Oxford Handbook of Developmental Behavioral Neuroscience

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Oxford Handbook of Developmental Behavioral Neuroscience OXFORD LIBRARY OF NEUROSCIENCE Editor-in-Chief GORDON M. SHEPHERD Oxford Handbook of Developmental Behavioral Neuroscience Edited by Mark S. Blumberg John H. Freeman Scott R. Robinson 3 2010 Introduction: A New Frontier for Developmental Behavioral Neuroscience Mark S. Blumberg, John H. Freeman, and Scott R. Robinson As editors of this volume, we wrestled with alter- (2) to highlight current opportunities to advance native titles to capture what we felt was a theo- our understanding of behavioral and neural devel- retically connected but highly interdisciplinary opment through enhanced interactions between fi eld of science. Previous edited volumes that have DP and its sister disciplines. addressed related content areas were published In 1975, in his infl uential book Sociobiology: over a 15-year span beginning in the mid-1980s T e New Synthesis, E. O. Wilson famously looked under the label of “developmental psychobiology” forward to the year 2000 when, he predicted, (e.g., Blass, 1986, 1988, 2001; Krasnegor, Blass, the various subdisciplines of behavioral biology Hofer, & Smotherman, 1987; Shair, Hofer, & Barr, could be represented by a fi gure in the shape of a 1991). Although all three of the editors of the pre- barbell—the narrow shaft representing the dwin- sent volume have longstanding ties to the fi eld of dling domain of the whole organism (i.e., ethology developmental psychobiology (DP) and its parent and comparative psychology) and the two bulging society (the International Society for Developmental orbs at each end comprising the burgeoning fi elds Psychobiology), we also view our work as part of a of sociobiology and neurophysiology. Wilson’s pre- larger community of researchers in behavioral neu- diction that the study of the whole organism would roscience, comparative psychology, developmental be “cannibalized” by population and reductionistic science, and evolutionary biology. T is volume is approaches seemed, to many behavioral research- aimed at this larger research community concerned ers over the last quarter century, to be relentlessly with empirical and theoretical issues about behav- fulfi lled. But ultimately, the “death of the organ- ioral and neural development. ism” has proven greatly exaggerated. On the con- DP has traditionally concerned itself with inves- trary, we are witnessing a resurgence of interest in a tigations of the biological bases of behavior and how diversity of mechanisms—especially developmen- they change during development. T e rich tradition tal mechanisms—that contribute to the form and of DP is seen in the many advances it has provided function of the organism. Most importantly (for to our understanding of behavior and behavioral this volume), the behavior of whole organisms has development. Moreover, DP has been distinguished emerged as a central product and causal infl uence by its adherence to an epigenetic perspective, that of developmental change. is, a perspective that embraces all contributions to Wilson’s view of the future from his 1975 individual development, from the molecular to the perch refl ected two biological themes–cell theory social. DP remains a productive and innovative dis- and evolutionary theory–that were central to the cipline, but it now faces new challenges posed by rise of modern biology in the nineteenth century rapid advances and the advent of powerful technol- and which were greatly refi ned and expanded in ogies in molecular biology, neuroscience, and evo- their infl uence in the twentieth century. By the lutionary biology. T ese challenges, however, are mid-twentieth century, these two perspectives cul- also opportunities. T us, our goal for this volume minated in the rise of the Modern Synthesis, the is twofold: (1) to communicate the central research discovery of DNA, and the success of the molecu- perspectives of DP to a wider community inter- lar revolution. T e new emphasis on parts and pop- ested in behavioral and neural development and ulations anchored Wilson’s barbell and relegated the organism to a transient vessel, a mere convey- (1967) at least called attention to the value of devel- ance for selfi sh genes (Dawkins, 1977). On the one opmental analyses of behavior and expanded the hand, the Modern Synthesis succeeded in reconcil- traditional dichotomy of causes into four “causes ing Darwinian evolution with population genetics and origins” of behavior: (1) causation or control (Provine, 1971); on the other, the successes of molec- (immediate physiological mechanisms), (2) devel- ular biology convinced many that whole organisms opment (history of change in the individual), could be reduced to individual traits and crucial (3) adaptive signifi cance (mechanisms acting on biochemicals produced through the actions of sin- past populations, such as natural selection), and gle genes (Keller, 2000; Moore, 2001). Although (4) evolution (history of change in the population). many prominent scientists tried very hard to off er But whether viewed as two, four, or even more clas- plausible alternatives and amendments to these two ses of cause, such classifi cation schemes have reifi ed dominant perspectives (Alberch, 1982; Gottlieb, the notion that biological causes can be treated as 1992; Gould & Lewontin, 1979; Lehrman, 1953; distinct and independent entities. Stent, 1977), they were unable to stem the tide. Tinbergen’s four-question scheme has been Proximate causes are the immediate conditions widely adopted in textbooks and behavioral train- that give rise to behavior. Such causes include ing programs and has contributed a great deal to the activity in particular neural circuits, the actions of clearer formulation of research questions in ethol- neuro transmitters at specifi c receptors, the modulat- ogy and comparative psychology (Dewsbury, 1994; ing infl uence of hormone molecules, and the trans- Hailman, 1982; Hogan, 1994; Sherman, 1988). duction of sensory stimuli into neural responses. But it also has obscured deep underlying connec- In contrast, ultimate causes refer to the function or tions between these areas of inquiry. For instance, purpose of behavior, which in evolutionary terms we are coming to appreciate that—in contrast to is the result of natural selection acting on popula- the comparative anatomy of behavior espoused tions. Although the distinction between proximate by Lorenz (1937, 1981)—behavior is not an entity and ultimate causation is evident in the early writ- such as a bone or internal organ that has a continu- ings of both biologists (Baker, 1938; Huxley, 1916; ous existence. Rather, each behavioral performance Lack, 1954) and comparative psychologists (Craig, is unique and ephemeral, although it may be recog- 1918; Dewsbury, 1999), this dichotomy of causes nizably similar to other performances by the same was promoted most eff ectively by Ernst Mayr individual in the past or other individuals of the (Beatty, 1994; Mayr, 1961), a central fi gure in the same species. Behavior is elaborated in time despite rise of the Modern Synthesis. Interestingly, Mayr the common research practice of treating individ- used proximate and ultimate causation as indepen- ual behavioral acts as instantaneous for purposes dent explanations to defend evolutionary interpre- of analysis. From these perspectives, the causation tations from criticisms coming from mechanistic of behavior, which encompasses the “proximate” physiologists and molecular biologists (Amundson, physiological mechanisms that generate behavior, 2005; Dewsbury, 1999; Mayr, 1974). In eff ect, also should be seen as a question of historical ori- Mayr appealed to the explanatory categories of gins, albeit on a much briefer time scale and there- proximate and ultimate causation to delineate the fore within the same continuum of phenomena as fi elds of molecular–cellular and population biol- development. ogy, thereby creating the very barbell that Wilson T eorists since Darwin also have recognized par- conveniently “predicted” in 1975. allels in patterns of change on developmental and Of course, what was missing from both the evolutionary time scales. Early attempts to explain Modern Synthesis and the reductionism of molec- the phylogenetic information evident in embryolog- ular biology was an adequate appreciation for the ical development were founded on notions such as role of development as a mediating cause of organic Haeckel’s biogenetic law, which stated that embryos change. As long as genes were viewed as root causes pass through the same sequence of stages during of individual characteristics (necessary for a mod- development as the adult forms of ancestral species ern synthetic interpretation of evolution), and gene during evolution (Haeckel, 1866). Although strong frequencies in populations were viewed as suffi cient forms of recapitulation have long since been discred- metrics of evolution, it was possible to skip over the ited (Gould, 1977), developmental issues have risen messy details of how a fertilized egg is transformed in prominence again over the last several decades into an organism that can, in turn, be a target of within both the evolutionary (Kirschner & Gerhart, natural selection. Tinbergen (1963) and Hailman 2005; West-Eberhard, 2003) and molecular (Carroll, INTRODUCTION: A NEW FRONTIER FOR DEVELOPMENTAL BEHAVIORAL NEUROSCIENCE 2005) domains. Moreover, the success of unsuper- 2005, 2009; Gottlieb, 1997; Oyama, Griffi ths, & vised processes such as natural selection in explain- Gray, 2001; West, King, & Arberg, 1988). Although ing evolutionary change has led to similar
Recommended publications
  • Neural Darwinism Inspired Implementation of an Artificial
    P. Chanthini and K. Shyamala International Journal of Control Theory and Applications ISSN : 0974–5572 © International Science Press Volume 10 • Number 23 • 2017 Neural Darwinism Inspired Implementation of an Artifi cial Neural Network Model P. Chanthinia and K. Shyamalab aResearch Scholar, PG and Research Department of Computer Science, Dr. Ambedkar Government Arts College (Autonomus), Affi liated to University of Madras, Chennai, India. E-mail: [email protected] bAssociate Professor, PG and Research Department of Computer Science, Dr. Ambedkar Government Arts College (Autonomus), Affi liated to University of Madras, Chennai,India E-mail: [email protected] Abstract : Vast scope in exploration of the biological neural system and brain functions continually open rooms for improvement in Artifi cial Neural Network (ANN) studies. This work is an effect of an effort in adopting the biological theory “Neural Darwinism: Selection” by GM. Edelman into Artifi cial Neural Network Model (ANNM). The newly implemented ANNM has provided scopes in designing new ANNMs using different biological theories in addition to the traditional way. This work illustrates an ANNM having two distinct portions, one physically static and other functionally dynamic. Rather than using the conventional method of training for weight adjustment, this model uses static weight representation and dynamic selection of artifi cial neural representations according to different problems, mimicking a biological neural selection theory- experiential selection. The result of this work depicts the successful implementation of an ANNM through newly adopted theory, solving multiple unipolar problems like XOR and N-Parity problems where the conventional method will require two or more separate feed-forward networks trained for each problem.
    [Show full text]
  • Affective and Immune System Influences
    Neural Development: Affective and Immune System Influences George F R Ellis 1 and Judith A Toronchuk 2 Abstract: This paper proposes that the developmental processes of Edelman's Neural Darwinism fit together in a very coherent way with the present increasing understanding of the importance of the affective dimension in neuroscience. A synthesis of these two features, with the evolutionarily determined primary affective systems together with the immune system providing the value system required by Neural Darwinism, provides an integrative viewpoint relating psychological issues at the macro level to neurobiological processes structuring neuronal connections at the micro level. We look at the various implications of such an integrative viewpoint relating genetically determined affective systems to higher cortical functions, considering successively developmental and functional issues, primary and secondary emotions, psychological issues, evolutionary issues, language, genetic issues, neurological issues, and potential outcomes of the proposal. We suggest that the “wet-wiring” nature of neurotransmitter mediated synaptic connections may be related to this integration. We then consider the implications of molecularly based links between the brain and the immune system, showing this too might play a significant role in the processes of neural Darwinism. Indeed this could possibly relate to the evolutionary origin of affective systems . 1: Introduction Two recent contributions have advanced understanding of brain function: Gerald Edelman’s “Neural Darwinism” (Edelman, 1989, 1992; Edelman and Tononi, 2001), dealing with how brain development and function can be well understood in terms of a process of natural selection applied to neural connections, and Jaak Panksepp’s formulation of “Affective Neuroscience” (Panksepp, 1998, 2001), addressing how neurobiological systems mediate the basic emotions 3.
    [Show full text]
  • Roger Sperry “Split-Brain” Experiment on Cats
    Thinking about Thought • Introduction • The Brain • Philosophy of Mind • Dreams and • Cognitive Models Emotions • Machine Intelligence • Language • Life and • Modern Physics Organization • Consciousness • Ecology 1 Session Six: The Brain for Piero Scaruffi's class "Thinking about Thought" at UC Berkeley (2014) Roughly These Chapters of My Book “Nature of Consciousness”: 7. Inside the Brain 2 Prelude to the Brain • A word of caution: everything we think about the brain comes from our brain. • When I say something about the brain, it is my brain talking about itself. 3 Prelude to the Brain • What is the brain good at? • Recognizing! 4 Prelude to the Brain • What is the brain good at? Who is younger? 5 Behaviorism vs Cognitivism 6 Behaviorism • William James – The brain is built to ensure survival in the world – Cognitive faculties cannot be abstracted from the environment that they deal with – The brain is organized as an associative network – Associations are governed by a rule of reinforcement 7 Behaviorism • Behaviorism – Ivan Pavlov • Learning through conditioning: if an unconditioned stimulus (e.g., a bowl of meat) that normally causes an unconditioned response (e.g., the dog salivates) is repeatedly associated with a conditioned stimulus (e.g., a bell), the conditioned stimulus (the bell) will eventually cause the unconditioned response (the dog salivates) without any need for the unconditioned stimulus (the bowl of meat) • All forms of learning can be reduced to conditioning phenomena 8 Behaviorism • Behaviorism – Burrhus Skinner (1938) • A person does what she does because she has been "conditioned" to do that, not because her mind decided so.
    [Show full text]
  • Affective Neuronal Darwinism: the Nature of the Primary Emotional
    Running Head: NATURE OF THE PRIMARY EMOTIONAL SYSTEMS Affective Neuronal Darwinism: The Nature of the Primary Emotional Systems Judith A. Toronchuk Psychology and Biology Departments, Trinity Western University and George F. R. Ellis Mathematics Department, University of Cape Town Contact information: Psychology Department, Trinity Western University 7600 Glover Road, Langley, B.C. V2Y 1Y1 Canada. Phone: 604-888-7511 extension 3104 email address: [email protected] Nature of the Primary Emotional Systems Abstract Based on studies in affective neuroscience and evolutionary psychiatry, a tentative new proposal is made here as to the nature and identification of primary emotions. Our model stresses phylogenetic origins of emotional systems, which we believe is necessary for a full understanding of the functions of emotions and additionally suggests that emotional organising systems play a role in sculpting the brain during ontogeny. Emotions thus affect cognitive development. A second proposal concerns two additions to the affective systems identified by Panksepp. We suggest there is substantial evidence for a primary emotional organising programme dealing with power, rank, dominance and subordination which instantiates competitive and territorial behaviour and becomes the evolutionary source of self-esteem in humans. A programme underlying disgust reactions which originally functioned in ancient vertebrates to protect against infection and toxins is also suggested. ___________________________________________________________ Introduction Cognitive development of individuals, we have suggested, proceeds in part due to influences of primary emotional operating systems which act collectively as fitness criteria guiding further neuronal development (Ellis & Toronchuk, 2005). In short, Panksepp’s (1998, 2001) formulation of affective neuroscience can be seen as a compliment to neural Darwinism as proposed by Edelman (1989, 1992).
    [Show full text]
  • An Essay Review of Gerald Edelman's Neural Darwinism
    Psychobiology 1989, Vol. 17 (3),326-333 BOOK REVIEW Brains, computation, and selection: An essay review of Gerald Edelman's Neural Darwinism PAUL PATrON Uniuersity of Texas at Austin, Austin, Texas and THOMAS PARISI Saint Mary's College, Notre Dame, Indiana Neural Darwinism: The theory of neuronal tunately, however, the book suffers on both substantive group selection and stylistic grounds, ultimately failing to convince the By Gerald M. Edelman. 1987, New York: Basic Books. reader that a theory of brain function has been either de­ 371 pp. $29.95. veloped or presented. In what folIows, we offer a sum­ mary and a critical discussion of Edelman 's ideas as Neuroscientists will have a difficult time ignoring the presented in Neural Darwinism. publication of Neural Darwinism, Gerald Edelman's ex­ The central aim of Edelman 's book is to gain an under­ position of his theory of neuronal group selection. Lav­ standing ofthe neural bases ofperceptual categorization. ish brochures were sent to members of such groups as The ideas that Edelman puts forth on this topic are clearly the Society for Neuroscience and the American Associa­ rooted in his earlier work in immunology, for wh ich he tion for the Advancement of Science, and prominent ad­ won the Nobel Prize in 1972. Edelman's immunological vertisements heralded the publication in periodicals such work elucidated the structure of antibody molecules, and as the New York Review 0/ Books. In dust-jacket blurbs, in doing so helped to resolve a long-standing puzzle about Maxwell Cowan described the book as "perhaps the most the way the immune system recognizes specific antigens original work on the nervous system in thirty years," and (for an account ofthis work see Rosenfield, 1988).
    [Show full text]
  • The Neuronal Mechanism of the Faith Robert Skopec
    Review Article iMedPub Journals Translational Biomedicine 2016 http://www.imedpub.com/ Vol.7 No.3:86 ISSN 2172-0479 DOI: 10.21767/2172-0479.100086 The Neuronal Mechanism of the Faith Robert Skopec Dubnik, Slovakia Corresponding author: Robert Skopec, Research Analyst, AXON, Dubnik, Slovakia, Tel: +421908220692; E-mail: [email protected] Received: Aug 01, 2016; Accepted: Sep 02, 2016; Published: Sep 05, 2016 Citation: Skopec R. The Neuronal Mechanism of the Faith. Transl Biomed. 2016, 7:2. then the left hemisphere, the seat of language, is called upon to make sense of this subjective entity, the mind generates a Abstract feeling of “sensed presence”. A different subjects label this ghostly perception with the names that their cultures have Top-down processes overrode brain circuits devoted trained them to use: Elijah, Jesus, the Virgin Mary, reading and detection conflict (the Stroop effect). Most of Muhammad, etc. It may seem sacrilegious to reduce God the time bottom-up information matches top-down experience to a few synapses activity, but modern expectations. If we imagine something different, so it is neuroscience isn’t shy about defining our most sacred notions: different. A number of recent brain imaging studies point love, joy, altruism, etc. Persinger’s work practically constitutes to top-down brain mechanism under the influence of a base for the grand unified theory of the otherworldly [3]. He suggestion. By Kosslyn, brain scans show that the control believes cerebral fritzing is responsible for many mystical mechanisms for detecting what to do in the face of feelings, including faith in divine, and in the almighty too [4].
    [Show full text]
  • Bibliography-Gerald M. Edelman [Current]
    Bibliography Gerald M. Edelman Books 1. Edelman, G.M. and Mountcastle, V.B. (1978) The Mindful Brain: Cortical Organization and the Group Selective Theory of Higher Brain Function. MIT Press, Cambridge. 2. Edelman, G.M. (1987) Neural Darwinism: The Theory of Neuronal Group Selection. Basic Books, New York. 3. Edelman, G.M. (1988) Topobiology: An Introduction to Molecular Embryology. Basic Books, New York. 4. Edelman, G.M. (1989) The Remembered Present: A Biological Theory of Consciousness. Basic Books, New York. 5. Edelman, G.M. (1992) Bright Air, Brilliant Fire: On the Matter of the Mind. Basic Books, New York. 6. Edelman, G.M. and Tononi, G. (2000) A Universe of Consciousness: How Matter Becomes Imagination. Basic Books, New York. 7. Edelman, G.M. (2004) Wider Than The Sky: The Phenomenal Gift of Consciousness. Yale University Press, New Haven, Connecticuit. Books Edited 1. Edelman, G.M., ed. (1974) Cellular Selection and Regulation in the Immune Response. Raven Press, New York. 2. Edelman, G.M., Gall, W.E., Cowan W.M., eds. (1984) Dynamic Aspects of Neo- Cortical Function. Wiley, New York. 3. Edelman, G.M., Gall, W.E., Cowan, W.M., eds. (1985) Molecular Bases of Neural Development. Wiley, New York. 4. Edelman, G.M., Thiery, J.-P., eds. (1985) The Cell in Contact: Adhesions and Junctions as Morphogenetic Determinants. Wiley, New York. 5. Edelman, G.M., ed. (1985) Molecular Determinants of Animal Form, UCLA Symposia on Molecular and Cellular Biology, New Series, Vol. 31 Alan R. Liss, New York. 6. Edelman, G.M., Gall, W.E., Cowan, W.M., eds.
    [Show full text]
  • Rose's Homeodynamic Perspective Is Not an Alternative to Neo-Darwinism
    Andrew J. Wells Rose's homeodynamic perspective is not an alternative to Neo-Darwinism Article (Published version) (Refereed) Original citation: Wells, Andrew J. (1999) Rose's homeodynamic perspective is not an alternative to Neo- Darwinism. Behavioral and brain sciences, 22 (5). pp. 911-912. ISSN 0140-525X DOI:10.1017/S0140525X9951220X © 1999 Cambridge University Press This version available at: http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/12103/ Available in LSE Research Online: August 2012 LSE has developed LSE Research Online so that users may access research output of the School. Copyright © and Moral Rights for the papers on this site are retained by the individual authors and/or other copyright owners. Users may download and/or print one copy of any article(s) in LSE Research Online to facilitate their private study or for non-commercial research. You may not engage in further distribution of the material or use it for any profit-making activities or any commercial gain. You may freely distribute the URL (http://eprints.lse.ac.uk) of the LSE Research Online website. BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1999) 22, 871–921 Printed in the United States of America Précis of Lifelines: Biology, freedom, determinism1 Steven Rose Biology Department, Brain and Behaviour Research Group, Open University, Milton Keynes, MK7 6AA, United Kingdom. [email protected] Abstract: There are many ways of describing and explaining the properties of living systems; causal, functional, and reductive accounts are necessary but no one account has primacy. The history of biology as a discipline has given excessive authority to reductionism, which collapses higher level accounts, such as social or behavioural ones, into molecular ones.
    [Show full text]
  • Darwin's Neuroscientist: Gerald M. Edelman, 1929-2014
    Darwin's neuroscientist: Gerald M. Edelman, 1929-2014 Article (Published Version) Seth, Anil K (2014) Darwin’s neuroscientist: Gerald M. Edelman, 1929-2014. Frontiers in Psychology, 5. p. 896. ISSN 1664-1078 This version is available from Sussex Research Online: http://sro.sussex.ac.uk/id/eprint/56167/ This document is made available in accordance with publisher policies and may differ from the published version or from the version of record. If you wish to cite this item you are advised to consult the publisher’s version. Please see the URL above for details on accessing the published version. Copyright and reuse: Sussex Research Online is a digital repository of the research output of the University. Copyright and all moral rights to the version of the paper presented here belong to the individual author(s) and/or other copyright owners. To the extent reasonable and practicable, the material made available in SRO has been checked for eligibility before being made available. Copies of full text items generally can be reproduced, displayed or performed and given to third parties in any format or medium for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-profit purposes without prior permission or charge, provided that the authors, title and full bibliographic details are credited, a hyperlink and/or URL is given for the original metadata page and the content is not changed in any way. http://sro.sussex.ac.uk OPINION ARTICLE published: 14 August 2014 doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00896 Darwin’s neuroscientist: Gerald M. Edelman, 1929–2014 Anil K. Seth* Department of Informatics, Sackler Centre for Consciousness Science, School of Informatics and Engineering, University of Sussex, Brighton, UK *Correspondence: [email protected] Edited and reviewed by: Axel Cleeremans, Université Libre de Bruxelles, Belgium Keywords: consciousness, neural Darwinism, gamma globulin, reentry, selection “The brain is wider than the sky.
    [Show full text]
  • Culture and the Evolution Learning of Social
    ELSEVIER Culture and the Evolution of Social Learning Mark V. Flinn Department of Anthropology, University of Missouri Applications of modern evolutionary theory to human culture have generated several different theoretical approaches that challenge traditional anthropological perspectives. “Cultural selection” and “mind parasite” theories model culture as an independent evo- lutionary system because transmission of cultural traits via social learning is distinct from transmission of genes vla DNA replication. “Dual-inheritance” and “co-evolution” theories model culture as an intermediary evolutionary process that involves informa- tion from two inheritance systems: genetics and social learning. “Evolutionary psychol- ogy” theories emphasize that the evolutionary history of natural selection on mental pro- cesses links culture and biological adaptation; hence, cultural information is viewed as part of the organic phenotype and not an independent evolutionary system. Cross-cul- tural universals and scenarios of the “environment of evolutionary adaptedness” are used to identify characteristics of the “evolved mind” (human nature). “Behavioral ecol- ogy” theories examine relations between behavior and environmental context. Behav- ioral/cultural variations are viewed as products of flexible decision-making processes (evolved mind) that may respond adaptively to micro-environmental differences. It is difficult to devise empirical tests that distinguish among these theories, because they share many basic premises and make similar predictions
    [Show full text]
  • Brain Functional Near Infrared Spectroscopy in Human Infants
    Department of Woman and Child Health Neonatal Research Unit Astrid Lindgren’s Children’s Hospital Karolinska Institute BRAIN FUNCTIONAL NEAR INFRARED SPECTROSCOPY IN HUMAN INFANTS CEREBRAL CORTICAL HAEMODYNAMICS COUPLED TO NEURONAL ACTIVATION IN RESPONSE TO SENSORY STIMULATION Marco Bartocci, MD Thesis for doctoral degree (Ph.D) 2006 Cover: “The Infrared Helix”. The image was captured by the NASA's Spitzer Space Telescope (telescope's infrared array camera), California Institute of Technology. All previously published papers were reproduced with permission from the publisher. Published and printed by Karolinska University Press Box 200, SE-171 77 Stockholm, Sweden © Marco Bartocci, 2006 ISBN 91-7357-034-6 The human newborn infant is able to perceive a myriad of different sensory stimuli. The “hard problem” is now to define how and to what extent newborn infants mature their ability to perceive and become aware of the surrounding world after birth. How much can be retained in their brain and influence future developmental junctures. This thesis is dedicated to Jan Winberg, Professor Emeritus of Paediatrics at the Karolinska Institute, whom I had the fortune and honour to work with at the beginning of my PhD studies. ABSTRACT The assessment of cortical activation in the neonatal brain is crucial in the study of brain development, as it provides precious information for how the newborn infant processes external or internal stimuli. Thus far functional studies of neonates aimed to assess cortical responses to certain external stimuli are very few, due to the lack of suitable techniques to monitor brain activity of the newborn. Near Infrared Spectroscopy (NIRS) has been found to be suitable for functional studies of the infant brain.
    [Show full text]
  • Animal Consciousness
    The Distribution and Evolution of Animal Consciousness By Joseph Vitti Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Bachelor of Arts with Honors in Philosophy Harvard University March 26, 2010 1 © Joseph Vitti 2010 Contents Chapter One Preliminaries of Animal Consciousness . 3 Chapter Two Towards a Function of Consciousness: Evolutionary Considerations and Global Workspace Theory . 13 Chapter Three From the Theoretical to the Empirical: The Broadcast Hypothesis, Modularity, and Associative Learning . 27 Chapter Four Evidence of Associative Capacities and Consciousness Across the Animal Kingdom . 35 Chapter Five Animal Consciousness and Ethics . 50 References . 59 2 © Joseph Vitti 2010 CHAPTER 1 Preliminaries of Animal Consciousness Which nonhuman animals (hereafter: animals) are conscious? Many people distinguish first between primary consciousness – which includes awareness of percepts, sensations, immediate thoughts and so on – and higher-order consciousness – which refers to awareness of one's primary awareness, or “thought about thought” (Edelman, 2003). A number of experimental paradigms have been devised in recent years to identify higher-order consciousness in animals (particularly primates, cetaceans, and birds), but the study of primary consciousness is somewhat more elusive. In what follows, I will use the term 'consciousness' to refer to primary consciousness. What does it mean to be a conscious animal? One oft-cited definition is the one Nagel invoked when he asked what it is like to be a bat (1974). An organism or a mental process can be said to be conscious if there is something that it is like to be that organism or to be undergoing that process; essential to consciousness is its phenomenal, experiential, or qualitative feel.
    [Show full text]