The Desire for Happiness and the Virtues of the Will

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Desire for Happiness and the Virtues of the Will Journal of Moral Theology, Vol. 3, No. 1 (2014): 18-38 The Desire for Happiness and the Virtues of the Will Jean Porter EAR THE BEGINNING of the prima secundae of the Summa theologiae, Aquinas says that every rational agent neces- sarily desires and seeks his or her own happiness (ST I-II q. 5, a. 4, ad. 2; I-II q. 5, a. 8). This was a commonplace forN Aquinas and his interlocutors, and it might seem that he only af- firms it out of deference to a long-established tradition.1 But Aquinas is very well able to distance himself from traditional claims when his overall position requires him to do so, and that is not what we see him doing here. On the contrary, he takes this claim as the starting point for the extended analysis of human actions that comprises the secunda pars, in accordance with the program set out in the prologue to ST I-II q. 1, a. 6. What is more, he interprets it in terms of the met- aphysical analysis sketched in the prima pars, in such a way as to integrate the doctrine of God with the analysis of the actions through which the rational creature returns to God—thus following the pro- gram set out at the beginning of the Summa theologiae, in the intro- duction to ST I q. 1, a. 2. Finally, as we will see further on, Aquinas maintains this claim even though it generates internal difficulties for his overall analysis. Briefly, he says at different points that the agent necessarily aims at her own happiness in every act, and that the vir- tuous will, informed by justice or charity, is disposed in such a way as to aim at something beyond the agent’s own good as an individu- al. Aquinas is the most systematic of thinkers, and even a prima facie inconsistency of this sort indicates that he has something of some importance at stake in these claims. Until recently, it was hard to see what this might be. Aquinas’s remarks about happiness place him at odds with a widespread mod- ern view, associated with Kant as well as with some strands of Re- formed theology, according to which the desire for happiness is at best distinct from and secondary to moral commitment, or at worst, 1 For an excellent overview of the classical origins of this tradition, and specifically the link between happiness and virtue, see Julia Annas, The Morality of Happiness (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993), 27-47. The Desire for Happiness 19 sinful and reprehensible.2 In this context, it has proven hard for some interpreters even to acknowledge that Aquinas says what he plainly does say about the universal desire for happiness, much less to try to understand why he says it.3 However, recent developments in moral philosophy have opened up possibilities for a fresh appraisal of Aquinas’s remarks on happiness. Specifically, there is a growing sense among our contemporaries that we have exaggerated the dif- ference between Aristotelian and Kantian theories of morality.4 Whatever we may say about Aristotle and Kant themselves, their followers do at least share commitments to the rationality of morali- ty, the normative or constitutive function of practical reason, and the importance of the unity of agency as an ideal, or perhaps a precondi- tion, for moral judgment and choice. Precisely because they share these key commitments, Aristotelian and Kantian moral philosophers have disagreed, deeply and yet fruitfully, about what each means and how they should be fitted together. But these disagreements, while deep, are not radical—on the contrary, they share common roots in very long-standing traditions of normative reflection on reason, ac- tivity, and the overall shape of one’s life. The Aristotelian Aquinas, who also anticipates some key ele- ments of Kant’s moral thought, is plainly part of this extended tradi- tion. In common with contemporary Aristotelian and Kantian moral philosophers, he is committed to an account of moral judgment which displays its rationality, on the one hand, and its integral con- nection to rational agency and action on the other. Recent develop- ments in moral philosophy open a space within which to see the point and significance of these commitments, for Aquinas himself and for moral thought generally. Seen in this light, his more specific claims about the centrality and pervasiveness of the desire for happi- ness make sense, and indeed, emerge as necessary elements within his overall theory. At the same time, contemporary work on practical 2 For a comprehensive analysis of modern philosophical and theological perspec- tives on self-love and the desire for happiness, see Gene Outka, Agape: An Ethical Analysis (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1972), 55-74. 3 See, for example, John Finnis, Aquinas. Founders of Modern Political and Social Thought (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998), 103-110. On his view, the happi- ness that Aquinas identifies as the proper end of life would be equivalent to a condi- tion of secure, unrestricted participation in the basic goods, which constitute the genuine, and irreducibly plural aims of human action. It is difficult to see how this analysis can be squared with Aquinas’s insistence that happiness itself, considered both as a subjective state and in terms of its objective target, is the ultimate, unitary end of human life. 4 In addition to the authors discussed below, see the essays collected by Stephen Engstrom and Jennifer Whiting in Aristotle, Kant, and the Stoics: Rethinking Hap- piness and Duty (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996). Their introductory essay, “Introduction,” 1-18 offers a good overview of the issues at stake in this reap- praisal. 20 Jean Porter reason offers new perspectives on these claims, suggesting a way to resolve the internal tension mentioned above. This will call on an extended interpretation that goes beyond what Aquinas says, but not in such a way as to undermine or distort the overall contours of his account. In this paper, I will accordingly offer an analysis of Aquinas’s treatment of the universal desire for happiness, focusing on his re- marks in the Summa theologiae, within which the idea of happiness plays a central organizing role. My aims will be primarily interpreta- tive—I hope to illuminate what Aquinas himself says, and to draw out the immediate implications of his views. The scope of this paper will not allow for a more extended examination of Aquinas’s overall position and its significance for theological as well as philosophical debates. However, this paper is motivated by the conviction that Aquinas is, fundamentally, right on the key questions. His metaphys- ically informed analysis of the unity of agency leaves ample room for what our contemporaries call self-constitution and the determina- tion of one’s own aims, and in addition it offers what they cannot, namely, a well-grounded and systematic account of the givens, the starting points and parameters, without which practical reason could not function in a coherent way at all. What is more, he interprets the universal desire for happiness in such a way as to show that this de- sire is in no way contrary to Christian charity, which is oriented out- wards, towards God and neighbor. Again, a defense, or even a full explication of these larger claims would go well beyond the scope of this paper, but I do hope to at least lend them plausibility by what follows. In the first section of this paper, I will argue that Aquinas’s claim that the will is necessarily oriented towards the agent’s happiness follows from his overall account of the metaphysics of agency, not only human agency, but causal agency of any kind. He says that all men and women necessarily desire happiness, because otherwise, human beings would not be causal agents at all. At the same time, Aquinas interprets happiness in such a way as to identify connatural happiness with the practice of the virtues. This line of analysis im- plies that the universal desire for happiness is not inconsistent with virtuous dispositions, but it does not account for the distinctively other-regarding orientation that is characteristic of the virtues of the will. In the second section, I attempt to lay the groundwork for re- solving this problem through an analysis of the objective and subjec- tive components of inclination, choice, and motivation, taking ad- vantage of recent work on practical reason, virtue, and motivation in order to draw out what I take to be implicit in Aquinas’s own thought. In the third section, I will apply these distinctions to Aqui- nas’s account of virtues of the will, in order to show how the virtu- ous will can be said to incline towards the agent’s own perfection, The Desire for Happiness 21 understood in one sense, while genuinely desiring the good of the other for her own sake, in another sense. PERFECTION, HAPPINESS, AND VIRTUE: FRAMING THE ISSUES In the first question of the prima secundae, Aquinas unequivocal- ly says that every human being acts for some one end, towards which all his actions are directed (ST I-II q. 1, aa. 5, 6). Formally consid- ered, this end is the same for all—namely, the individual’s own per- fection, or equivalently, his beatitude, or happiness (ST I-II q. 1, aa. 6, 8). This presupposes that the individual is in fact capable of acting in a characteristically human way, that is to say, rationally, implying that he is capable of directing his own activities in accordance with a reasoned idea of goodness (ST I-II qq.
Recommended publications
  • The Influence of Emotional States on Short-Term Memory Retention by Using Electroencephalography (EEG) Measurements: a Case Study
    The Influence of Emotional States on Short-term Memory Retention by using Electroencephalography (EEG) Measurements: A Case Study Ioana A. Badara1, Shobhitha Sarab2, Abhilash Medisetty2, Allen P. Cook1, Joyce Cook1 and Buket D. Barkana2 1School of Education, University of Bridgeport, 221 University Ave., Bridgeport, Connecticut, 06604, U.S.A. 2Department of Electrical Engineering, University of Bridgeport, 221 University Ave., Bridgeport, Connecticut, 06604, U.S.A. Keywords: Memory, Learning, Emotions, EEG, ERP, Neuroscience, Education. Abstract: This study explored how emotions can impact short-term memory retention, and thus the process of learning, by analyzing five mental tasks. EEG measurements were used to explore the effects of three emotional states (e.g., neutral, positive, and negative states) on memory retention. The ANT Neuro system with 625Hz sampling frequency was used for EEG recordings. A public-domain library with emotion-annotated images was used to evoke the three emotional states in study participants. EEG recordings were performed while each participant was asked to memorize a list of words and numbers, followed by exposure to images from the library corresponding to each of the three emotional states, and recall of the words and numbers from the list. The ASA software and EEGLab were utilized for the analysis of the data in five EEG bands, which were Alpha, Beta, Delta, Gamma, and Theta. The frequency of recalled event-related words and numbers after emotion arousal were found to be significantly different when compared to those following exposure to neutral emotions. The highest average energy for all tasks was observed in the Delta activity. Alpha, Beta, and Gamma activities were found to be slightly higher during the recall after positive emotion arousal.
    [Show full text]
  • About Emotions There Are 8 Primary Emotions. You Are Born with These
    About Emotions There are 8 primary emotions. You are born with these emotions wired into your brain. That wiring causes your body to react in certain ways and for you to have certain urges when the emotion arises. Here is a list of primary emotions: Eight Primary Emotions Anger: fury, outrage, wrath, irritability, hostility, resentment and violence. Sadness: grief, sorrow, gloom, melancholy, despair, loneliness, and depression. Fear: anxiety, apprehension, nervousness, dread, fright, and panic. Joy: enjoyment, happiness, relief, bliss, delight, pride, thrill, and ecstasy. Interest: acceptance, friendliness, trust, kindness, affection, love, and devotion. Surprise: shock, astonishment, amazement, astound, and wonder. Disgust: contempt, disdain, scorn, aversion, distaste, and revulsion. Shame: guilt, embarrassment, chagrin, remorse, regret, and contrition. All other emotions are made up by combining these basic 8 emotions. Sometimes we have secondary emotions, an emotional reaction to an emotion. We learn these. Some examples of these are: o Feeling shame when you get angry. o Feeling angry when you have a shame response (e.g., hurt feelings). o Feeling fear when you get angry (maybe you’ve been punished for anger). There are many more. These are NOT wired into our bodies and brains, but are learned from our families, our culture, and others. When you have a secondary emotion, the key is to figure out what the primary emotion, the feeling at the root of your reaction is, so that you can take an action that is most helpful. .
    [Show full text]
  • Ethics – Handout 10 My Notes on Mill’S Utilitarianism
    24.231 Ethics – Handout 10 My Notes on Mill’s Utilitarianism (1) General concerns: • Are interpersonal comparisons of utility even possible? • What are we talking about – maximizing total utility or average utility? • Both seem to ignore issues of distributive justice (except instrumentally – diminishing marginal utility of resources) • Average utility has some implausible implications (especially when considering harms, rather than benefits – is it really not worse for a total population of 100 people to be suffering torture than for a total population of 10 people to be suffering it?), and seems not to sit comfortably with utilitarian intuitions. Total utility invites the repugnant conclusion (but it’s important to remember that this isn’t just a problem for utilitarianism). (2) On higher and lower pleasures: • Should a utilitarian make any distinction between these? Is “pushpin as good as poetry,” if the quatity of pleasure they produce is the same? • How are we to determine which of two pleasures is higher? Is Mill’s appeal to “competent judges who have experienced both pleasures” plausible? And if competent judges prefer the higher pleasures, should we think they do so because activities leading them are more pleasurable, or have a higher quality of pleasure? Isn’t it perhaps more plausible to think they value them more for some other reason, having nothing to do with pleasure? • Relatedly, even if competent judges do take more pleasure in engaging in “higher” activities, are these activities more valuable because they are more pleasurable
    [Show full text]
  • Zest and Work
    Journal of Organizational Behavior J. Organiz. Behav. 30, 161–172 (2009) Published online in Wiley InterScience (www.interscience.wiley.com) DOI: 10.1002/job.584 Zest and work CHRISTOPHER PETERSON1*, NANSOOK PARK2, NICHOLAS HALL3 AND MARTIN E.P.SELIGMAN 3 1University of Michigan, Michigan, U.S.A. 2University of Rhode Island, Rhode Island, U.S.A. 3University of Pennsylvania, Pennsylvania, U.S.A. Summary Zest is a positive trait reflecting a person’s approach to life with anticipation, energy, and excitement. In the present study, 9803 currently employed adult respondents to an Internet site completed measures of dispositional zest, orientation to work as a calling, and satisfaction with work and life in general. Across all occupations, zest predicted the stance that work was a calling (r ¼.39), as well as work satisfaction (r ¼.46) and general life satisfaction (r ¼.53). Zest deserves further attention from organizational scholars, especially how it can be encouraged in the workplace. Copyright # 2009 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. Your work is to discover your work, and then with all of your heart to give yourself to it.—the Buddha Introduction Recent years have seen a widespread call for the study of work organizations in which people can be well and do well (Cameron, Dutton, & Quinn, 2003; Gardner, Csikszentmihalyi, & Damon, 2001; Luthans, 2003; Wright, 2003). The emergence of the positive perspective within organizational psychology has brought new attention to the venerable topic of work satisfaction (Hoppock, 1935). Satisfaction with the work that one does is seen not just as a contributor to good performance and increased profitability but as a worthy end in its own right (Heslin, 2005).
    [Show full text]
  • A Faithful Love Yields Enduring Happiness July 2018
    A faithful love yields enduring happiness July 2018 Married love is also faithful and exclusive of all other, and this until death. This is how husband and wife understood it on the day on which, fully aware of what they were doing, they freely vowed themselves to one another in marriage. Though this fidelity of husband and wife sometimes presents difficulties, no one has the right to assert that it is impossible; it is, on the contrary, always honorable and meritorious. The example of countless married couples proves not only that fidelity is in accord with the nature of marriage, but also that it is the source of profound and enduring happiness. (Humanae vitae no. 9) Reflection There tends to be a common view in the culture that freedom means doing anything one wants, anytime, with no restraints. Such a view makes it difficult to understand the vowed commitment to lifelong, faithful marriage. Bl. Pope Paul VI in Humanae vitae reminds the world that the Church offers a different view of freedom, a view that authentic freedom can only be found when it is ordered towards the truth. When we live our lives according to the truth, as with the example of a husband and wife living a life of faithfulness and fidelity to each other in marriage, we experience the “profound and enduring happiness” and authentic freedom our hearts are truly longing for. How have you experienced the fruits of living faithful love in your life? Are there areas God may be inviting you to grow in trust and faithfulness in your relationship with Him? Intercessory Prayer to Paul VI God our Father, Empower married couples to live the beautiful call to free, total, faithful, fruitful love in the vow they exchanged in holy matrimony.
    [Show full text]
  • Positive Psychology
    7 WAYS TO APPLY POSITIVE PSYCHOLOGY Learn practical, proven strategies to live a happier, more engaged and more meaningful life. We all want to live happier, more engaging and more meaningful lives. The science of positive psychology contributes new Introduction insights and proven strategies to increase wellbeing in individuals, workplaces and communities. After years classifying and repairing the worst of human experience, positive psychology emerged to help us flourish and learn from the best. This rich and varied field now spans many areas, building on philosophies and practices from Aristotle to Maslow. This eBook introduces you to some of the most practical and research-backed ways to apply positive psychology to increase happiness, wellbeing and effectiveness—in your life, at work, at home and with the people you care for, help and lead. You will learn: • How to maximise the power of positivity to create sustainable pathways to happiness and success. • Seven positive psychology practices - “[Positive Psychology is] the from optimism to mindfullness. scientific study of positive • Tips to apply these practices at work, at human functioning and home and when helping people. flourishing on multiple levels.” We look forward to inspiring you and others to live a Martin Seligman &Mihaly Csikszentmihalyi happier, more engaged and fulfilling life! The Langley Group team © 2015 Langley Group. All rights reserved 2 Positive psychology 7 POSITIVE PRACTICES Positive emotion 1 Generating positive emotions helps broaden and build our resources and moves us toward greater wellbeing. Spearheaded by Martin Seligman and Mindset Mihaly Csikszentmihalyi in 1998, positive 2 psychology focuses on exploring and Adopting a positive attitude and Growth Mindset enhances learning and opens our expanding what makes life worthwhile, mind to new ways to raise happiness levels.
    [Show full text]
  • John F. Helliwell, Richard Layard and Jeffrey D. Sachs
    2018 John F. Helliwell, Richard Layard and Jeffrey D. Sachs Table of Contents World Happiness Report 2018 Editors: John F. Helliwell, Richard Layard, and Jeffrey D. Sachs Associate Editors: Jan-Emmanuel De Neve, Haifang Huang and Shun Wang 1 Happiness and Migration: An Overview . 3 John F. Helliwell, Richard Layard and Jeffrey D. Sachs 2 International Migration and World Happiness . 13 John F. Helliwell, Haifang Huang, Shun Wang and Hugh Shiplett 3 Do International Migrants Increase Their Happiness and That of Their Families by Migrating? . 45 Martijn Hendriks, Martijn J. Burger, Julie Ray and Neli Esipova 4 Rural-Urban Migration and Happiness in China . 67 John Knight and Ramani Gunatilaka 5 Happiness and International Migration in Latin America . 89 Carol Graham and Milena Nikolova 6 Happiness in Latin America Has Social Foundations . 115 Mariano Rojas 7 America’s Health Crisis and the Easterlin Paradox . 146 Jeffrey D. Sachs Annex: Migrant Acceptance Index: Do Migrants Have Better Lives in Countries That Accept Them? . 160 Neli Esipova, Julie Ray, John Fleming and Anita Pugliese The World Happiness Report was written by a group of independent experts acting in their personal capacities. Any views expressed in this report do not necessarily reflect the views of any organization, agency or programme of the United Nations. 2 Chapter 1 3 Happiness and Migration: An Overview John F. Helliwell, Vancouver School of Economics at the University of British Columbia, and Canadian Institute for Advanced Research Richard Layard, Wellbeing Programme, Centre for Economic Performance, at the London School of Economics and Political Science Jeffrey D. Sachs, Director, SDSN, and Director, Center for Sustainable Development, Columbia University The authors are grateful to the Ernesto Illy Foundation and the Canadian Institute for Advanced Research for research support, and to Gallup for data access and assistance.
    [Show full text]
  • Rational Desire and Rationality in Desire: an Unapologetic Defense Peter Railton Preliminary Draft of October 2008—Please Do Not Circulate Without Permission
    Rational Desire and Rationality in Desire: An Unapologetic Defense Peter Railton Preliminary draft of October 2008—please do not circulate without permission Introduction Consider Robert Stalnaker’s well-known, elegant formulation of the interlocking, functional nature of belief and desire: Belief and desire … are correlative dispositional states of a potentially rational agent. To desire that P is to be disposed to act in ways that would tend to bring it about that P in a world in which one’s beliefs, whatever they are, were true. To believe that P is to be disposed to act in ways that would tend to satisfy one’s desires, whatever they are, in a world in which P (together with one’s other beliefs) were true. [Stalnaker (1984), 15; emphasis added] This characterization gives a picture of a potentially rational agent as, so to speak, at the mercy of his beliefs and desires, whatever they are. Whether an individual agent is actually rational, one might naturally think, will depend on what fills in for ‘whatever they are’—for this will determine the shape of her life and, roughly, who, if anyone, is in charge. Put another way: Autonomy will depend heavily on how ‘whatever they are’ is filled in—what role does the agent herself play? And rationality will depend heavily on what is filled in—will the agent’s beliefs and desires be as they rationally should be?1 The thought is: If your beliefs and desires are as they rationally should be, and you as agent have played the right sort of role in acquiring them, then insofar as they are functioning normally—namely, as Stalnaker indicates—to guide how you act, then your actions, too, will be autonomous, and as they rationally should be.
    [Show full text]
  • Understanding and Watering the Seeds of Compassion
    Research in Human Development, 12: 280–287, 2015 Copyright © Taylor & Francis Group, LLC ISSN: 1542-7609 print / 1542-7617 online DOI: 10.1080/15427609.2015.1068060 Understanding and Watering the Seeds of Compassion Mark T. Greenberg and Christa Turksma Pennsylvania State University The authors call for a broad agenda to create comprehensive models and research on the devel- opment and promotion of empathy and compassion. This wish would lead to a new level of 5 developmental/ecological understanding of the growth of compassion as well as effective policies and practices and interventions that nurture caring, compassion, and service to others in our schools and communities. The authors define empathy and compassion, briefly discuss the outline of early developmental processes, and call for basic research on these essential aspects of human develop- ment. The authors conclude by discussing the need to develop new ways to promote empathy and 10 compassion in families, schools and communities. Our wish is for a life-span developmental psychology to make greater contributions to building a compassionate world society. This calls for a broad agenda to create comprehensive models and research on the development and promotion of emotional awareness, empathy, and com- passion. The practical outcome of such a comprehensive program would include (1) clearer 15 developmental/ecological models of the growth of compassion; (2) effective policies, programs, and practices that support the development of caring, compassion, and service to others in our schools and communities; and (3) children, youth, and adults who show greater service to others as well as caring about the preservation of the earth’s ecology.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is Compassion? How Can It Bring Happiness and Build Resilience? by Brandel France De Bravo
    What is compassion? How can it bring happiness and build resilience? By Brandel France de Bravo Compassion is one of those words that no one is entirely sure about. What is it, and how is it different from empathy, pity, or plain-old kindness? I wasn’t really able to answer those questions either until I took an eight-week meditation course developed at Stanford University called Compassion Cultivation Training (CCT™). Dr. Kelly McGonigal, who helped create the curriculum and trained me to become a CCT teacher, says that compassion “is actually a human strength that …evolved to help you meet stress in a way that is good for you and good for others.” As a certified CCT teacher, one of the exercises I like to begin with is this: think of a time when someone showed you compassion or you behaved compassionately towards someone. How did you know it was compassion and not some other emotion? And, how did it feel in your body? Can you recollect any physical sensations that arose during that experience? If asked to recall an experience of compassion, I think of the time I lost my child in a crowd. This has happened to many parents at some point. The difference was this was in Mexico, at night, in the state with the highest per capita rate of kidnapping. We were in a church yard watching hundreds participate in a beautiful silent, candle-lit procession when my six-year-old daughter’s hand slipped from her father’s. “Oh, yes, we saw a little girl being led away, crying that she didn’t want to leave,” one woman told my husband, our entire frantic search carried out in whispers.
    [Show full text]
  • Reaching the Minds and Hearts of Those We Serve
    Connection Through Self-Compassion and Compassion for Others: Reaching the Minds and Hearts of Those We Serve Roseann Cervelli, MS, LACDC, CCS, CPS [email protected] 732-937-5437 Ext.122 Compassion, COVID 19 And the Year 2020: A New Threshold for Humanity Objectives • To analyze and explore how Mindful Self-Compassion serves as an antidote to apathy and disconnection in today’s world. • To define Mindful Self-Compassion and Compassion for Others as an approach to well-being, physically, mentally, emotionally and spiritually. • To describe how Compassion Awareness can address meeting Basic Core Needs and healing Core Wounds • To explore the Neuroscience within Compassion Focused Therapy and Compassion Awareness. • To introduce and experience several Mindful Compassion Exercises and Practices What words come to mind when you hear or see the word "APATHY"? ⓘ Start presenting to display the poll results on this slide. What Is Apathy ? A feeling and/or attitude of indifference, unconcern, unresponsiveness, detachment, dispassion. An absence of interest or concern about emotional, social, spiritual, philosophical and/or physical life and the world. Why Apathy? To understand the part of us that Rarely is it good to run, but we are wants nothing to do with the full wiser, more present, more mature, necessities of work, of more understanding and more relationship, of loss, of seeing thoroughly human when we realize what is necessary, is to learn we can never flee from the need to humility, to cultivate self- run away. compassion and to sharpen that - David Whyte, Consolations: The Solace, Nourishment and sense of humor essential to a Underlying Meaning of Everyday Words (2106) merciful perspective of both a self and another.
    [Show full text]
  • The Perfect Storm: Gay Men, Crystal Meth and Sex Cultural Considerations for Gay Affirming Treatment
    The Perfect Storm: Gay Men, Crystal Meth and Sex Cultural Considerations for Gay Affirming Treatment Craig Sloane, LCSW, CASAC Private Practice New York City [email protected] 917-670-0483 How did Crystal Meth become so popular with Gay Men? In order to figure this out we need to understand: • Pharmacology of Crystal Meth • Cultural consideraons • Crystal meth, gay men and sex • Crystal meth and HIV • Gay Male Sex and Drug SuB-Cultures • Gay Men’s Vulnerabili:es to SuBstance ABuse and Why Crystal Meth is such a “Good Fit” How can addic9on professionals help? In order to figure this out we need to understand: • Gay Affirmave Treatment • How to Treat the Fusion of Crystal Meth Use and Sex • How to Overcome the Unique Challenges of Treang this PoPulaon Pharmacology of Methamphetamine Street Names for Methamphetamine • Chrissy • Ice • Crystal • Speed • Meth • Crank • Tina • Glass What is Crystal Meth? Crystal meth can Be found as a white, yellowish or reddish Powder, a waxy solid or a clear rock. A 1⁄4 gram dose costs about $20. As a s:mulant, crystal increases the release of doPamine and norePinePhrine, the Brain’s Pleasure and alert chemicals. This Produces euPhoria, increases energy, Prolongs sexual Performance, and suPPresses apPe:te. Crystal can also Produce feelings of Power, confidence, invulnerability, and intense sexual desire. The high can last 8 to 12 hours (dePending on tolerance) and is followed By a Period of exhaus:on, dePression, irritability, and (some:mes) Paranoia known as the “crash.” Crystal is extremely addic:ve. Many gay and Bi men overes:mate their ability to keeP recreaonal use from escalang into dependence History of Methamphetamines • 1887 synthesized By German Pharmacologist L.
    [Show full text]