Of Plato's Republic? David Lachterman 173

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Of Plato's Republic? David Lachterman 173 The St. John's Review Volume XXXIX, numbers one and two (1989-90) Editor Elliott Zuckerman Editorial Board Eva Brann Beale Ruhm von Oppen Cary Stickney John Van Doren Robert B. Williamson Subscriptions Assistant Deirdre Routt The St. John,s Review is published three times a year by the Office of the Dean, St. John's College, Annapolis; William Dyal, President; Thomas Slakey, Dean. For those not on the distribution list, subscriptions are $12.00 per year. Unsolicited essays, stories, poems, and reasoned letters are welcome. Address correspondence to the Review, St. John's College, Annapolis, MD 21404. Back issues are available, at $4.00 per issue, from the St. John's College Bookstore. © 1990 St. John's College. All rights reserved; reproduction in whole or in part without permission is prohibited. ISSN 0277-4720 Composition Fishergate, Inc. Printing The St. John's College Print Shop v ...... Preface David Lachterman I . The Music of the Republic Eva T. H Brann 105 . Eidos and Agathon in Plato's Republic Robert B. Williamson 139 . What is "The Good" of Plato's Republic? David Lachterman 173 . Imitation John White 201 . A Note About the Authors Preface Although the four essays iu this volume were conceived and generated on separate occasions, they form, I think, a true collection, and not only by virtue of their common theme, Plato's Republic. First, all four authors are "historically" indebted to the speeches (spoken or wntten) and to the silences of Jacob Klein. The first two writers were his colleagues, while the third and the fourth were students at St.John's College during four of the more than forty years Jacob Klein taught there. The ec·;ays gathered together in this book, however, are not static testimonies to his ·'influence," but are intended as lively episodes in the continuing, even L nremitting, course of serious reading and education he practiced, often •n the most playful manner. (The colloquial expression "former teachcc·" is here, if anywhere, an oxymoron.) T\.,: Platonic dialogues were his exemplars of that uncanny kinship bet­ ween nlay and seriousness to which Plato, or a soul-mate, refers in the Sixth Letter (kai tei tes spoudes adelphei paidiai-323d). Imitating, or comment­ ing OL. these exemplars, he brought to the awareness of the authors of these .essays the status of the dialogues as "ethological mimes." Interroga­ tion o ,· the souls and opinions of the interlocutors, with, on a very few occas: ms, a display of the abrupt "turnabout" (periagoge) in which, ac­ cording to Socrates (Rep. VII, 518d), the beginnings of education consist, takes orecedence over any of the putative theses, theories, or systems to which Platonic thinking was reduced or calcified, as early as Aristotle's On the Ideas (Peri !dean) and as recently as Hegel and Heidegger. Noteworthy is the way the comic poets of Plato's age (e.g., Theopom­ pus, Amphis, Aristophon) and their Athenian audiences seem to have been quite amused by such reductions or by their ascription, in all seriousness, to Plato; compare, too, the newly discovered papyrus-fragment in which v vi PREFACE the dramatic, or miming genre of the dialogues is discussed ( =P. Oxy, 3219). An exotic modern variant, or obversion, of the same thoughts may be found in Nietzsche's Twilight of the Idols (par. 5): "Socrates was the buffoon who got himself taken seriously: What really happened there?" Klein's own account of these "ethological mimes"· is familiar from the Introductory Remarks to his book A Commentary on Plato's Meno (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1965); his renditions ofthe various modes of Socratic interrogation and its dramatization by Plato are available in his lectures on the Phaedo, the Ion, and the Philebus (Essays and Lec­ tures, ed. E. Zuckerman and R. Williamson [Annapolis: The St. John's College Press, 1985]), as well as in his last book Plato's 'Ii'ilogy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1977). Accordingly a very few comments should be sufficient here. (For further reflections on some differences bet­ ween Klein's approach to Plato and now traditional or institutional fashions, see the review of Plato's Trilogy in Nous 13 [1979], pp. 106-12.) Emphasis on the dialogues as "ethological mimes," on their dramatic, sly, convoluted ironies, is not at odds with the presence in those same dialogues of Platonic "teachings," those teachings with which Klein was equally preoccupied, especially in his first. book Greek Mathematical Thought and the Origin of Algebra (trans. E. Brann [Cambridge, Mass.: M.I.T. Press, 1968]; German original, 1934-1936). The link between that emphasis and this preoccupation may be stated in the following, unavoidably truncated, way: that to take the due measure of Socratic in­ terrogations one must reflect deeply on the sources of their governing begin, nings or archai. Reflection of this sort leads, in turn, to consideration of the most plausible source of those sources (esp. Aristotle, Metaph. A6, 988a7-14). Mathematics, especially arithmetic, carries a heavy weight in the bulk of ancient testimonia concerning the outcome of Plato's reflections on the governing beginnings and their own sources. Three speculations-not necessarily shared in full by Klein or by all four authors in this volume­ suggest themselves: (!) If mathematics does play this conspicuous role in Platonic reflec­ tion, this is due not to its being a precise technique of problem-solving or a formal deductive system, but to the way its elements and their con­ nections come home to us as truly ta mathemata, the items we can suc­ ceed in understanding by questioning and learning. · (2) When it is a question of the very first among these first beginnings or archai, understanding and discursive articulation (dianoia) part com­ pany. Reports of Plato's "mathematical" speculations on The One, The Unlimited Dyad, etc., refer to his "unwritten opinions" (agrapha dogmata); LACHTERMAN vii rivers of ink have subsequently flowed over these reports. Secretiveness or esotericism, however, seems less the point than the acknowledgment that what makes learning always possible is not open to discursive articulation (either in speech or in writing). Paradoxically, perhaps, the underpinnings of intelligibility are not themselves intelligible, at least not in any accus­ tomed fashion. When Plato, in the Seventh Letter, speaks of "the weakness of the logos" (to asthenes tou logou), this is not an index of human finitude or of the critical limits of reason, but an indication that logos, a collected tally of the beings that belong together in discourse and learning, cannot offer a similar reckoning of its own ultimate archai. These make their ap­ pearance, if at all, in the interstices of discourse, and with the suddenness characteristic of recognition as well as of eros (cf. Symp. 2!0e). (3) Because speculation on the "mathematical" constitution of the governing beginnings remains tied to concern for the human enterprise of learning (and of failing to learn), Plato's putative "unwritten opinions" cannot be divorced from his crafting of psychic characters in words, his ethopoiia, as the Ancients called it. Ethopoiia, mathematics, and what was later named "ontology" meet at the point of optimum responsiveness to the testing demands of Socratic questioning. Souls are all together better off by virtue of this responsiveness. Hence one version of the probably legendary inscription over the entrance to the Academy explains "'Let no one who is not a geometer enter here.' That is, let no one who is unjust come in here, for geometry is equality and the just" (Cf. Johannes Tzetzes, Chiliades, VIII, 974-77 [ed. Kiessling]). The three points just made can also be put somewhat differently. Ac­ cording to an anonymous follower of the neoplatonic school (ca. 6th C. E.), each Platonic dialogue "is a cosmos," composed of elements at first hearing motley (poikilos), but finally arrayed decorously with one another (Anonymous Prolegomena to Platonic Philosophy 16.1-40 [ed. Westerink]). In the light provided by Klein's own readings we might be tempted to discern three dimensions of a dialogue such as The Republic, three measures of responsiveness through which that written artifact is given amplitude and audibility: (a) The seeming impromptus of Socrates, the two strangers, and the other interlocutors, given voice by Plato's ethopoietic art (the dialogue as eiki5n); (b) Plato's formal orchestration of these voices, always modulated to suit the disparate perspectives of his listeners and readers (the dialogue as phantasma); (c) The dialogue of the soul with, and within, itself (Soph. 263e), provoked by Plato's two-fold art (the dialogue as psychagi5gia or maieusis). viii PREFACE The Platonic dialogue as a "cosmos" takes its proportions from the interplay of these three dimensions. In sometimes very different ways the authors of the following essays try to do justice to that interplay and thus to both versions of Jacob J(lein's teaching. Eva Brann's "The Music of Plato's Republic" first appeared as a special supplement to The Collegian (March 1966) before being published in the inaugural issue of AGON. Journal of Classical Studies (April, 1967). In it the animated structure of so-called "ring-composition" in early Greek poetry, or in the design of "geometric" vases, is displayed as the shaping force of The Republic as well. By exposing the plot of the dialogue she renews the truth of Aristotle's claim in the Poetics: "The governing princi­ ple and, so to say, the soul of the tragic play is the tale it tells (muthos)" (1450a39). So, among many other things, she shows how the dyad of des­ cent and ascent, far from being merely part of the spectacle (apsis) of the dialogue, is consubstantial with its primary philosophical themes.
Recommended publications
  • The Collected Works of Eric Voegelin, Volume 16: Order and History, Volume III, Plato and Aristotle
    The Collected Works of Eric Voegelin, Volume 16: Order and History, Volume III, Plato and Aristotle Dante Germino, Editor University of Missouri Press the collected works of ERIC VOEGELIN VOLUME 16 ORDER AND HISTORY VOLUME III PLATO AND ARISTOTLE projected volumes in the collected works 1. On the Form of the American Mind 2. Race and State 3. The History of the Race Idea: From Ray to Carus 4. The Authoritarian State: An Essay on the Problem of the Austrian State 5. Modernity without Restraint: The Political Religions; The New Science of Poli- tics; and Science, Politics, and Gnosticism 6. Anamnesis 7. Published Essays, 1922– 8. Published Essays 9. Published Essays 10. Published Essays 11. Published Essays, 1953–1965 12. Published Essays, 1966–1985 13. Selected Book Reviews 14. Order and History, Volume I, Israel and Revelation 15. Order and History, Volume II, The World of the Polis 16. Order and History, Volume III, Plato and Aristotle 17. Order and History, Volume IV, The Ecumenic Age 18. Order and History, Volume V, In Search of Order 19. History of Political Ideas, Volume I, Hellenism, Rome, and Early Christianity 20. History of Political Ideas, Volume II, The Middle Ages to Aquinas 21. History of Political Ideas, Volume III, The Later Middle Ages 22. History of Political Ideas, Volume IV, Renaissance and Reformation 23. History of Political Ideas, Volume V, Religion and the Rise of Modernity 24. History of Political Ideas, Volume VI, Revolution and the New Science 25. History of Political Ideas, Volume VII, The New Order and Last Orientation 26.
    [Show full text]
  • Editorial. Transitory Parerga : Access and Inclusion in Contemporary
    Editorial. Transitory Parerga: Access and Inclusion in Contemporary Art Vlad Strukov University of Leeds, United Kingdom This item has been published in Issue 01 ‘Transitory Parerga: Access and Inclusion in Contemporary Art,’ edited by Vlad Strukov. To cite this item: Strukov V (2020) Editorial. Transitory parerga: Access and inclusion in contemporary art. The Garage Journal: Studies in Art, Museums & Culture, 01: v-xvii. DOI: 10.35074/GJ.2020.1.1.001 To link to this item: DOI: https://doi.org/10.35074/GJ.2020.1.1.001 Published: 30 November 2020 ISSN-2633-4534 thegaragejournal.org 18+ Full terms and conditions of access and use can be found at: https://thegaragejournal.org/en/about/faq#content Editorial Editorial. Transitory Parerga: Access and Inclusion in Contemporary Art Vlad Strukov Introduction The issue of access and inclusion is both topical and integral to Garage Museum of Contemporary Art, one of the backers of The Garage Journal: Studies in Art, Museums & Culture (hereafter, The Garage Journal). Institutions (museums, art colleges), ideologies (value systems, the canon), architecture (buildings, urban planning), curatorial paraphernalia (interpretation, frames, plinths) frame contemporary art. They include and exclude, give and withhold access by centralizing contemporary art in Eurocentric urban areas, by creating precarious employment opportunities, and by catering, mostly, to non-diverse audiences. By looking at these structures that frame contemporary art—point to its significance, signal its value, and movein and out of the transitory focus of art itself—we have a framework that allows us to discuss art and its boundaries, without limiting our investigation of access and inclusion to art’s ‘intrinsic’ qualities.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant's Doctrine of Religion As Political Philosophy
    Kant's Doctrine of Religion as Political Philosophy Author: Phillip David Wodzinski Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/987 This work is posted on eScholarship@BC, Boston College University Libraries. Boston College Electronic Thesis or Dissertation, 2009 Copyright is held by the author, with all rights reserved, unless otherwise noted. Boston College The Graduate School of Arts and Sciences Department of Political Science KANT’S DOCTRINE OF RELIGION AS POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY a dissertation by PHILLIP WODZINSKI submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy May 2009 © copyright by PHILLIP DAVID WODZINSKI 2009 ABSTRACT Kant’s Doctrine of Religion as Political Philosophy Phillip Wodzinski Advisor: Susan Shell, Ph.D. Through a close reading of Immanuel Kant’s late book, Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason, the dissertation clarifies the political element in Kant’s doctrine of religion and so contributes to a wider conception of his political philosophy. Kant’s political philosophy of religion, in addition to extending and further animating his moral doctrine, interprets religion in such a way as to give the Christian faith a moral grounding that will make possible, and even be an agent of, the improvement of social and political life. The dissertation emphasizes the wholeness and structure of Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason as a book, for the teaching of the book is not exhausted by the articulation of its doctrine but also includes both the fact and the manner of its expression: the reader learns most fully from Kant by giving attention to the structure and tone of the book as well as to its stated content and argumentation.
    [Show full text]
  • All of a Sudden: the Role of Ἐξαίφνης in Plato's Dialogues
    Duquesne University Duquesne Scholarship Collection Electronic Theses and Dissertations Spring 1-1-2014 All of a Sudden: The Role of Ἐξαιφ́ νης in Plato's Dialogues Joseph J. Cimakasky Follow this and additional works at: https://dsc.duq.edu/etd Recommended Citation Cimakasky, J. (2014). All of a Sudden: The Role of Ἐξαιφ́ νης in Plato's Dialogues (Doctoral dissertation, Duquesne University). Retrieved from https://dsc.duq.edu/etd/68 This Worldwide Access is brought to you for free and open access by Duquesne Scholarship Collection. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Duquesne Scholarship Collection. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ALL OF A SUDDEN: THE ROLE OF ἘΧΑΙΦΝΗΣ IN PLATO’S DIALOGUES A Dissertation Submitted to the McAnulty College and Graduate School of Liberal Arts Duquesne University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy By Joseph Cimakasky May 2014 Copyright by Joseph Cimakasky 2014 ALL OF A SUDDEN: THE ROLE OF ἘΧΑΙΦΝΗΣ IN PLATO’S DIALOGUES By Joseph Cimakasky Approved April 9, 2014 ________________________________ ________________________________ Ronald Polansky Patrick Lee Miller Professor of Philosophy Professor of Philosophy (Committee Chair) (Committee Member) ________________________________ John W. McGinley Professor of Philosophy (Committee Member) ________________________________ ________________________________ James Swindal Ronald Polansky Dean, McAnulty College Chair, Philosophy Department Professor of Philosophy Professor of Philosophy iii ABSTRACT ALL OF A SUDDEN: THE ROLE OF ἘΧΑΙΦΝΗΣ IN PLATO’S DIALOGUES By Joseph Cimakasky May 2014 Dissertation supervised by Professor Ronald Polansky There are thirty-six appearances of the Greek word ἐξαίφνης in Plato’s dialogues.
    [Show full text]
  • Moneymakers and Craftsmen: a Platonic Approach to Privatization
    DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12133 Moneymakers and Craftsmen: A Platonic Approach to Privatization Jonny Thakkar Abstract: Debates over the privatization of formerly public industries and services are common in contemporary politics. The overall goal of this paper is to suggest a normative framework within which deliberations over public ownership might take place. I draw this framework from Plato’s Republic, which I claim justifies pub- lic ownership as a means for ensuring that citizens labour as craftsmen rather than moneymakers; according to Plato’s social ontology, only craftsmen can constitute a genuine society and hence enjoy access to the full array of goods for the sake of which society comes into existence. This justificatory structure implies that public ownership is only a means for ensuring the appropriate teleology of labour; if there turn out to be better means, so be it. But what does turn out to be indispensable on this view, as G. A. Cohen understood, is an ethos of justice, especially among those in charge of regulating social institutions. 1. Introduction The last 30 years or so have seen a trend towards the privatization of formerly pub- lic industries and services in developed and developing countries alike. From banks, car manufacturers and electricity companies to ports, roads and railways, prisons, hospitals and security services, the overall pattern is clear. Each case is of course different in its particulars; the arguments around a given case may be more practical than philosophical; and it may be that the quality of arguments
    [Show full text]
  • The Rationality of Plato's Theory of Good and Evil
    Wilfrid Laurier University Scholars Commons @ Laurier Theses and Dissertations (Comprehensive) 1979 The Rationality of Plato’s Theory of Good and Evil Allan A. Davis Wilfrid Laurier University Follow this and additional works at: https://scholars.wlu.ca/etd Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Davis, Allan A., "The Rationality of Plato’s Theory of Good and Evil" (1979). Theses and Dissertations (Comprehensive). 1508. https://scholars.wlu.ca/etd/1508 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by Scholars Commons @ Laurier. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses and Dissertations (Comprehensive) by an authorized administrator of Scholars Commons @ Laurier. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ABSTRACT Plato has been called the "father of rational theology." This thesis is an attempt to examine in the light of contemporary Platonic scholarship five of Plato's essentially religious doctrines insofar as they support the idea that Plato's theory of good and evil is rational. Chapters 1 and 2 examine the plausibility of Plato's theory of knowledge. Chapter 3 states briefly his theory of Forms, while Chapter 4 attempts to give this doctrine credence by analysing those aspects of it which seem least convincing. Chapters 5 and 6 consider Plato's theory of soul and conclude that, although some of his beliefs in this area lack credibility, his interpretation of the nature and function of soul is basically plausible. Chapters 7 and 8 examine the rationality of Plato's Idea of the Good. Chapter 9 sketches his notion of balance and proportion and, in conclusion, Chapter 10 attempts to show how this theory provides an underlying credibility not only to all the theories discussed but also to Plato's theory of good and evil in its entirety.
    [Show full text]
  • Hero As Citizen Models of Heroic Thought and Action in Homer, Plato and Rousseau
    Man as Hero - Hero as Citizen Models of Heroic Thought and Action in Homer, Plato and Rousseau Dominic Stefanson Thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Discipline of Politics School of History and Politics The University of Adelaide December 2004 Frontisp iece Illustration included in print copy of thesis: Jacques-Louis David, The Death of Socrates (1787) iii Contents Abstract………………………………………………………………………… v Declaration…………………………………………………………………….. vi Acknowledgements……………………………………………………………. vii Introduction…………………………………………………………………… 1 PART I HOMER: THE BIRTH OF HEROISM 1. Homeric Man: The Hero …………………………………………………… 21 • Homeric heroes as models for men 22 • Seeking immortal glory achieving a “god-like status” 26 • Who is the hero? Preconditions for heroism 35 • A guide to heroism: transparency of thought, speech and action 44 • The transparency of Homeric narration 48 • Conclusion 55 2. Homeric Polis: the absence of a polis……………………………………… 57 • Finley and Adkins 58 • Seeking a polis in the Iliad 66 • The heroic code as an anti-model 77 • Patroclus’ funeral games as a microcosm of the polis 87 • Conclusion 93 PART II PLATO: EXTENDING HEROISM TO THE POLITICAL 3. Platonic Man: The philosopher as a new hero…………………………… 95 • Socrates: an heroic life 97 • Socratic Intellectualism: the primacy of knowledge 101 • Androgynous virtue 106 • Seeking eternity: philosophy as an activity for gods 111 • Tripartite psychology: heroism within human reach 117 • Theory of Forms 119 • The late dialogues 125 • Conclusion 130 iv 4. Platonic Polis: The political engagement of the heroic philosopher…….. 133 • Enlisting Philosophers to rule 135 • The elitist nature of philosophical rule throughout the Platonic corpus 137 • Philosophical leadership in the late dialogues 143 • The benefits of philosophical rule: harmony and unity in the Republic 150 • Does the community benefit from philosophical leadership? 154 • Conclusion 162 PART III ROUSSEAU: THE DEMISE OF HEROISM IN POLITICAL THOUGHT 5.
    [Show full text]
  • About: Plato an Entity of Type : Person, from Named Graph : Within Data Space : Dbpedia.Org
    About: Plato An Entity of Type : person, from Named Graph : http://dbpedia.org, within Data Space : dbpedia.org Plato (/ˈpleɪtoʊ/; Greek: Πλάτων, Plátōn, "broad"; 428/427 or 424/423 – 348/347 BCE) was a philosopher, as well as mathematician, in Classical Greece. He is considered an essential figure in the development of philosophy, especially the Western tradition, and he founded the Academy in Athens, the first institution of higher learning in the Western world. Along with Socrates and his most famous student, Aristotle, Plato laid the foundations of Western philosophy and science. Property Value dbo:abstract Plato (/ˈpleɪtoʊ/; Greek: Πλάτων, Plátōn, "broad"; 428/427 or 424/423 – 348/347 BCE) was a philosopher, as well as mathematician, in Classical Greece. He is considered an essential figure in the development of philosophy, especially the Western tradition, and he founded the Academy in Athens, the first institution of higher learning in the Western world. Along with Socrates and his most famous student, Aristotle, Plato laid the foundations of Western philosophy and science. Alfred North Whitehead once noted: "the safest general characterization of the European philosophical tradition is that it consists of a series of footnotes to Plato."Plato's dialogues have been used to teach a range of subjects, including philosophy, logic, ethics, rhetoric, religion and mathematics. His lasting themes include Platonic love, the theory of forms, the five regimes, innate knowledge, among others. His theory of forms launched a unique perspective on abstract objects, and led to a school of thought called Platonism. Plato's writings have been published in several fashions; this has led to several conventions regarding the naming and referencing of Plato's texts.
    [Show full text]
  • The Divine As Mirror of the Human Soul
    The Divine as Mirror of the Human Soul Human being soar higher and higher, for awesome strengths are yours, you own wings of spirit, wings of noble eagles. Don’t deny your abilities, for if you do they will deny you- Seek your strengths, and you will find them immediately. Rabbi A.Y. Kook, Orot Hakodesh 1:64 Man is the mirror which God holds up to himself, or the sense organ with which he apprehends his being. Carl Jung At their source, sound and sight are united. Only in our limited, physical world, in this alma depiruda (disjointed world), are these phenomena disconnected and detached. It is similar to our perception of lightning and thunder, which become increasingly separated from one another as the observer is more distanced from the source. If we are bound and limited to the present, if we can only perceive the universe through the viewpoint of the temporal and the material, then we will always be aware of the divide between sight and sound. The prophetic vision at Mount Sinai, however, granted the people a unique perspective, as if they were standing near the source of Creation. From that vantage point, they were able to witness the underlying unity of the universe. They were able to see sounds and hear sights. God’s revelation at Sinai was registered by all their senses simultaneously, as a single, undivided perception. Rav Kook Dear Pastor Amstutz, 28 March 1953 …My criticism of the Yahwistic God-image is for you what the experience of the book was for me: a drama that was not mine to control.
    [Show full text]
  • For the Sentiment Emotions As Practice in the Development of Eighteenth- Century British Abolitionism
    For The Sentiment Emotions as Practice in the Development of Eighteenth- Century British Abolitionism Stefania Chiro School of Humanities Department of English and Creative Writing The University of Adelaide October 2017 Acknowledgments So many thanks need to go to my supervisor, Dr Heather Kerr, for her unfailing guidance throughout the researching, planning, and writing process, for calmly reassuring me during my moments of self-doubt, and for continuing to do so despite the tyranny of distance. Thanks also to my co-supervisor, Professor Amanda Nettelbeck, whose encouraging feedback was very much appreciated. I also need to thank the British Library and the Liverpool Record Office for giving me access to their incredible archives. It was a true privilege to be able to get my hands on such important and fragile documents. To my friends and family, thanks for not giving up on me over the past few years. Thanks to my father for being a sounding board for my ideas and, of course, to Jordan for keeping me grounded and allowing me to do what I have to do without question or complaint. Finally, to my mum, thank you for your unconditional love and support. You pulled me through this more than anyone with your encouragement and your unwavering belief in me. 3 Abstract At the end of the eighteenth century the British movement for the abolition of the slave trade emerged, arguing for reform based on notions of humanity and the fellow-feeling of mutual sympathy. With slavery still one of the biggest and most profitable crimes in the world today, how public sentiment was mobilised to create the first humanitarian movement to attempt to put an end to the slave trade remains a pertinent question.
    [Show full text]
  • James' Pure Experience and the Creative Potential of the Metaxy
    “James’ Pure Experience and the Creative Potential of the Metaxy” by Macon Boczek, Ph.D. Department of Philosophy, Kent State University, Kent, Ohio The elucidation of the creative potential William James’ of ‘pure experience’1 as an instance of that of the metaxy will be undertaken in this paper form the perspective of Eric Voegelin’s explanation of “equivalency of experience and symbolization in history”.2 Hence a preliminary definition of the basic notions of pure experience and the metaxy will begin this essay----with the comprehensive explanations of them to follow in the body of the text. Also, the definition of Voegelin’s “equivalence of experience” will be provided in these introductory remarks because this idea is the methodological one for my study. Finally, it should also be noted that the topic of my research is concentrated on the higher order, open-ended intelligent and conscious capabilities of human beings that excited the attention of both Plato and William James. Hence the emphasis will be on the discovery of the talent of intuitive intelligence with a minimum investigation of discursive abilities of human reason.3 1William James, “Does Consciousness Exist?” in William James: A Comprehensive Edition, edited , with an Introduction and New Preface by John J. McDermott, (Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press, 1977), pp. 163-183. This essay, reprinted from Essays in Radical Empiricism, pp. 1-38, contains a comprehensive articulation and rationale for James’ notion of ‘pure experience’. 2Eric Voegelin, “”Equivalences of Experience and Symbolizations in History” in Eric Voegelin, Published Essays, C.W. 12, edited with an Introduction by Ellis Sandoz, (Baton Rouge and London: Louisiana State University Press, 1990), pp.
    [Show full text]
  • The Relationship Between Poverty and Eros in Plato's Symposium Lorelle D
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Dissertations (2009 -) Dissertations, Theses, and Professional Projects Love's Lack: The Relationship between Poverty and Eros in Plato's Symposium Lorelle D. Lamascus Marquette University Recommended Citation Lamascus, Lorelle D., "Love's Lack: The Relationship between Poverty and Eros in Plato's Symposium" (2010). Dissertations (2009 -). Paper 71. http://epublications.marquette.edu/dissertations_mu/71 LOVE’S LACK: THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN POVERTY AND EROS IN PLATO’S SYMPOSIUM By Lorelle D. Lamascus A Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School, Marquette University, In partial fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy Milwaukee, Wisconsin December 2010 ABSTRACT LOVE’S LACK: THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN EROS AND POVERTY IN PLATO’S SYMPOSIUM Lorelle D. Lamascus Marquette University, 2010 This dissertation responds to a long-standing debate among scholars regarding the nature of Platonic Eros and its relation to lack. The more prominent account of Platonic Eros presents the lack of Eros as a deficiency or need experienced by the lover with respect to the object needed, lacked, or desired, so that the nature of Eros is construed as self-interested or acquisitive, subsisting only so long as the lover lacks the beloved object. This dissertation argues that such an interpretation neglects the different senses of lack present in the Symposium and presents an alternative interpretation of Eros based on the Symposium ’s presentation of Eros as the child of Poverty and Resource. Chapter one examines the origin and development of the position that Platonic Eros is acquisitive or egocentric and the influence this has had on subsequent interpretations of Plato’s thought.
    [Show full text]