Normative Concepts and Motivation

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Normative Concepts and Motivation How is our grasp of reasons related to motivation? Are judgments about what justifies our behavior entirely inde- pendent from the motivational processes that actually cause that behavior? Internalists think they are not: they claim that there is a necessary connection between our grasp of reasons and motivation. The central topic of this paper will be a new approach to the debates about internalism. Proponents of internalism have traditionally drawn a sharp contrast between theoreti- cal inquiry and practical reasoning.1 Breaking with this tra- dition, Philip Pettit, Michael Smith, and Tyler Burge have re- cently suggested that the similarities between theoretical and Normative Concepts 2 practical reasoning can bolster the case for internalism. Focusing on the similarities between theoretical and and Motivation practical reasoning provides a fruitful perspective on the internalist debates. For one thing, the new approach places the focus squarely on the core issue in the internalist de- bates: what are the connections between our grasp of rea- 1 See, in particular, the standard expressivist defenses of internalism: A. J. Ayer, Language, Truth, and Logic (London: Gollancz, 1946), chap. 6; Charles François Schroeter L. Stevenson, “The Emotive Meaning of Moral Terms,” Mind 46 (1937): 14-31; R. M. Hare, The Language of Morals (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1952); and Simon Blackburn, Spreading the Word (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984), chap. 6. Expressivists typically emphasize that theoretical inquiry is constrained by evidence and aims at representing the world while practical reasoning is con- strained by desires and issues in judgments whose necessary connection to mo- tivation jeopardizes their status as beliefs representing the world. Allan Gibbard also proposes an expressivist defense of internalism (see his Wise Choices, Apt Feelings: A Theory of Normative Judgment [Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1990]). Gibbard, however, is concerned to emphasize some of the major similarities between theoretical inquiry and practical reasoning. In his view, theoretical inquiry is infused with normative judgments and these judgments are amenable to the same theoretical treatment as those which are the upshot of Philosophers’ Imprint practical deliberation. <www.philosophersimprint.org/005003/> 2 See Philip Pettit and Michael Smith, “Freedom in Belief and Desire,” Journal of Philosophy 93 (1996): 429-49; and Tyler Burge, “Reason and the Volume 5, No. 3 First Person,” in Knowing Our Own Minds, ed. Crispin Wright, Barry C. Smith, May 2005 and Cynthia McDonald (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998), 243-70. © 2005 François Schroeter François Schroeter is a Lecturer in the Philosophy Department at the University of Melbourne. François Schroeter Normative Concepts and Motivation sons – both epistemic and practical – and motivation? All these judgments (or beliefs).5 (2) Existence internalists, on too often, disputes about internalism have centered on the the other hand, claim that necessarily, if an action is the right particular nature of moral judgments and have evaded this thing for an agent to do, that agent is capable of being moti- more fundamental question.3 In addition, the new approach vated to act accordingly. In this paper, I’ll be exclusively exploits an important insight about the nature of practical concerned with the first of these two types of internalism, reasoning: there are clearly important similarities between which I simply call ‘internalism’.6 our recognition and assessment of reasons in the theoretical We can distinguish between two different types of moti- and the practical domains. Given the prominence of neo- vation which the internalist might have in mind when he Humean views in practical philosophy, it is easy to forget claims that normative beliefs are necessarily tied to motiva- how sophisticated our reasoning about what to do typically tion: is and how closely it parallels theoretical reasoning. Much of this paper will be devoted to exploring the similarities (i) a motivation that is “grounded” or “based” between theoretical and practical reasoning (sections 3 and in the normative belief; 4). This exploration will provide the necessary background (ii) a motivation that is independent from the for filling in the details of the new approach to internalism normative belief. and for assessing its success (sections 5 and 6). Suppose, for instance, that I judge that the right thing to do 1. A new perspective on internalism is to eat chocolate. It’s not just that it tastes good; as it hap- I’ll start with some clarifications about how internalism pens it is also good for my health. In this case, I might have should be understood and turn then to the new approach to two kinds of motivation to perform the action sanctioned as internalism. right by my judgment: a motivation based on my normative Following Stephen Darwall, metaethicists usually distin- belief and a brute desire to eat the chocolate. In this paper, guish between two main types of internalism.4 (1) Judgment my focus will be on motivation of type (i), which I call “mo- internalists claim that necessarily, if a person makes norma- 5 Internalists are standardly interpreted as making claims about conceptual tive judgments (or holds normative beliefs) about what is necessity, where conceptual necessity is understood as metaphysical necessity knowable a priori on the basis of reflection available to anyone who possesses right for her to do, she is motivated to act in conformity with the relevant concepts. In this paper, I’ll follow this standard interpretation of internalism. 6 In order to remain neutral between cognitivists and expressivists, 3 See, for instance, the criticisms of internalism in David O. Brink, Moral metaethicists typically use the term ‘judgment’ rather than ‘belief’ in their expli- Realism and the Foundations of Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University cation of internalism (a normative judgment may be a belief, but it may also be, Press, 1989), 37-80; and Sigrún Svavarsdóttir, “Moral Cognitivism and Motiva- as expressivists maintain, a pro-attitude). The use of the term ‘judgment’ may tion,” Philosophical Review 108 (1999): 161-219. Brink and Svavarsdóttir con- suggest that internalists are concerned with the occurrent, conscious state of centrate their attention on the amoralist: they ask whether the amoralist can making a judgment and not with the standing state of believing. This suggestion count as making moral judgments even if he has no moral motivation. The is unfortunate: if there are general motivational constraints on the deployment of question of the connection between our grasp of practical reasons and motiva- normative concepts in judgments, the deployment of these concepts in beliefs tion is left to the side in these debates. should be subject to similar constraints. I’ll talk about normative beliefs in my 4 See Stephen L. Darwall, Impartial Reason (Ithaca: Cornell University explication of internalism and I’ll leave it to expressivists to substitute for ‘be- Press, 1983), 54, for this distinction. lief’ a term referring to their favorite pro-attitude. 2 François Schroeter Normative Concepts and Motivation tivation to act in conformity (or accordance) with”, or “moti- between normative concepts and motivation. I’ll focus here vation to conform to”, one’s normative beliefs. This is the on a weak form of internalism that is entailed by all different type of motivation that plays the central role in Pettit, Smith versions of the doctrine and suffices to demarcate it from and Burge’s approach to internalism. It is also the type of standard externalist claims. A strong version of internalism motivation that matters in the story I’ll sketch about the would claim that normative beliefs must always, or in gen- normal functional role of normative beliefs. eral, be accompanied by motivation. Instead, I will consider Traditionally, proponents of internalism have claimed here the minimal internalist claim that, necessarily, such ties that motivation is constitutive of normative beliefs. Expres- exist at least in some cases. The externalist, on the other hand, sivists, for instance, contend that the mental state expressed insists that a subject who is never motivated to act in accor- in a normative judgment is constituted at least in part by dance with his putative normative judgments can possess having some motivation to act as the judgment prescribes. normative concepts and thus can have beliefs with norma- One can be an internalist, however, while rejecting this con- tive content. Similarly, the point of contention in the debates stitutive claim.7 There may be necessary connections be- over experiential concepts is whether possessing such con- tween normative beliefs and the corresponding motivation cepts is consistent with never having had the relevant experi- even if the motivation is not literally part of the belief itself. ence. As the example of experiential concepts suggests, the Thus, the internalist can simply argue that a subject who is necessary connection between a concept and a different type never motivated to act according to normative considera- of mental state (such as an experience or a motivation) can tions cannot possess the concept ‘is the right thing to do’ and be a weak one without vitiating the interest of that necessary thus cannot hold genuine normative beliefs. Similar claims connection.9 can be found in the debates about the possession conditions My weak version of the internalist thesis is preferable to for experiential concepts such as ‘experiencing red’: some an important alternative proposal inspired by Michael theorists claim that one cannot possess such an experiential Smith.10 Like most internalists, Smith rejects the strong in- concept without being able to recognize the relevant experi- ternalist claim according to which first-person present-tense ence from a first-person perspective.8 In what follows, I will normative judgments must always be linked to the corre- approach internalism via the question of the possession con- sponding motivation. In his view, internalists should be in- ditions for normative concepts.
Recommended publications
  • Scanlon on the Metaphysics of Reasons
    Against Quietist Normative Realism Forthcoming in Philosophical Studies Tristram McPherson University of Minnesota Duluth [email protected] Note: This is the author’s penultimate manuscript of this paper (ms. of March 1, 2010). The final publication is available at www.springerlink.com. Abstract: Recently, some philosophers have suggested that a form of robust realism about ethics, or normativity more generally, does not face a significant explanatory burden in metaphysics. I call this view metaphysically quietist normative realism. This paper argues that while this view can appear to constitute an attractive alternative to more traditional forms of normative realism, it cannot deliver on this promise. I examine T. M. Scanlon’s attempt to defend such a quietist realism, and argue that rather than silencing metaphysical questions about normative reasons, his defense at best succeeds only in shifting the focus of metaphysical enquiry. I then set aside the details of Scanlon’s view, and argue on general grounds that that the quietist realist cannot finesse a crucial metanormative task: to explain the contrast between the correct normative system and alternative putatively normative standards. Keywords: metaethics, metanormative quietism, metanormative realism, normativity, reasons, Scanlon McPherson Against quietist normative realism MS 1 Introduction Philosophers interested in normative domains such as ethics or epistemology face a persistent challenge: to understand how our practices of normative judgment and discourse fit within our best general account of the world. I will call this the metanormative project.1 (Contrast the more familiar metaethical project, which addresses similar questions about specifically moral or practical norms.) Roughly, metanormative realists think that normative claims are made true by their correspondence to the normative facts.2 Metanormative realists appear to face a daunting metaphysical challenge, which can be partially characterized by noting three central desiderata for a metanormative theory.
    [Show full text]
  • Moral Theories Course Leader
    PHIL 101: Conceptual Foundations of Bioethics: Moral Theories Course Leader: Stavroula Tsinorema Semester: 1st (7 ECTS) Course Type: Required Objectives: The aims of this course unit are (a) to bring students in contact with the theoretical basis of Bioethics, through training in the methodologies and analytical tools of moral reasoning, (b) to provide them with the basic categories which show the conceptual links between the frameworks of moral philosophy and normative bioethical reasoning, (c) to equip them with the appropriate theoretical frameworks in order to be able to investigate critically and, where possible, to resolve specific moral problems deriving in biomedical research, its application in clinical contexts, health care and environmental policy. The overall aim is to enable students to develop core skills for the conduct of normative analysis and reasoning in Bioethics. Content: The normative resources for moral argument and justification in Bioethics are found in moral philosophy and philosophical theories of ethics. This course unit will survey some of the principle philosophical approaches in addressing a number of bioethical controversies and bring appropriate perspectives from ethical theories to bear on case studies in Bioethics. Topics include: 1) Philosophical ethics and its relation to Bioethics. 2) Classical approaches. Ethics and metaphysics. Ontological approaches to ethics. 3) Modern classical approaches to ethics. Theories of Scottish Enlightenment. Moral sentiments and the ethics of work: David Hume and Adam Smith. 4) Immanuel Kant: The ethics of form. 5) Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill. Utilitarianism. 6) Contemporary moral theories: - Contractarian and constructivist theories. John Rawls, Jurgen Habermas, Onora O’ Neill Postgraduate Prospectus 17 - Virtue ethics, ethics of care, feminism, communitarianism 7) Theories of a deflatory kind and moral scepticism.
    [Show full text]
  • Moral Fallibility and Moral Smugness
    This is a repository copy of Gibbardian Humility: Moral Fallibility and Moral Smugness. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/93155/ Version: Accepted Version Article: Lenman, J.W. (2014) Gibbardian Humility: Moral Fallibility and Moral Smugness. Journal of Value Inquiry, 48 (2). 235 - 245. ISSN 0022-5363 https://doi.org/10.1007/s10790-014-9420-6 Reuse Unless indicated otherwise, fulltext items are protected by copyright with all rights reserved. The copyright exception in section 29 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988 allows the making of a single copy solely for the purpose of non-commercial research or private study within the limits of fair dealing. The publisher or other rights-holder may allow further reproduction and re-use of this version - refer to the White Rose Research Online record for this item. Where records identify the publisher as the copyright holder, users can verify any specific terms of use on the publisher’s website. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ 1 1 Gibbardian Humility: Moral Fallibility and Moral Smugness This is my version of a paper published in The Journal of Value Inquiry 48, 2014, pp. 235-245. DOI 10.1007/s10790-014-9420-6. Please refer to the latter when quoting or citing Abstract Andy Egan objects to quasi-realism that quasi-realists are committed to a form of smugness: when confronted with cases of fundamental disagreement, the quasi-realist must see him/herself as immune to moral error in a way that others are not.
    [Show full text]
  • Sense and Sensibility
    Nils Franzén Sense and Sensibility Four Essays on Evaluative Discourse Dissertation presented at Uppsala University to be publicly examined in Geijersalen, Thunbergsvägen 3H, Uppsala, Thursday, 20 September 2018 at 15:00 for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. The examination will be conducted in English. Faculty examiner: Professor Pekka Väyrynen (University of Leeds, Faculty of Arts, Humanities and Cultures ). Abstract Franzén, N. 2018. Sense and Sensibility. Four Essays on Evaluative Discourse. 37 pp. Uppsala: Department of Philosophy. ISBN 978-91-506-2717-6. The subject of this thesis is the nature of evaluative terms and concepts. It investigates various phenomena that distinguish evaluative discourse from other types of language use. Broadly, the thesis argues that these differences are best explained by the hypothesis that evaluative discourse serves to communicate that the speaker is in a particular emotional or affective state of mind. The first paper, “Aesthetic Evaluation and First-hand Experience”, examines the fact that it sounds strange to make evaluative aesthetic statements while at the same time denying that you have had first-hand experience with the object being discussed. It is proposed that a form of expressivism about aesthetic discourse best explains the data. The second paper, “Evaluative Discourse and Affective States of Mind”, discusses the problem of missing Moorean infelicity for expressivism. It is argued that evaluative discourse expresses states of mind attributed by sentences of the form “Nils finds it wrong to tell lies”. These states, the paper argues, are non-cognitive, and the observation therefore addresses the problem of missing infelicity. The third paper, “Sensibilism and Evaluative Supervenience”, argues that contemporary theories about why the moral supervenes on the non-moral have failed to account for the full extent of the phenomenon.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaethics and the Autonomy of Morality
    Philosophers’ volume8,no.6 july2008 Imprint 1. Introduction SincethepublicationofG.E.Moore’sPrincipia Ethicaithasbecome commonplace for philosophers to distinguish between questions in metaethics and those in normative ethics.1 A sympathetic character- Metaethics izationofthecenturyofself-consciouslymetaethicalresearchthatfol- lowedwouldemphasizetheextraordinarydevelopmentbothinour understandingofthecentralmetaethicalproblemsandinthesophis- ticationofthetheorieselaboratedtomeetthem.However,someare & notsosympathetic.Inthispaper,Iexamineonesourceofdistrustin metaethicalresearch:itsapparenttensionwiththenotionthatmoral- ityisautonomous. Tobegin,IbrieflysketchhowIamthinkingofmetaethics,ofthe the Autonomy of autonomyofmorality,andofthetensionthatcanappeartoexistbe- tweenthem.Onetraditionalconceptionofmetaethicstakesittocon- cern only the analysis of moral language.2 However, contemporary philosophers typically use the term more expansively.3 Here, I use Morality the term to pick out elements common to these contemporary dis- cussions.Thiscommoncoreencompassesmoralontologyandmoral psychologyaswellasmoralsemantics.Bycontrast,normativeethics (sometimesalsocalled‘substantiveethics’)concernsthestructureand contentofthecorrectmoralevaluationofagents,statesofaffairs,and actions.Normativeethicaltheoriestypicallyofferaccountsofmoral valueandmoralreasons,ofvirtuouscharactertraits,ofrightness,and Tristram McPherson oftherelationshipsbetweenthese. 1. The word ‘metaethics’ came into regular philosophical usage much later. University of Minnesota Duluth
    [Show full text]
  • Gibbard, Allan
    ThinkingH ow to Live with Each Other ALLAN GibbARD The Tanner Lectures on Human Values Delivered at TheU niversity of California, Berkeley February 28–March 2, 2006 Allan Gibbard is Richard Brandt Distinguished University Professor of Philosophy at the University of Michigan. He graduated from Swarth- more College and received his Ph.D. from Harvard University. He taught at Achimota School in Ghana while in the Peace Corps, and at the Uni- versity of Chicago and the University of Pittsburgh. He has also been a visiting professor at Stanford University. He is a member of the American Philosophical Society and a fellow of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences. He has served as president of the Central Division of the Ameri- can Philosophical Society. His many publications include Manipulation of Voting Schemes: A General Result (1973); Wise Choices, Apt Feelings: A Theory of Normative Judgment (1990); Moral Discourse and Practice (co- editor with Stephen Darwall and Peter Railton, 1997); and ThinkingH ow to Live (2003). I. INSight, CONSISTENCY, AND PLANS FOR LiviNG Jonathan Haidt, the social psychologist, entitles a fascinating article “The Emotional Dog and Its Rational Tail.” His topic is moral judgment, and the emotional dog is what he calls “intuition.” Mostly, he argues, we don’t arrive at our moral conclusions by reasoning. We jump to them with emo- tional judgments, with “affectively valenced intuitions,” as he puts it. We will often be firmly convinced that our moral judgments rest on sound reasoning, and that unless others are driven by bias, they will appreciate the force of our arguments.
    [Show full text]
  • Truth and Metaethics
    TRUTH AND METAETHICS THE POSSIBILITY OF METAETHICS RUSS SHAFER-LANDAU∗ INTRODUCTION ............................................................................................... 479 I. SECOND-ORDER QUESTIONS ............................................................... 480 II. EXTERNAL SKEPTICISM AND HUME’S PRINCIPLE ................................ 483 III. EXTERNAL SKEPTICISM: ERROR THEORETIC ARGUMENTS ................. 487 A. Morons ......................................................................................... 487 B. Characterizing Error Skepticism ................................................. 488 C. The Missing Arguments ............................................................... 491 IV. EXTERNAL STATUS SKEPTICISM .......................................................... 493 CONCLUSION ................................................................................................... 495 INTRODUCTION I found the first few chapters of Ronald Dworkin’s Justice for Hedgehogs1 very disconcerting. True, the manuscript is written in Dworkin’s lovely style. It is wide-ranging and provocative throughout. The book pulls no punches and advances a challenging thesis. It is very ambitious and full of interesting observations and arguments. There is much for everyone to admire, and something for everyone to question. In my case, two distinct sources of worry kept pressing. My initial unease grew steadily to something approaching panic as I assimilated the underlying message of these chapters – metaethics is largely a sham;
    [Show full text]
  • Allan Gibbard Reviews ‘On What Matters’ by Derek Parfit · LRB 7 June 2012 9/27/12 1:15 PM
    Allan Gibbard reviews ‘On What Matters’ by Derek Parfit · LRB 7 June 2012 9/27/12 1:15 PM This site uses cookies. By continuing to browse this site you are agreeing to our use of × cookies. (More Information) Back to article page Five Girls on a Rock Allan Gibbard On What Matters by Derek Parfit Oxford, 540 pp. and 825 pp, £30.00, May 2011, ISBN 978 0 19 926592 3 Morality can’t just be a system of arbitrary taboos. We want its protections, and others want those same protections against us. A morality worth heeding must have a rationale. A chief task of moral philosophers is to discern such a rationale and to shape it by criticism and argument. Derek Parfit’s On What Matters looks to two great moral philosophers, Immanuel Kant in the late 18th century and Henry Sidgwick, whose treatise The Methods of Ethics first appeared in 1874. Kant, Parfit writes, ‘is the greatest moral philosopher since the ancient Greeks’, but Sidgwick’s Methods ‘is, I believe, the best book on ethics ever written’. Kant and Sidgwick are normally taken to stand for the two great opposing moral visions: Sidgwick for utilitarianism, which concerns itself with how to maximise happiness, and Kant for a moral law grounded in reason. Parfit finds, however, that Kant and Sidgwick are ‘climbing the same mountain’ by different routes. We are still far from the summit by either route, but as Parfit said a quarter-century ago, ‘compared with the other sciences, non-religious ethics is the youngest and the least advanced.’ As with any science, a mature ethics might take generations to formulate.
    [Show full text]
  • Disparate Goods and Rawls' Difference Principle: a Social Choice Theoretic Treatment
    ALLAN GIBBARD DISPARATE GOODS AND RAWLS' DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE: A SOCIAL CHOICE THEORETIC TREATMENT ABSTRACT. Rawls' Difference Principle asserts that a basic economic structure is just if it makes the worst off people as well off as is feasible. How well off someone is is to be measured by an 'index' of 'primary social goods'. It is this index that gives content to the principle, and Rawls gives no adequate directions for constructing it. In this essay a version of the difference principle is proposed that fits much of what Rawls says, but that makes use of no index. Instead of invoking an index of primary social goods, the principle formulated here invokes a partial ordering of prospects for opportunities. i. PRIMARY SOCIAL GOODS AND THE INDEXING PROBLEM In A Theory of Justice, Rawls claims as one of the virtues of his theory that it does not require interpersonal comparisons of utility. Instead, the interpersonal comparisons needed for the theory are based on an 'index of primary social goods'. Primary goods are goods useful toward widely disparate ends, "things which it is supposed a rational man wants what- ever else he wants" (p. 92). 1 The primary social goods include rights and liberties, powers and opportunities, income and wealth (pp. 62, 92). In Rawls' theory, then, the basis of interpersonal comparisons is overt: the compari- sons are to be made on the basis of who gets how much of what. Why might this be an advantage? To anyone who denies that interpersonal comparisons of utility are meaningful, the advantage will seem obvious: by not invoking such comparisons, the theory avoids a pseudo-concept.
    [Show full text]
  • A Guilt Trip: Expressivism, Moral Judgment, and Basic Emotions*
    A Guilt Trip: Expressivism, Moral Judgment, and Basic Emotions* Jay Odenbaugh Associate Professor Lewis & Clark College [email protected] December 14, 2014 1 Introduction In this essay, I first sketch Allan Gibbard's (1992) norm expressivism. Sec- ond, I consider Shaun Nichols' (2004) critique of Gibbard's account of moral judgment. In essence, Nichols argues that since norm expressivism assumes moral judgment requires the experience and attribution of guilt and that chil- dren younger than 7 - 8 cannot experience and attribute guilt, then they can- not make moral judgments. However, he contends that they can given that they can pass the moral/conventional task. Thus, Gibbard's norm expressivist account of moral judgment is fatally flawed. Third, I provide a response on behalf of Gibbard. Fourth, I conclude with an account of guilt as an emotion. *Thanks to participants at the PSA session specifically Edouard Machery, Grant Ram- sey, and Caitlin O'Connor. Additionally, I thank colleagues John Fritzman, Joel Martinez, William Rottschaefer, and Nicholas D. Smith at Lewis & Clark College for their feedback. Finally, I would to thank Harris Rosenbaum, Gabe Ruimy, and Cory Wilson for their work with me on a Mellon Faculty-Student Research Grant. 1 2 Norm Expressivism Allan Gibbard writes, Narrowly moral judgments are not feelings but judgments of what moral feelings it is rational to have. Feelings, we think, can be apt or not, and moral judgments of when guilt or resentment are apt. (1992, 6) A simple minded emotivism might hold the following: One judges an action morally wrong if, and only if, one would feel guilty for doing it.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Gibbard on Meaning and Normativity
    Gibbard on Meaning and Normativity (to appear in book symposium in Inquiry) Timothy Williamson It is a long time since equating a sentence’s meaning with its verification condition looked like a promising idea. But have we been too hasty? Let’s not use the ominous phrase ‘verification condition’. We can take the more fashionable normative turn, and speak instead of the condition under which a speaker ought to accept the sentence. If we want to be even more sophisticated, and a little bit formal, we can grade acceptance, and speak of the condition under which one ought to give the sentence a given degree of credence. We can gloss ‘condition’ here as ‘evidential condition’. We can also emphasize how one’s credence in a complex sentence ought to be related to one’s credence in other sentences, especially those with which it shares constituents. As verificationism is revamped along such lines, it sounds increasingly like the position at which Allan Gibbard arrives in Meaning and Normativity. Here is a sample passage: The meanings of the words in a sentence combine to explain which inferential oughts apply to the sentence and the evidential conditions under which one ought to accept or reject the sentence. A word’s meaning what it does consists in the pattern of oughts that enters into such explanations. (p. 114)1 1 Of course, Gibbard’s intention is not to perform the Vienna Circle in modern dress. His thoughtful, ingenious, impressively crafted, and subtly reflexive monograph goes far to work out an intriguing line of thought in response to Saul Kripke’s suggestive remarks about the normativity of meaning in his book on Wittgenstein’s rule-following considerations.
    [Show full text]
  • Evolving Moral Knowledge
    EVOLVING MORAL KNOWLEDGE by ALLAN GIBBARD The Lindley Lecture The University of ~ansas March 12, 2009 The E. H. Lindley Memorial Lectureship Fund was established in 1941 in memory of Ernest H. Lindley, Chancellor of the University of Kansas from 1920 to 1939. In February 1941 Mr. Roy Roberts, the chairman of the committee in charge, suggested in the Graduate Magtrine t.hat the Chancellor should invite to the University for a lecture or a series of lectures, some outstanding national or world figure to speak on "Values ofLiving'' - just as the late Chancellor proposed to do in his courses "The Human Situation" and "Plan for Living." Ln the following June Mr. Roberts circulated a letter on behalf of the Committee, proposing in somewhat broader terms that The income from this fund should be spent in a quest of social betterment by bringing to the University each year outstanding world leaders for a lecture or series of Iecru res, yet with a design so broad in its outline that in the years to come, if it is deemed wise, this living memorial could take some more desirable form . The fund was allowed to accumulate until 1954, when Professor Richard McKeon lectured on "Human Rights and International Relations." The next lect.ure was given in 1959 by Professor Everett C. Hughes, and has been published by the University of Kansas School of Law as part of bis book Students· Culture and Perspectives: Lectures on Medical and General Education. Tile selection of lectures for the Lindley series has since been delegated to the Department of Philosophy.
    [Show full text]