Behavioral Experiments in 15 Small-Scale Societies Author(S)

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Behavioral Experiments in 15 Small-Scale Societies Author(S) In Search of Homo Economicus: Behavioral Experiments in 15 Small-Scale Societies Author(s): Joseph Henrich, Robert Boyd, Samuel Bowles, Colin Camerer, Ernst Fehr, Herbert Gintis, Richard McElreath Source: The American Economic Review, Vol. 91, No. 2, Papers and Proceedings of the Hundred Thirteenth Annual Meeting of the American Economic Association (May, 2001), pp. 73-78 Published by: American Economic Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2677736 Accessed: 28/08/2008 19:20 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=aea. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. http://www.jstor.org In Search of Homo Economicus: Behavioral Experiments in 15 Small-Scale Societies By JOSEPHHENRICH, ROBERT BOYD, SAMUELBOWLES, COLIN CAMERER,ERNST FEHR, HERBERTGINTIS, AND RICHARDMCELREATH* Recent investigations have uncovered large, ments shape behavior? If the latter, which eco- consistent deviationsfrom the predictionsof the nomic and social conditions are involved? Is textbook representationof Homo economicus reciprocalbehavior better explained statistically (Alvin E. Roth et al., 1991; Ernst Fehr and by individuals' attributessuch as their sex, age, Simon Gachter, 2000; Colin Camerer, 2001). or relative wealth, or by the attributesof the One problem appears to lie in economists' ca- group to which the individuals belong? Are nonical assumptionthat individuals are entirely there cultures that approximate the canonical self-interested:in additionto their own material account of self-regardingbehavior? payoffs, many experimentalsubjects appear to Existing research cannot answer such ques- care about fairness and reciprocity, are willing tions because virtually all subjects have been to change the distributionof materialoutcomes university students,and while there are cultural at personal cost, and are willing to rewardthose differences among studentpopulations through- who act in a cooperative mannerwhile punish- out the world, these differences are small com- ing those who do not even when these actions pared to the range of all social and cultural are costly to the individual. These deviations environments.To address the above questions, from what we will term the canonical model we and our collaborators undertook a large have importantconsequences for a wide range cross-cultural study of behavior in ultimatum, of economic phenomena,including the optimal public good, and dictatorgames. Twelve expe- design of institutions and contracts,the alloca- rienced field researchers,working in 12 coun- tion of property rights, the conditions for suc- tries on five continents, recruitedsubjects from cessful collective action, the analysis of 15 small-scale societies exhibiting a wide vari- incomplete contracts, and the persistence of ety of economic and cultural conditions. Our noncompetitive wage premia. sample consists of three foraging societies, six Fundamentalquestions remain unanswered. that practice slash-and-burnhorticulture, four Are the deviations from the canonical model nomadic herding groups, and three sedentary, evidence of universalpatterns of behavior,or do small-scale agriculturalistsocieties. Our results the individual's economic and social environ- are described in detail, with extensive ethno- graphicaccounts of the cultures we studied and citations to the relevant literature,in Henrich et * Henrich: School of Business Administration,Univer- sity of Michigan, Ann Arbor, MI 48109; Boyd and McEl- al. (2001); an extended overview paper is avail- reath: Department of Anthropology, University of able online.1 California at Los Angeles, Los Angeles, CA 90095; We can summarize our results as follows. Bowles: Department of Economics, University of Massa- First, the canonical model is not supportedin chusetts, Amherst,MA 01003, and SantaFe Institute;Cam- any society studied. Second, there is consider- erer: Department of Economics, California Institute of Technology, Pasadena, CA 91125; Fehr: Institute for Em- ably more behavioral variability across groups pilical Research in Economics, University of Ztiiich, Bltim- than had been found in previous cross-cultural lisalpstrasse 10, CH-8006, Zurich, Switzerland; Gintis: research, and the canonical model fails in a University of Massachusetts, Amherst, MA 01003. The wider variety of ways than in previous experi- research described in this paper was funded by the MacArthurFoundation's Research Group on the Natureand ments. Third, group-level differences in eco- Origin of Norms and Preferences,directed by Robert Boyd nomic organization and the degree of market and HerbertGintis. The field experiments were calTiedout by Henrich, McElreath,Michael Alvard, Abigail Barr,Jean Ensminger,Francisco Gil-Vhite, Michael Gurven,Kim Hill, FrankMarlowe, John Patton, Natalie Smith, and David Tracer. 1 URL: (www.santafe.edu) 73 74 AEA PAPERSAND PROCEEDINGS MAY2001 integrationexplain a substantialportion of the TABLE 1-THE ULTIMATUMGAME IN SMALL-SCALE behavioralvariation across societies: the higher SOCIETIES the degree of marketintegration and the higher Low- the payoffs to cooperation,the greaterthe level offer of cooperation in experimentalgames. Fourth, Mean Rejection rejection Group Country offera Modesb ratec rated individual-level economic and demographic variables do not explain behavior either within Machiguenga Peru 0.26 0.15/0.25 0.048 0.10 (72) (1/21) (1/10) or across groups. Fifth, behavior in the experi- Hadza Tanzania 0.40 0.50 0.19 0.80 ments is generally consistent with economic (big camp) (28) (5/26) (4/5) Hadza Tanzania 0.27 0.20 0.28 0.31 patternsof everyday life in these societies. (small (38) (8/29) (5/16) camp) I. The Evidence Tsiman6 Bolivia 0.37 0.5/0.3/0.25 0.00 0.00 (65) (0/70) (0/5) Quichua Ecuador 0.27 0.25 0.15 0.50 Because the ultimatumgame (UG) has been (47) (2/13) (1/2) conducted the Torguud Mongolia 0.35 0.25 0.05 0.00 throughout world with student (30) (1/20) (0/1) populationsand has generatedrobust violations Khazax Mongolia 0.36 0.25 of the canonicalmodel, we conductedthis game Mapuche Chile 0.34 0.50/0.33 0.067 0.2 (46) (2/30) (2/10) in all of our 17 societies. The "proposer"in this Au PNG 0.43 0.3 0.27 1.00 game is provisionally assigned an amount (33) (8/30) (1/1) equivalentto a day or two' s wages in the society Gnau PNG 0.38 0.4 0.4 0.50 (32) (10/25) (3/6) and asked to propose an offer to a second per- Sangu Tanzania 0.41 0.50 0.25 1.00 son, the "respondent."The respondentmay then farmers (35) (5/20) (1/1) Sangu Tanzania 0.42 0.50 0.05 1.00 either accept the offer, in which case the two herders (40) (1/20) (1/1) players receive the proposed amounts, or reject Unresettled Zimbabwe 0.41 0.50 0.1 0.33 it, in which case the two receive nothing. If both villagers (56) (3/31) (2/5) Resettled Zimbabwe 0.45 0.50 0.07 0.57 players conform to the canonical model and if villagers (70) (12/86) (4/7) this is common knowledge, it is easy to see that Achuar Ecuador 0.42 0.50 0.00 0.00 the proposerwill know that the respondentwill (36) (0/16) (0/1) Orma Kenya 0.44 0.50 0.04 0.00 accept any positive offer and so will offer the (54) (2/56) (0/0) smallest possible amount, which will be Ach6 Paraguay 0.51 0.50/0.40 0.00 0.00 (75) (0/5 1) (0/8) accepted. Lamelarae Indonesia 0.58 0.50 0.00 0.00 In most of our field experiments subjects (63) (3/8) (4/20) played anonymously, not knowing the identity Note: PNG = Papua New Guinea. of the person or persons with whom they were a This column shows the mean offer (as a proportion) in the ultimatum paired. The stakes of most games were denom- game for each society. b This column shows the modal offer(s), with the percentage of inated in money (though in some cases tobacco subjects who make modal offers (in parentheses). c The rejection rate (as a proportion), with the actual numbers given in or other goods were used). In all cases, we parentheses. d The rejection rate for offers of 20 percent or less, with the actual tested prospectiveparticipants for their compre- numbers given in parentheses. hension of the experiment and eliminated any e Includes experimenter-generated low offers. who appearednot to grasp the game. The systematic deviations from the canonical model in our sample of simple societies can be between 40 percent and 50 percent.Finally, the inferred from Table 1, which lists all groups Ache and the Lamelarahad mean offers greater where UG's were conducted. Contraryto the than 50 percent. prediction of the standard model, even the These group differences are strikingly large groups with the smallest offers have mean of- comparedto previous cross-culturalwork com- fers greaterthan 25 percent of stake size. Illus- paringultimatum-game behavior among univer- trating our second result (the large variation in sity students (Roth et al., 1991).
Recommended publications
  • Gender Differences in Responsiveness to a Homo Economicus Prime in the Gift-Exchange Game
    A Service of Leibniz-Informationszentrum econstor Wirtschaft Leibniz Information Centre Make Your Publications Visible. zbw for Economics Mertins, Vanessa; Warning, Susanne Working Paper Gender differences in responsiveness to a homo economicus prime in the gift-exchange game IAAEU Discussion Paper Series in Economics, No. 09/2013 Provided in Cooperation with: Institute for Labor Law and Relations in the European Union (IAAEU), University of Trier Suggested Citation: Mertins, Vanessa; Warning, Susanne (2013) : Gender differences in responsiveness to a homo economicus prime in the gift-exchange game, IAAEU Discussion Paper Series in Economics, No. 09/2013, University of Trier, Institute for Labour Law and Industrial Relations in the European Union (IAAEU), Trier This Version is available at: http://hdl.handle.net/10419/80863 Standard-Nutzungsbedingungen: Terms of use: Die Dokumente auf EconStor dürfen zu eigenen wissenschaftlichen Documents in EconStor may be saved and copied for your Zwecken und zum Privatgebrauch gespeichert und kopiert werden. personal and scholarly purposes. Sie dürfen die Dokumente nicht für öffentliche oder kommerzielle You are not to copy documents for public or commercial Zwecke vervielfältigen, öffentlich ausstellen, öffentlich zugänglich purposes, to exhibit the documents publicly, to make them machen, vertreiben oder anderweitig nutzen. publicly available on the internet, or to distribute or otherwise use the documents in public. Sofern die Verfasser die Dokumente unter Open-Content-Lizenzen (insbesondere CC-Lizenzen) zur Verfügung gestellt haben sollten, If the documents have been made available under an Open gelten abweichend von diesen Nutzungsbedingungen die in der dort Content Licence (especially Creative Commons Licences), you genannten Lizenz gewährten Nutzungsrechte. may exercise further usage rights as specified in the indicated licence.
    [Show full text]
  • Kranton Duke University
    The Devil is in the Details – Implications of Samuel Bowles’ The Moral Economy for economics and policy research October 13 2017 Rachel Kranton Duke University The Moral Economy by Samuel Bowles should be required reading by all graduate students in economics. Indeed, all economists should buy a copy and read it. The book is a stunning, critical discussion of the interplay between economic incentives and preferences. It challenges basic premises of economic theory and questions policy recommendations based on these theories. The book proposes the path forward: designing policy that combines incentives and moral appeals. And, therefore, like such as book should, The Moral Economy leaves us with much work to do. The Moral Economy concerns individual choices and economic policy, particularly microeconomic policies with goals to enhance the collective good. The book takes aim at laws, policies, and business practices that are based on the classic Homo economicus model of individual choice. The book first argues in great detail that policies that follow from the Homo economicus paradigm can backfire. While most economists would now recognize that people are not purely selfish and self-interested, The Moral Economy goes one step further. Incentives can amplify the selfishness of individuals. People might act in more self-interested ways in a system based on incentives and rewards than they would in the absence of such inducements. The Moral Economy warns economists to be especially wary of incentives because social norms, like norms of trust and honesty, are critical to economic activity. The danger is not only of incentives backfiring in a single instance; monetary incentives can generally erode ethical and moral codes and social motivations people can have towards each other.
    [Show full text]
  • The Social Side of Homo Economicus
    TREE-1308; No. of Pages 3 Update Forum The social side of Homo economicus Daniel J. Rankin1,2 1 Department of Biochemistry, University of Zu¨ rich, Building Y27, Winterthurerstrasse 190, CH-8057 Zu¨ rich, Switzerland 2 Swiss Institute of Bioinformatics, Quartier Sorge Baˆ timent Ge´ nopode, CH-1015 Lausanne, Switzerland Many recent experiments in the field of behavioural cooperatively than traditional economic theory would pre- economics appear to demonstrate a willingness of dict [1,11]. humans to behave altruistically, even when it is not in their interest to do so. This has led to the assertion that Are humans especially cooperative? humans have evolved a special predisposition towards Cooperation in public goods games is unstable and most altruism. Recent studies have questioned this, and dem- players quickly realise that not contributing maximises onstrated that selfless cooperation does not hold up in their profit (see Figure 1 for an explanation of public controlled experiments. As I discuss here, this calls for goods games). Despite this, the public goods game fre- more economic ‘field experiments’ and highlights the quently results in higher levels of contribution than one need for greater integration of the evolutionary and would expect if individuals were selfishly rational and economic sciences. 10% of participants contribute in the long run [1,12]. This has led to the conclusion that humans have a special Kto nekradne, okra´da svoju rodinu degree of cooperation, or ‘other regarding preferences’, (He who does not steal, steals from his family) that cannot be explained from a purely selfish perspec- Slovak Saying tive and that has been used as evidence that humans behave more cooperatively than theory would predict The apparent puzzle of human cooperation [1,12].
    [Show full text]
  • The Appearance of Homo Rivalis: Social Preferences and the Nature of Rent Seeking
    Centre for Decision Research and Experimental Economics Discussion Paper Series ISSN 1749-3293 CeDEx Discussion Paper No. 2008–10 The Appearance of Homo Rivalis: Social Preferences and the Nature of Rent Seeking Benedikt Herrmann and Henrik Orzen August 2008 The Centre for Decision Research and Experimental Economics was founded in 2000, and is based in the School of Economics at the University of Nottingham. The focus for the Centre is research into individual and strategic decision-making using a combination of theoretical and experimental methods. On the theory side, members of the Centre investigate individual choice under uncertainty, cooperative and non-cooperative game theory, as well as theories of psychology, bounded rationality and evolutionary game theory. Members of the Centre have applied experimental methods in the fields of Public Economics, Individual Choice under Risk and Uncertainty, Strategic Interaction, and the performance of auctions, markets and other economic institutions. Much of the Centre's research involves collaborative projects with researchers from other departments in the UK and overseas. Please visit http://www.nottingham.ac.uk/economics/cedex/ for more information about the Centre or contact Karina Whitehead Centre for Decision Research and Experimental Economics School of Economics University of Nottingham University Park Nottingham NG7 2RD Tel: +44 (0) 115 95 15620 Fax: +44 (0) 115 95 14159 [email protected] The full list of CeDEx Discussion Papers is available at http://www.nottingham.ac.uk/economics/cedex/papers/index.html The appearance of homo rivalis: Social preferences and the nature of rent seeking by Benedikt Herrmann and Henrik Orzen University of Nottingham August 2008 Abstract While numerous experiments demonstrate how pro-sociality can influence economic decision-making, evidence on explicitly anti-social economic behavior has thus far been limited.
    [Show full text]
  • Walrasian Economics in Retrospect
    A Service of Leibniz-Informationszentrum econstor Wirtschaft Leibniz Information Centre Make Your Publications Visible. zbw for Economics Bowles, Samuel; Gintis, Herbert Working Paper Walrasian Economics in Retrospect Working Paper, No. 2000-04 Provided in Cooperation with: Department of Economics, University of Massachusetts Suggested Citation: Bowles, Samuel; Gintis, Herbert (2000) : Walrasian Economics in Retrospect, Working Paper, No. 2000-04, University of Massachusetts, Department of Economics, Amherst, MA This Version is available at: http://hdl.handle.net/10419/105719 Standard-Nutzungsbedingungen: Terms of use: Die Dokumente auf EconStor dürfen zu eigenen wissenschaftlichen Documents in EconStor may be saved and copied for your Zwecken und zum Privatgebrauch gespeichert und kopiert werden. personal and scholarly purposes. Sie dürfen die Dokumente nicht für öffentliche oder kommerzielle You are not to copy documents for public or commercial Zwecke vervielfältigen, öffentlich ausstellen, öffentlich zugänglich purposes, to exhibit the documents publicly, to make them machen, vertreiben oder anderweitig nutzen. publicly available on the internet, or to distribute or otherwise use the documents in public. Sofern die Verfasser die Dokumente unter Open-Content-Lizenzen (insbesondere CC-Lizenzen) zur Verfügung gestellt haben sollten, If the documents have been made available under an Open gelten abweichend von diesen Nutzungsbedingungen die in der dort Content Licence (especially Creative Commons Licences), you genannten Lizenz gewährten Nutzungsrechte. may exercise further usage rights as specified in the indicated licence. www.econstor.eu WALRASIAN ECONOMICS IN RETROSPECT∗ Department of Economics University of Massachusetts Amherst, Massachusetts, 01003 Samuel Bowles and Herbert Gintis February 4, 2000 Abstract Two basic tenets of the Walrasian model, behavior based on self-interested exogenous preferences and complete and costless contracting have recently come under critical scrutiny.
    [Show full text]
  • Striking a Blow for Sanity in Theories of Rationality
    Published in: M. Augier & J. G. March (Eds.). (2004). Models of a man: Essays in memory of Herbert A. Simon (pp. 389– 409). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. © 2004 MIT Press. Striking a Blow for Sanity in Theories of Rationality Gerd Gigerenzer I took the title of this chapter from an email Herbert A. Simon sent me in May 1999. In this email, he wrote a statement for the back cover of Simple Heuristics That Make Us Smart in which he commented: “I think the book strikes a great blow for sanity in the approach to rationality [and shows] why more than minor tampering with existing optimization theory is called for.” But Herb wouldn’t be Herb if he hadn’t added “and you wouldn’t believe I had ever skimmed the volume if I didn’t fi nd SOMETHING to disagree with.” And so he continued, pointing out that he hadn’t found the expert/novice topic treated, that scientifi c discovery would have been a great example for ill-structured domains … Bringing sanity into theories of rationality was a major guideline in Herbert Simon’s scientifi c life. However, as he himself was prepared to admit, sanity in rationality entered his thinking as a negatively defi ned concept, a kind of black box that contained everything that was not optimiza- tion. What he opposed has various names: full rationality, substantial rationality, maximization of expected utility, Homo economicus, or simply optimization. What he proposed had its seeds in his revised dissertation, Administrative Behavior (1947), and eventually became termed bounded rationality, satisfi cing, or procedural rationality.
    [Show full text]
  • WELFARE CRITERIA Witih ENDOGENOUS PREFERENCES: the ECONOMICS of EDUCATION*
    iNTERNATIONAL ECONOMIC REVIEW Vol. 15, No. 2, Jtune, 1974 WELFARE CRITERIA WITIh ENDOGENOUS PREFERENCES: THE ECONOMICS OF EDUCATION* BY HERBERT GINTIS1 1. INTRODUCTION "BY ACTING on the external world and changing it," Karl Marx once re- marked, "[the worker] at the same time changes his own nature." [18, (197-98)] Much of Marxist theory is a development of this basic observation. The special position in Marxist theory of economic structure, its conception of materialism, of ideology, of classes and of social change, hinge on this connection. Indeed, again to quote Marx, "the whole of history is nothing but a continual transfor- mation of human nature" [19, (160)]. It is less than happenstance that the major competitor to Marxist theory, the tradition culminating in modern neo-classical economics, is grounded firmly not merely in the abstraction from, but the negation of this insight. The Marxist observation, translated into neo-classical terminology, holds that individual pref- erence structures are products of economic activity. Or more precisely, indi- vidual preferences develop and change according to variables endogenous to the economic model: prices, quantities, and availabilities of consumption goods, jobs, and the social institutions conditioning the supply of labor. Neo-classical theory starts from the contrary position: the Walrasian system takes preferences as either fixed, or changirngonly in response to variables external to the model. In positive economics, the formationi of preferences is relegated to sociology or social psychology; and in welfare economics, preference structures are amonig the fundamiiental,unexplained data. In the words of Harrod [13], The method of procedure is to take certain elements of the structure as given-namely the preference lists of individuals for goods and services, the terms on which they are willing to contribute their assistance to production and the current state of technologyy..
    [Show full text]
  • Reciprocity and Overoptimism in Public Goods Games
    Biased Beliefs and Reciprocal Behavior in Social Dilemmas Von der Fakultät für Wirtschaftswissenschaften der Rheinisch-Westfälischen Technischen Hochschule Aachen zur Erlangung des akademischen Grades eines Doktors der Wirtschafts- und Sozialwissenschaften genehmigte Dissertation vorgelegt von Dipl.-Ing. Anselm Hüwe Berichter: Univ.-Prof. Dr. rer. pol. Wolfgang Breuer Univ.-Prof. Dr. rer. pol. Christine Harbring Tag der mündlichen Prüfung: 21.04.2015 Diese Dissertation ist auf den Internetseiten der Hochschulbibliothek online verfügbar. Table of Contents 1 Introduction ............................................................................................................................. 1 2 Economic Experiments ........................................................................................................... 3 3 Game Theory and (Common) Belief in Rationality ................................................................ 8 3.1 Boundedly Rational Behavior ........................................................................................ 11 3.2 Biased Beliefs ................................................................................................................. 14 4 Social Preferences ................................................................................................................. 15 4.1 When Social Preferences Should Be Assumed, and When Not ..................................... 16 4.2 Evolutionary Analysis ...................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • On Philosophy, Politics, and Economics
    On Philosophy, Politics, and Economics Gerald F. Gaus University of Arizona THOMSON VVADSVVORTH Australia • Brazil • Canada , Mexico • Singapore • Spain United Kingdom • United States THC>IVISC>N VVADSVVORTH On Philosophy, Politics, and Economics Gerald F. Gaus Executive Publisher: Marcus Boggs Creative Director: Rob Hugel Acquisitions Editor: Worth Hawes Art Director: Maria Epes Assistant Editor: Patrick Stockstill Print Buyer: Linda Hsu Editorial Assistant: Kamilah Lee Permissions Editor: Bob Kauser Marketing Manager: Christina Shea Production Service: Tintu Thomas, Marketing Assistant: Mary Anne lntegra Payumo Copy Editor: Linda Ireland Marketing Communications Compositor: lntegra Manager: Darlene Amidon-Brent Project Manager, Editorial Production: Samen Iqbal © 2008 Thomson Wadsworth, a part Thomson Higher Education of The Thomson Corporation. 1 0 Davis Drive Thomson, the Star logo, and Belmont, CA 94002-3098 Wadsworth are trademarks used USA herein under license. ALL RIGHTS have reverted to author. For more information about our products, contact us at: Printed in the United States of America Thomson Learning Academic 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 11 10 09 08 07 Resource Center 1-800-423-0563 Library of Congress Control Number: For permission to use material 2007936260 from this text or product, submit Student Edition: a request online at http://www.thomsonrights.com. ISBN-13: 978-0-495-00898-9 Any additional questions ISBN-10: 0-495-00898-2 about permissions can be submitted by e-mail to [email protected]. Contents ABOUT THE AUTHOR VII LIST OF FIGURES AND TABLES VIII ACKNOWLEDGMENTS XII INTRODUCTION 1 1. INSTRUMENTAL AND ECONOMIC RATIONALITY 7 Overview 7 1.1 Instrumental Rationality 7 1.2 "Consumption Rationality" as Direct Satisfaction of Goals 15 1.3 Homo Economicus 19 Summary 27 Notes 28 2.
    [Show full text]
  • Behavioral Economics: Past, Present, and Future†
    American Economic Review 2016, 106(7): 1577–1600 http://dx.doi.org/10.1257/aer.106.7.1577 Behavioral Economics: Past, Present, and Future† By Richard H. Thaler* In recent years there has been growing interest in the mixture of psychology and economics that has come to be known as “behavioral economics.” As is true with many seemingly overnight success stories, this one has been brewing for quite a while. My frst paper on the subject was published in 1980, hot on the heels of Kahneman and Tversky’s 1979 blockbuster on prospect theory, and there were ( ) earlier forerunners, most notably Simon 1955, 1957 and Katona 1951, 1953 . ( ) ( ) The rise of behavioral economics is sometimes characterized as a kind of paradigm-shifting revolution within economics, but I think that is a misreading of the history of economic thought. It would be more accurate to say that the method- ology of behavioral economics returns economic thinking to the way it began, with Adam Smith, and continued through the time of Irving Fisher and John Maynard Keynes in the 1930s. In spite of this early tradition within the feld, the behavioral approach to eco- nomics met with considerable resistance within the profession until relatively recently. In this essay I begin by documenting some of the historical precedents for utilizing a psychologically realistic depiction of the representative agent. I then turn to a discussion of the many arguments that have been put forward in favor of retaining the idealized model of Homo economicus even in the face of apparently contradictory evidence. I argue that such arguments have been refuted, both theo- retically and empirically, including in the realm where we might expect rationality to abound: the fnancial markets.
    [Show full text]
  • Goodbye, Homo Economicus1 Anatole Kaletsky [The Times, UK]
    real-world economics review, issue no. 50 Goodbye, homo economicus1 Anatole Kaletsky [The Times, UK] Was Adam Smith an economist? Was Keynes, Ricardo or Schumpeter? By the standards of today’s academic economists, the answer is no. Smith, Ricardo and Keynes produced no mathematical models. Their work lacked the “analytical rigour” and precise deductive logic demanded by modern economics. And none of them ever produced an econometric forecast (although Keynes and Schumpeter were able mathematicians). If any of these giants of economics applied for a university job today, they would be rejected. As for their written work, it would not have a chance of acceptance in the Economic Journal or American Economic Review. The editors, if they felt charitable, might advise Smith and Keynes to try a journal of history or sociology. If you think I exaggerate, ask yourself what role academic economists have played in the present crisis. Granted, a few mainstream economists with practical backgrounds—like Paul Krugman and Larry Summers in the US—have been helpful explaining the crisis to the public and shaping some of the response. But in general how many academic economists have had something useful to say about the greatest upheaval in 70 years? The truth is even worse than this rhetorical question suggests: not only have economists, as a profession, failed to guide the world out of the crisis, they were also primarily responsible for leading us into it. By “economists” in this context I do not mean the talking heads and commentators (myself included) employed by the media and financial institutions to explain the credit crunch or the collapse of house prices or the rise of unemployment or the movements of currencies and stock markets—usually well after the event.
    [Show full text]
  • From Wald to Savage: Homo Economicus Becomes a Bayesian Statistician
    Munich Personal RePEc Archive From Wald to Savage: homo economicus becomes a Bayesian statistician Giocoli, Nicola University of Pisa, Department of Economics 14 October 2011 Online at https://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/34117/ MPRA Paper No. 34117, posted 14 Oct 2011 22:24 UTC From Wald to Savage: homo economicus becomes a Bayesian statistician Nicola Giocoli* Department of Economics, University of Pisa Bayesian rationality is the paradigm of rational behavior in neoclassical economics. A rational agent in an economic model is one who maximizes her subjective expected utility and consistently revises her beliefs according to Bayes’s rule. The paper raises the question of how, when and why this characterization of rationality came to be endorsed by mainstream economists. Though no definitive answer is provided, it is argued that the question is far from trivial and of great historiographic importance. The story begins with Abraham Wald’s behaviorist approach to statistics and culminates with Leonard J. Savage’s elaboration of subjective expected utility theory in his 1954 classic The Foundations of Statistics. It is the latter’s acknowledged fiasco to achieve its planned goal, the reinterpretation of traditional inferential techniques along subjectivist and behaviorist lines, which raises the puzzle of how a failed project in statistics could turn into such a tremendous hit in economics. A couple of tentative answers are also offered, involving the role of the consistency requirement in neoclassical analysis and the impact of the postwar transformation of US business schools. Word count: 19,618 (including footnotes and references) JEL Codes: B21, B31, D81 Keywords: Savage, Wald, rational behavior, Bayesian decision theory, subjective probability, minimax rule, statistical decision functions, neoclassical economics * Via Curtatone e Montanara 15, 56126, Pisa, Italy; [email protected].
    [Show full text]