository.wvu.edu/faculty_publications Part of the Mathematics Commons Digital Commons Citation Ciesielski, Krzysztof, "Cardinal Invariants Concerning Functions Whose Sum Is Almost Continuous" (1995). Faculty Scholarship. 822. https://researchrepository.wvu.edu/faculty_publications/822 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The Research Repository @ WVU. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of The Research Repository @ WVU. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Cardinal invariants concerning functions whose sum is almost continuous. Krzysztof Ciesielski1, Department of Mathematics, West Virginia University, Mor- gantown, WV 26506-6310 ([email protected]) Arnold W. Miller1, York University, Department of Mathematics, North York, Ontario M3J 1P3, Canada, Permanent address: University of Wisconsin-Madison, Department of Mathematics, Van Vleck Hall, 480 Lincoln Drive, Madison, Wis- consin 53706-1388, USA ([email protected]) Abstract Let A stand for the class of all almost continuous functions from R to R and let A(A) be the smallest cardinality of a family F ⊆ RR for which there is no g: R → R with the property that f + g ∈ A for all f ∈ F . We define cardinal number A(D) for the class D of all real functions with the Darboux property similarly.
    [Show full text]
  • Composite Subset Measures
    Composite Subset Measures Lei Chen1, Raghu Ramakrishnan1,2, Paul Barford1, Bee-Chung Chen1, Vinod Yegneswaran1 1 Computer Sciences Department, University of Wisconsin, Madison, WI, USA 2 Yahoo! Research, Santa Clara, CA, USA {chenl, pb, beechung, vinod}@cs.wisc.edu [email protected] ABSTRACT into a hierarchy, leading to a very natural notion of multidimen- Measures are numeric summaries of a collection of data records sional regions. Each region represents a data subset. Summarizing produced by applying aggregation functions. Summarizing a col- the records that belong to a region by applying an aggregate opera- lection of subsets of a large dataset, by computing a measure for tor, such as SUM, to a measure attribute (thereby computing a new each subset in the (typically, user-specified) collection is a funda- measure that is associated with the entire region) is a fundamental mental problem. The multidimensional data model, which treats operation in OLAP. records as points in a space defined by dimension attributes, offers Often, however, more sophisticated analysis can be carried out a natural space of data subsets to be considered as summarization based on the computed measures, e.g., identifying regions with candidates, and traditional SQL and OLAP constructs, such as abnormally high measures. For such analyses, it is necessary to GROUP BY and CUBE, allow us to compute measures for subsets compute the measure for a region by also considering other re- drawn from this space. However, GROUP BY only allows us to gions (which are, intuitively, “related” to the given region) and summarize a limited collection of subsets, and CUBE summarizes their measures.
    [Show full text]