Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science

Volume 40

Series editors Shahid Rahman, University of Lille III, France John Symons, University of Texas at El Paso, USA

Editorial Board Jean Paul van Bendegem, Free University of Brussels, Belgium Johan van Benthem, University of Amsterdam, The Netherlands Jacques Dubucs, CNRS/Paris IV, France Anne Fagot-Largeault, Collège de France, France Göran Sundholm, Universiteit Leiden, The Netherlands Bas van Fraassen, Princeton University, USA Dov Gabbay, King’s College London, UK Jaakko Hintikka, Boston University, USA Karel Lambert, University of California, Irvine, USA Graham Priest, University of Melbourne, Australia Gabriel Sandu, University of Helsinki, Finland Heinrich Wansing, Ruhr-University Bochum, Germany Timothy Williamson, Oxford University, UK , Epistemology, and the Unity of Science aims to reconsider the question of the unity of science in light of recent developments in logic. At present, no single logical, semantical or methodological framework dominates the philosophy of science. However, the editors of this series believe that formal techniques like, for example, independence friendly logic, dialogical , multimodal logics, game theoretic and linear logics, have the potential to cast new light on basic issues in the discussion of the unity of science. This series provides a venue where philosophers and logicians can apply specific technical insights to fundamental philosophical problems. While the series is open to a wide variety of perspectives, including the study and analysis of argumentation and the critical discussion of the relationship between logic and the philosophy of science, the aim is to provide an integrated picture of the scientific enterprise in all its diversity.

More information about this series at http://www.springer.com/series/6936 Walter Carnielli • Marcelo Esteban Coniglio

Paraconsistent Logic: Consistency, and

123 Walter Carnielli Marcelo Esteban Coniglio Department of Philosophy and Centre Department of Philosophy and Centre for Logic, Epistemology and the History for Logic, Epistemology and the History of Science (CLE) of Science (CLE) University of Campinas (UNICAMP) University of Campinas (UNICAMP) Campinas, São Paulo Campinas, São Paulo Brazil Brazil

ISSN 2214-9775 ISSN 2214-9783 (electronic) Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science ISBN 978-3-319-33203-1 ISBN 978-3-319-33205-5 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-33205-5

Library of Congress Control Number: 2016936981

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved by the Publisher, whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way, and transmission or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar or dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed. The use of general descriptive , registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publication does not imply, even in the absence of a specific , that such names are exempt from the relevant protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use. The publisher, the authors and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in this book are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor the authors or the editors give a warranty, express or implied, with respect to the material contained herein or for any errors or omissions that may have been made.

Printed on acid-free paper

This Springer imprint is published by Springer Nature The registered company is Springer International Publishing AG Switzerland To absent friends, and to Elias Alves, in memoriam. To our children: Bá, Juju, Matheus, Paolo, Gabriela, Vittorio… and to the kids we would have had, and to Juli and Tati. Sine qua non.

Campinas, February 29, 2016 Preface

I protest against the use of infinite magnitude as something completed, which in mathe- matics is never permissible. Infinity is merely a façon de parler, the real meaning being a limit which certain ratios approach indefinitely near, while others are permitted to increase without restriction.

C.F. Gauss, Brief an Schumacher (1831); Werke 8, 216 (1831) In a letter to the astronomer H.C. Schumacher in 1831, Gauss was rebuking mathematicians for their use of the infinite as a number, and even for their use of the symbol for the infinite. It would be difficult to sustain that kind of finitism, regardless of any epistemological considerations: a good part of mathematics simply cannot survive with only the potential infinite. The reaction against the infinite, as well as against complex or imaginary numbers, and against negative numbers before, are interesting examples of the difficulties faced, even by great minds, in accepting certain abstractions. Aristotle in Chaps. 4–8 of Book III of Physics argued against the actual infinite, advocating for the potential infinite. His idea was that natural numbers could never be conceived as a whole. Euclid in a certain sense never proved that there exist infinitely many prime numbers. What was actually stated in Proposition 20 of Book IX, carefully avoiding the term infinite, was that “prime numbers are more than any previously thought (total) number of primes”, which agrees with his tradition. It was only in the nineteenth century that G. Cantor dispelled all those accepted views by showing that an infinite set can be treated as a totality, as a full-fledged mathematical object with honorable properties, no less than the natural numbers. Imaginary numbers were introduced to mathematics in the sixteenth century (through Girolamo Cardano, though others had already used them in different guises). These numbers caused an embarrassment among mathematicians for cen- turies, since they faced astonishing difficulties in accepting an extension of the concept of number, especially in light of the problem of computing the square root of −1. Only after the fundamental works of L. Euler and Gauss did the complex

vii viii Preface numbers rid themselves of the label “imaginary” given them by Descartes in 1637, and even then not without difficulty. The mathematics of the infinite and of complex numbers, and all they represent in contemporary science, are triumphant cases of amplified concepts, but are not the only ones. A notable case of expansion of concepts, with deep implications for the development of contemporary logic, can be traced back to Frege and his famous article of 1891, Funktion und Begriff (see [1]). In this seminal paper, Frege recalls how the meaning of the term ‘function’ has changed in the history of mathematics, and how the mathematical operations used to define functions have been extended by, as he says, ‘the progress of science’: basically, through passages (or transitions) to the limit, as in the process of defining a new function y0 ¼ f 0ðxÞ from a function y ¼ f ðxÞ (provided that the limits involved in the calculus exist), and through accepting complex numbers in domains and images of functions. Starting from this point, Frege goes further into adding expressions that now we call predicates, such as ‘=’, ‘<’ and ‘>’. Leaving aside his philosophical motivations for seeing arithmetic as a “further development of logic”, what Frege started was a real revolution, that made possible the development of quantifiers and an unprecedented unification of propositional and predicate logic into a far more powerful system than any that preceded it. Not only could the -values, True and False, be taken as outputs of a function, but any object whatsoever could be similarly treated. To rephrase an example from Frege himself, if we suppose ‘the capital of x’ expresses a function, of which ‘the German Empire’ is the argument, Berlin is returned as the value of the function. In this way, Frege’s system could represent non-mathematical thoughts and predications, and founded the basis of the modern predicate calculus. Frege’s idea of defining an independent notion of ‘concept’ as a function which maps every argument to one of the truth-values True or False was instrumental in the development of a strict understanding of the notions of ‘proof’, ‘derivation’, and ‘semantics’ as parts of the same logic mechanism. Regarding ‘concept’ as a wide and independent notion based on an amplification of the idea of function was an essential step for Frege’s fundamental break between the older Aristotelian tradition and the contemporary approach to logic. Paraconsistency is the study of logical systems in which the presence of a contradiction does not imply triviality, that is, logical systems with a non-explosive negation : such that a pair of propositions A and :A does not (always) trivialize the system. However, it is not only the syntactic and semantic properties of these systems that are worth studying. Some questions arise that are perennial philo- sophical problems. The question of the nature of the allowed by paraconsistent logics has been a focus of debate on the philosophical significance of paraconsistency. Although this book is primarily focused on the logico-mathematical development of paraconsistency, the technical results emphasized here aim to help, and hopefully to guide, the study of some of those philosophical problems. Preface ix

Paraconsistent logics are able to deal with contradictory scenarios, avoiding triviality by means of the rejection of the Principle of Explosion, in the sense that these theories do not trivialize in the presence of (at least some) contradictory sentences. Different from traditional logic, in paraconsistent logics triviality is not necessarily connected to contradictoriness; in intuitive terms (a more formal account in given in Sect. 1.2) the situation could be described by the pictorial equation:

contradictoriness þ consistency ¼ triviality

The Logics of Formal Inconsistency, from now on LFIs, introduced in [2] and additionally developed in [3], are a family of paraconsistent logics that encom- passes a great number of paraconsistent systems, including the majority of systems developed within the Brazilian tradition. An important characteristic of LFIs is that they are endowed with linguistic resources that permit to express the notion of consistency of sentences inside the object language by using a sentential unary connective referred to as ‘circle’: A meaning A is consistent. Explosion in the presence of contradictions does not hold in LFIs, as much as in any other para- consistent logic. But LFIs are so designed that some contradictions will cause deductive explosion: consistent contradictions lead to triviality–intuitively, one can understand the notion of a ‘consistent contradiction’ as a contradiction involving well-established facts, or involving propositions that have conclusive favorable evidence. In this sense, LFIs are logics that permit one to separate the sentences for which explosion hold, from those for which explosion does not hold. It is not difficult to see that, in this way, reasoning under LFIs extend and expand the reasoning under : although LFIs are technically subsystems of classical logic, classical logic can be identified with that portion of LFIs that deals with ‘consistent contradictions’. Therefore LFIs subsume classical reasoning. This point will be explained in more detail in Sect. 1.2. We may say that a first step in paraconsistency is the distinction between triv- iality and contradictoriness. But there is a second step, namely, the distinction between consistency and non-contradictoriness. In LFIs the consistency connective  is not only primitive, but it is also not necessarily equivalent to non-contradiction. This is the most distinguishing feature of the logics of formal inconsistency. Once we break up the equivalence between A and :ðA ^:AÞ, some quite inter- esting developments become available. Indeed, A may express notions of con- sistency independent from freedom from contradiction. The most important conceptual distinction between LFIs and traditional logic is that LFIs start from the principle that assertions about the world can be divided into two categories: consistent sentences and non-consistent sentences. Consistent propositions are subjected to classical logic, and consequently a theory T that contains a pair of contradictory sentences A; :A explodes only if A is taken to be a consistent sentence, linguistically marked as A (or :A). This is the only dis- tinction between LFIs and classical logic, albeit with far-reaching consequences: x Preface classical logic in this form is augmented, in such a way that in most cases an LFI encodes classical logic. The concept of LFIs generalizes and extends the famous hierarchy of C-systems introduced in [4] and popularized by hundreds of papers. At the same time, LFIs expand the classical logical stance, and consequently the majority of the traditional concepts and methods of classical logic, propositional or quantified (and even higher-order), can be adapted, with careful attention to detail. Since, as much as , LFIs are more of an epistemic nature, rather than of an ontological, there is no point in advocating the replacement of classical logic with . Because LFIs extend the classical stance, the analogy with transfinite ordinal numbers and with complex numbers is com- pelling: in such cases, there is no rejection of what has come before, but a refinement of it. It is not infrequent that an argument as of the skeptics, such as that given by Sextus Empiricus1 against the sophists, is trumpeted against the need of paracon- sistent logic, in science or reasoning in general:

[If an argument] leads to what is inadmissible, it is not we that ought to yield hasty assent to the absurdity because of its plausibility, but it is they that ought to abstain from the argument which constrains them to assent to absurdities, if they really choose to seek truth, as they profess, rather than drivel like children. Thus, suppose there were a road leading up to a chasm, we do not push ourselves into the chasm just because there is a road leading to it but we avoid the road because of the chasm; so, in the same way, if there should be an argument which leads us to a confessedly absurd conclusion, we shall not assent to the absurdity just because of the argument but avoid the argument because of the absurdity. So whenever such an argument is propounded to us we shall suspend judgement regarding each premiss, and when finally the whole argument is propounded we shall draw what conclusions we approve. This argument, however, if it is not against the use of any logic, is indeed favorable to the kind of paraconsistency represented by LFIs. The notion of con- sistency—symbolized as  when applied to propositions—actually increases our wisdom: it does not stop one to jump into the chasm, but rather marks out the dangerous roads and, precisely, helps avoid such roads because of the chasm! The idea that consistency can be taken as a primitive, independent notion, and be axiomatized for the good profit of logic is a new idea, which permits one to separate not only the notion of contradiction from the notion of deductive triviality, which is true of all paraconsistent logics, but also the notion of inconsistency from the notion of contradiction—as well as consistency from non-contradiction. This refined idea of consistency has great potential, as we shall see in detail in this book, as unan- ticipated as the possibilities that imaginary numbers, completed infinite, and Frege’s idealization of a ‘concept’ as a function mapping arguments to one of the truth-values represented in mathematics, logic and philosophy. The rest of the book will speak for itself.

1Sextus Empiricus, Outlines of Pyrrhonism, LCL 273: 318–319. http://www.loebclassics.com/ view/sextus_empiricus-outlines_pyrrhonism/1933/pb_LCL273.3.xml Preface xi

Book’s Content: A Road Map

Chapter 1 Chapter 1 purports to clarify the whole project behind LFIs, making sense of its idealization and basic tenets. The paraconsistent viewpoint—materialized by means of LFIs—objects to classical logic, but only on the grounds that contradiction and triviality cease to coincide, and that contradiction ceases to coincide with incon- sistency. But this requires no opposition to the classical stance, just the awareness that ‘classical’ logic involves some hidden assumptions, as discussed above in this chapter. In the light of this, Sect. 1.2 makes explicit some of the philosophical underpinning implicit in LFIs. Section 1.3 will briefly retrace the motivations for the forerunners of LFIs and paraconsistency in general. No discussion of paraconsistency can avoid touching on, if only summarily, questions of the nature of logic, and Sect. 1.4 does this. Next challenges to be faced are questions about the nature of contradictions. Section 1.5 takes up this thorny philosophical topic from the times of the ancient Greece, cursorily discussing some remarks from Aristotle concerning three alleged versions of the Principle of Non-Contradiction that correspond to the three traditional aspects of logic, namely, ontological, epistemological, and linguistic. This stance helps to give a justification for the rational acceptance of contra- dictory sentences, and to better appreciate the distinctions among contradiction, consistency, and negation, as characterized in Sect. 1.6. It will also help to make palatable the rationale behind the semantics of LFIs to be developed in all math- ematical details in Chaps. 2 and 3, as well as to give support to alternative semantics for LFIs developed in Chap. 6. There is a wide variety of for repudiating (or at least to be cautioned against) classical logic, and many of them find an expression among paraconsistent logics. This chapter makes clear that LFIs are not coincidental with this spectrum of philosophical views, neither are they antagonistic, but can be combined with, and can complement, some of them. A summary of the main varieties of paraconsis- tency is given in Sect. 1.7, which attempts to clarify the position of LFIs with respect to other paraconsistent logics in the hope that this will justify some claims made in next chapters. Chapter 2 Chapter 2 offers a careful survey of the basic logic of formal inconsistency, mbC: it is basic in the sense that, starting with positive classical logic CPL+ and adding a negation and a consistency operator, it is endowed with minimal properties in order to satisfy the definition of LFIs. The chapter also lays out the main notation, ongoing definitions and main ideas that will be used throughout the book. Positive classical logic is assumed as a natural starting point from which the LFIs will be defined, although in Chap. 5 some LFIs will be studied starting from other logics than CPL+. A non-truth-functional valuation semantics for mbC is defined in Sect. 2.2, and its meaning and consequences explored in Sect. 2.3. xii Preface

A remarkable feature of LFIs in general, and of mbC in particular, as mentioned above, is that classical logic (CPL) can be codified, or recovered, inside such logics, as shown, for instance, in Sect. 2.4. One of the criteria proposed by da Costa in [5], p. 498, is that a paraconsistent calculus must contain as many of the schemata and rules of classical logic as can be endorsed without validating of the laws of explosion and non-contradiction. This vague criterion can be formalized in the sense that some LFIs can be proved to be maximal with respect to CPL, as in the case, for instance, of some three-valued LFIs treated in Chap. 4. Moreover, in addition to being a subsystem of CPL, mbC is also an extension of CPL, obtained by adding to the latter a consistency operator  and a paraconsistent negation : (see Sect. 2.5). In this sense, mbC can be viewed, both, as a subsystem and as a conservative extension of CPL. A similar phenomenon holds for several other LFIs. That section also sheds light on how CPL can be codified in mbC, showing that this can be achieved by way of a conservative translation, or by establishing a Derivability Adjustment Theorem (or DAT) between CPL and mbC. Section 2.5 also discusses an alternative formulation for mbC called mbC?, showing that by means of linguistic adaptations mbC can be directly introduced as an extension of CPL. Chapter 3 Chapter 3 deals with extensions of mbC, which by its turn is a minimal extension of CPL+ with a consistency operator  and a paraconsistent negation : charac- terizable as an LFI. This chapter defines several extensions of mbC, strengthening or expanding different characteristics of this basic system. In mbC, however, negation and consistency are totally separated concepts. The first extension of mbC, called mbCciw,isdefined as the minimal extension guaranteeing that the truth-values of α and :α completely determine the truth-value of α. Besides being a subsystem of classical logic, mbC is strong enough to contain the germ of classical negation, possessing a kind of hidden classical negation, as explained in Sect. 2.4 of Chap. 2. Section 3.2 of this chapter shows that here is another hidden operator in mbC: an alternative consistency operator β, one for each formula β. This operator establishes an important distinction, from a con- ceptual point of view, between mbC and mbC ? as clarified in Sect. 3.4. When he introduced his famous hierarchy Cn (1  n\ωÞ of paraconsistent systems, da Costa defined, for each system Cn, a kind of “well-behavedness” operator (later identified with consistency) in terms of the paraconsistent negation and conjunction (see Sect. 3.7). A special type of LFIs called dC-systems, char- acterized by the fact that the consistency operator can be defined in terms of the others, has been defined in [2]. The systems Cn of da Costa turn out to be examples of dC-systems. Section 3.3 of this chapter analyzes the formal notion of dC-systems, and investigates how to expand mbC in order to define the consistency Preface xiii and/or the inconsistency operator in terms of the other connectives of the given signature. In general terms, LFIs are concerned with the notion of consistency, expressed by the operator . The notion of inconsistency of α is usually defined via the new operator :α, expressing the (formal) inconsistency of α. Section 3.5 studies the balance (or better, unbalance) between the formal concepts of consistency and inconsistency, defining a new LFI (mbC, which, in fact, is a dC-system) where inconsistency is a primitive notion and consistency is a defined one. A natural requirement when characterizing consistency, as much as negation, is how consistency can be propagated through the remaining connectives. Sections 3.6 and 3.8 analyze extensions of mbC enjoying propagation of consistency in different forms, in the spirit of the historical systems of da Costa. Chapter 4 Chapter 4 deals with matrices and algebraizability, and their consequences. In particular, the question of characterizability by finite matrices, as well as the algebraizability of (extensions of) mbC is tackled. Some negative results, in the style of the famous Dugundji’s theorem for modal logics, are shown for several extensions of mbC. This results in new, compact proofs of previously established results, to the effect that a wide variety of LFIs extending mbC cannot be semantically characterized by finite matrices. Despite these general results, some three-valued extensions of LFIs can be characterized by finite matrices, and most of them are algebraizable in the well-known sense of Blok and Pigozzi. This is surprising, considering that several extensions of mbC, including the systems Cn of da Costa, cannot be algebraizable in Blok and Pigozzi’s sense (and consequently, not in Lindenbaum and Tarski’s sense). On the topic of LFIs that can be defined matricially, the chapter also covers Halldén’s. logic of nonsense as well as Segerberg’s variation, da Costa and D’Ottaviano’s, logic J3, also known in its variants LFI1 and MPT, Sette’s logic P1, Priest’s logic LP, the system Ciore, and several other related systems. Chapter 5 Chapter 5 is devoted to giving an account of LFIs based on other logics, distinct from what was done in previous chapters, in which LFIs based exclusively on positive classical logic CPL+ were studied. Although several extensions of the basic system mbC have been proposed, including several three-valued logics (some of them even algebraizable in the sense of Blok and Pigozzi, which is not possible in the case of mbC) the underlying basis was always CPL+. This chapter, instead, analyzes LFIsdefined over other logical basis, to wit: positive intuitionistic logic, the four-valued Belnap and Dunn’s logic BD, some families of fuzzy logics, and some positive modal logics. Section 5.1 starts by defining LFIs based on positive intuitionistic logic, instead of CPL+, beginning with paraconsistent logics based on IPL+ (taking as a basis Johansson’s minimal logic and Nelson’s logic). A weaker version of mbC called xiv Preface imbC obtained from the former by changing the positive basis CPL+ to IPL+ is also investigated, Section 5.2 is dedicated to the task of combining two paradigms of uncertainty: fuzziness and paraconsistency, with exciting possibilities. Taking as a basis the monoidal t-norm based logic MTL introduced in [6] as a generalization of the famous basic fuzzy logic BL due to P. Hájek (which, in turn, simultaneously generalizes three chief fuzzy logics, namely Łukasiewicz, Gödel-Dummet and Product logics) several new LFIs had been recently developed (see [7]). Justified by the fact that MTL is the most general residuated fuzzy logic whose semantics is based on t-norms, the LFIsdefined over MTL give a finely controlled combination of fuzzy and consistency (as well inconsistency) operators, giving rise to mathematical models for the novel notion of fuzzy (in)consistency operators, which formalizes the nice and natural idea of degrees of consistency and inconsistency. Section 5.3 investigates a four-valued modal LFI based on N. Belnap and J.M. Dunn’s logic BD, a logic (based on their famous bilattice logic FOUR) suitable for representing lack of information (a sentence is neither true nor false) or excess of information (a sentence is both true and false). The logic BD was defined from the notion of proposition surrogates introduced by J.M. Dunn about five decades ago as a set-theoretic tool for representing De Morgan Lattices. The logic M4m, a matrix logic expanding Belnap and Dunn’s logic BD by adding a modal operator, is then defined and proved to be an LFI. Moreover, it is a dC-system based on the logic preserving degrees of truth of the variety of bounded distributive lattices. The logic M4m is based on the previous work by A. Monteiro on tetravalent modal algebras. The chapter closes, in Sect. 5.4, with an overview of the notion of modal LFIs and their unfoldings. Chapter 6 Chapter 6 studies alternative semantics for the LFIs presented in Chaps. 2 and 3, concentrating on the novel notion of swap structures. As much as modal logics, LFIs are in general non-truth-functional, and (as much as modal logics) have access to different kinds of semantics (like algebraic semantics, Kripke or relational semantics, topological semantics, and neighborhood semantics, among others) to better clarify their meaning, LFIs also naturally require a plurality of semantics. But unlike modal logics, LFIs in general do not have non-trivial logical congruences, and the question of defining other semantics for LFIs becomes more sensible. Standard tools, like categorial or algebraic semantics, will not work so easily for LFIs and the development of alternative semantical techniques for certain LFIsis an ongoing and relevant task. The chapter clarifies the heritage of swap structures from M. Fidel’s notion of twist structures (studied in Chap. 5), and also discusses the close relationship between the concept of Fidel structures, swap structures and non-deterministic matrices (or Nmatrices). Section 6.8 surveys the possible-translations semantics (PTSs), a broad semantical concept introduced in 1990 that gives new philosophical interpretations Preface xv for some non-classical logics, and especially for paraconsistent logics. It happens that PTSs is a very general semantical notion, to the point that virtually any logic may have a PTS interpretation, under certain conditions. It also happens that several other semantical notions can be seen as particular cases of PTSs; those points are carefully explained in that section. Chapter 7 Chapter 7 gives a full account of LFIs for first-order languages. The quantified versions of LFIs are essential for certain mathematical applications, such as , and also for concrete applications in computer science, such as databases and logic programming. The combination of the consistency operator  with quantifiers 8 and 9 demands a careful treatment: now, the propagation of consis- tency through quantifiers has to be duly balanced, generalizing from the propaga- tion of consistency for conjunction and disjunction. The intuitive idea, of course, is to regard the existential quantifiers as arbitrary conjunctions and disjunctions, but this has to be done taking a certain technical care. The chapter is structured around a complete treatment of the system QmbC,a quantified exension of the system mbC, the basic LFI studied in Chap. 2. Other extensions of QmbC, such as QCi and QmbC  (the latter including an equality predicate), are also treated, keeping QmbC at the horizon. From the point of view of semantics, Tarskian first-order structures are now endowed with a paraconsistent bivaluation, and what results is a wide generalization of familiar model theory. An alternative approach to three-valued first-order LFIs is developed in detail in Sect. 7.9, based on the theory of quasi-truth. This treatment, of course, can be extended to other many-valued paraconsistent logics. The paradigm of quasi-truth, which provides a way of accommodating the conceptual incompleteness inherent in scientific theories as studied in [8], views scientific theories from the perspective of paraconsistent logic. This paradigm offers a rational account for the dynamics of theory change, allowing for theories involving contradictions without triviality, with deep implications for the founda- tions of science and for the understanding of the scientific method. A generalization of the logical aspects of the theory of quasi-truth has been undertaken in [9], by means of a three-valued model theory for an LFI called LPT1, which in turn coincides (setting aside some details of language) with the quantified version of the three-valued paraconsistent logic LFI1 introduced in Definition 4.4.41. An addi- tional discusion on quasi-truth can be found in Sect. 9.3 of Chap. 9. One of the aims of this chapter is to endorse the claim that basically the same results of classical model theory hold for QmbC, and for first-order LFIs in gen- eral, with certain provisos. Well-established results in traditional model theory such as the Completeness, Compactness and Lowenhëim–Skolem Theorems can be proved for first-order LFIs along the same lines as the classical case. In this way, the chapter makes clear that first-order LFIs expand traditional logic, and allows for a revision of the uses of logic in mathematics and computer science from the vantage point of richer logics. xvi Preface

Chapter 8 The confusion between the concept of set on the one hand, and of class, or species, on the other hand, has plagued the foundations of set theory since its birth. The Principle of Comprehension (also referred to as the Principle of Naïve Comprehension, or Abstraction) was proposed in the nineteenth century, fruit of the somewhat romantic ideas of Dedekind, Cantor, and Frege, and states that for every property, expressed as a predicate, there exists a set consisting of exactly those objects that satisfy the predicate. This principle lurks behind certain tough para- doxes, such as Russell’s , and the history of contemporary set theory has much to do with efforts to rescue Cantor’snaïve set theory from triviality, an inevitable consequence, in traditional logic, of the contradictions entailed by those . Paraconsistent set theory has been an endeavor to save set theory from certain (it not all) paradoxes for at least three decades. Chapter 8 aims to offer a new approach to this question by means of employing LFIs and their powerful con- sistency operator. By assuming that not only sentences, but sets themselves can be classified as consistent or inconsistent objects, the basis for new paraconsistent set-theories that can resist certain paradoxes without falling into trivialism is established. One of the main motivations of this chapter, as stated in Sect. 8.1,isto rescue, together with Cantor’snaïve set theory, the proper Cantor’s intuition towards ‘inconsistent sets’. Indeed, the chapter attempts to show that Cantor’s treatment of inconsistent collections can be related to the one provided by means of LFIs. Section 8.2 defines ZFmbC, a basic system of paraconsistent set theory whose underlying logic is QmbC , and which contains two non-logical predicates (be- sides the equality predicate ): the binary predicate “2” (for membership), and the unary predicate C (for consistency of sets). Section 8.3 proposes some extensions of ZFmbC by means of employing stronger LFIs as underlying logics and setting appropriate axioms for the consistency operator C for sets. Section 8.4 discusses the relationship between the notions of ‘to be a consistent object in set theory’ (as formalized in the chapter) and ‘to be a set’. It shows that consistent objects can be (without risk of trivialism) regarded as sets, by means of an appropriate axiom. In the same spirit, proper classes can be regarded as inconsistent objects. Such affinities between consistent objects in set theory and sets, and between proper classes and inconsistent objects, though it cannot be strengthened into equivalence, testify to the richness of this approach. Section 8.5, the last in the chapter, starts the discussion of models of paracon- sistent set theory. If the construction of models for standard set theory is a fraught task, the analogue for paraconsistent set theory is adventurous, to say the least. One might consider standard models of paraconsistent set theory, where the ε relation of that model corresponds exactly to the membership relation 2 of the universe of ZFmbC and its extensions, and the same for the consistency operator , but it is also reasonable to make room for non-standard models. Only in this way could one venture into deeper waters, such as extending forcing machinery to paraconsistent Preface xvii set theory. Although this is not done in this book, and it may be an ambitious project, it is not unrealistic. Chapter 9 Chapter 9 attempts to clarify the close connections between paraconsistency and philosophy of science: in a nutshell, there are so many cases of contradictions, even if temporary, arising between scientific theories, as well as between facts and theories, that a paraconsistent approach to the foundations of science seem to be almost inevitable. Section 9.1 advocates an epistemological understanding of paraconsistency based upon the notion of evidence, and questions its significance for science supported by some examples of real situations, examined in Sect. 9.2. Consistency and contradiction in scientific theories can be understood by an epis- temic approach to paraconsistency, we claim, inspired by some Kantian insights about the limits of human . Some historical examples of cases where sci- entists have held contradictory positions, and where science as a whole has gained from holding them, are reviewed in this section. The controversy surrounding the movement of the luminiferous aether of the nineteenth century, the controversies in the early development of quantum theory, the case of Mercury’s orbit and the failure in hypothesizing Vulcan, a planet that only existed in the heads of certain astronomers, and the contradictions arising from the ‘imponderable’ phlogiston in the beginnings of the chemistry of the eighteenth century are illuminating cases. The provisional contradictions faced by Einstein just before he formulated the special theory of relativity in 1905 is another typical example of what we call epistemic contradictions, which arise between two non-contradictory theories that, when put together, yield contradictory results. The phenomenon is not restricted to natural sciences: the imaginary numbers, which baffled mathematicians and philosophers until the beginning of the twentieth century, is another piece of epistemic contradiction. Section 9.3 reviews—from a more philosophical perspective—the concept of pragmatic truth, also referred to as quasi-truth, or partial truth, already analyzed from the formal point of view in Chap. 7. Quasi-truth, developed as part of efforts to expand the bounds of the traditional Tarskian account of formalized truth, proposes a partial (or pragmatic) notion of truth, intending to capture the meaning of wider, more flexible, theories of truth held by anti-realist thinkers in philosophy of science. Section 9.4 emphasizes the evidence-based approach to paraconsistency, in the sense of understanding a pair of contradictory sentences as representing, and allowing us to reason about, conflicting evidence, defending this view as particu- larly promising for philosophical interpretations of paraconsistent logics. The last section, Sect. 9.5, succinctly wraps up one of the chief points behind LFIs: they are concerned with truth, since classical logic can be fully recovered inside most of the LFIs, but they are also concerned with the notion of evidence, a notion weaker than truth that allows for an intuitive and plausible understanding of the acceptance of contradictions in some reasoning contexts. In this regard, both intuitionistic and paraconsistent logics may be conceived as normative theories of endowed with an epistemic character. This view not only xviii Preface stresses the brotherhood between the intuitionistic and the paraconsistent para- digms, but explains the adequacy of LFIs for wider accounts in the philosophy of science, and also their applicability in the fields of linguistics, theoretical computer science, inferential , and confirmation theory.

References

1. Frege, Gottlob. 1891. Über Funktion und Begriff (in German). In Jenaischen Gesellschaft für Medizin und Naturwissenschaft. Jena: Verlag Hermann Pohle. Translated by Peter Geach as ‘Function and Concept’.InTranslations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege, ed. Peter Geach and Max Black, Blackwell, 1980. 2. Carnielli, Walter A., and João Marcos. 2002. A taxonomy of C-systems. In Paraconsistency: The Logical Way to the Inconsistent. Proceedings of the 2nd World Congress on Paraconsistency (WCP 2000), volume 228 of Lecture Notes in Pure and Applied Mathematics, eds. Carnielli, Walter A., Marcelo E. Coniglio, and Itala M.L. D’Ottaviano, 1–94, New York: Marcel Dekker. 3. Carnielli, Walter A., Marcelo E. Coniglio, and João Marcos. 2007. Logics of Formal Inconsistency. In Handbook of (2nd edn), ed. Dov M. Gabbay and Franz Guenthner, vol. 14, 1–93. Springer, doi:10.1007/978-1-4020-6324-4_1. 4. da Costa, Newton C.A. 1963. Sistemas formais inconsistentes (Inconsistent formal systems, in Portuguese). Habilitation thesis, Universidade Federal do Paraná, Curitiba, Brazil, Republished by Editora UFPR, Curitiba, Brazil, 1993 5. da Costa, Newton C.A. 1974. On the theory of inconsistent formal systems (Lecture delivered at the First Latin-American Colloquium on , held at Santiago, Chile, July 1970). Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 15(4): 497–510. 6. Esteva, Francesc and Lluís Godo. 2001. Monoidal t-norm based logic: Towards a logic for left-continuous t-norms. Fuzzy Sets and Systems 124(3): 271–288. 7. Coniglio, Marcelo E., Francesc Esteva, and Lluís Godo. 2014. Logics of formal inconsistency arising from systems of fuzzy logic. Logic Journal of the IGPL 22(6): 880–904, doi:10.1093/ jigpal/jzu016. 8. Bueno, Otávio and Newton C. A. da Costa. 2007. Quasi-truth, paraconsistency, and the foundations of science. Synthese 154(3): 383–399. 9. Coniglio, Marcelo E., and Luiz H. Silvestrini. 2014. An alternative approach for quasi-truth. Logic Journal of the IGPL 22(2): 387–410, doi:10.1093/ljigpal/jzt026. Acknowledgments

We would like to express our gratitude to the many organizations and people who read, wrote, and offered criticisms and comments, allowed us to quote their papers, assisted in editing and proofreading, and provided support of all kinds—monetary, philosophical, personal, and emotional. We would like to acknowledge support from FAPESP (Thematic Project LogCons 2010/51038-0, Brazil) and from indi- vidual research grants from The National Council for Scientific and Technological Development (CNPq), Brazil. The intellectual environment of the Centre for Logic, Epistemology and the History of Science (CLE) of the State University of Campinas—UNICAMP deserves a special mention: we thank the colleagues and the officers of CLE for having provided all necessary facilities, from library facilities, to secretarial work, computers, and good coffee. Personal thanks go to Abílio Rodrigues (Belo Horizonte), Henrique Antunes Almeida (Campinas), Peter Verdée (Campinas and Brussels), Raymundo Morado (Campinas and Mexico City), Itala D’Ottaviano (Campinas), Giorgio Venturi (Campinas), David Gilbert (Campinas and Urbana), Gabriele Pulcini (Campinas), Rodolfo Ertola (Campinas), Francesc Esteva (Barcelona), Lluís Godo (Barcelona), Josep Maria Font (Barcelona), Ramón Jansana (Barcelona), Tommaso Flaminio (Varese), Carles Noguera (Prague), João Marcos (Natal), Juliana Bueno-Soler (Limeira), Newton Peron (Chapecó), Rafael Testa (Campinas), Marcio Ribeiro (Guarulhos), Erin O’Connor (Sorocaba), and Gareth J. Young (Glasgow). Thanks also to Christi Lue and to the Springer team (Dordrecht) for their continuous support over the many years this book took to complete. We beg forgiveness from all those we might have unintentionally failed to mention: we have made every effort to leave that set consistently empty.

xix Contents

1 Contradiction and (in)Consistency ...... 1 1.1 Introduction ...... 1 1.2 On the Philosophy of the Logics of Formal Inconsistency...... 4 1.3 A Historical Sketch: The Forerunners of the Logics of Formal Inconsistency ...... 10 1.4 Paraconsistency and the Nature of Logic ...... 11 1.5 Paraconsistency and the Nature of Contradictions ...... 15 1.6 Contradiction, Consistency and Negation ...... 18 1.6.1 On Contradiction ...... 19 1.6.2 On Consistency ...... 20 1.6.3 On Negation ...... 21 1.7 Varieties of Paraconsistency Involvement ...... 24 ...... 26 2 A Basic Logic of Formal Inconsistency: mbC ...... 29 2.1 Introducing mbC...... 29 2.2 A Valuation Semantics for mbC ...... 35 2.3 Applications of mbC-Valuations ...... 39 2.4 Recovering Classical Logic Inside mbC ...... 43 2.5 Reintroducing mbC as an Expansion of CPL ...... 50 2.5.1 The New Presentation mbC? of mbC ...... 51 2.5.2 Valuation Semantics for mbC ...... 53 2.5.3 Equivalence Between mbC and mbC?...... 55 References ...... 61 3 Some Extensions of mbC ...... 63 3.1 A Wider Form of Truth-Functionality for Consistency ...... 63 3.2 A Hidden Consistency Operator ...... 68 3.3 Consistency and Inconsistency as Derived Connectives...... 71 3.4 Some Conceptual Differences Between mbC and mbC? ...... 91 3.5 Inconsistency Operators and Double- ...... 95

xxi xxii Contents

3.6 Propagating Consistency...... 104 3.7 da Costa’s Hierarchy and Consistency Propagation ...... 111 3.8 A Stronger Consistency Propagation ...... 115 References ...... 119 4 Matrices and Algebraizability...... 121 4.1 Logical Matrices ...... 121 4.2 Uncharacterizability by Finite Matrices...... 122 4.3 The Problem of Algebraizability of LFIs ...... 129 4.4 Some 3-Valued LFIs ...... 136 4.4.1 Halldén’s Logic of Nonsense (1949) ...... 136 4.4.2 Segerberg’s Logic of Nonsense (1965) ...... 138 4.4.3 da Costa and D’Ottaviano’s Logic J3 (1970)...... 140 4.4.4 Sette’s Logic P1 (1973) ...... 144 4.4.5 Asenjo-Priest’s Logic LP (1966–1979) ...... 149 4.4.6 Ciore and Other Related Systems ...... 151 4.4.7 LFI1, MPT and J3 ...... 158 References ...... 168 5 LFIs Based on Other Logics...... 171 5.1 LFIs Based on Positive Intuitionistic Logic ...... 171 5.1.1 Basic Features of Positive Intuitionistic Logic ...... 171 5.1.2 Johansson’s Minimal Logic...... 175 5.1.3 Nelson’s Paraconsistent Logic N4 ...... 179 5.1.4 An Intuitionistic Version of mbC ...... 187 5.2 LFIs Based on Fuzzy Logics...... 191 5.2.1 Preliminaries on MFL ...... 191 5.2.2 Fuzzy Logics with a Consistency Operator ...... 197 5.2.3 Propagation of Consistency and DAT...... 205 5.2.4 Fuzzy Logics with an Inconsistency Operator ...... 208 5.3 A Modal LFI Based on Belnap and Dunn’s Logic BD ...... 211 5.3.1 The Logic M4m of Tetravalent Modal Algebras ...... 213 5.3.2 M4m as an LFI ...... 218 5.3.3 M4m as a dC-System ...... 222 5.3.4 The Contrapositive Implication ...... 224 c 5.3.5 A Hilbert-Style Axiomatization of M4m ...... 226 5.4 Paraconsistent Modalities, Consistency and Determinedness . . . . 229 References ...... 233 6 Semantics of Non-deterministic Character for LFIs ...... 237 6.1 Fidel Structures for mbC ...... 238 6.2 Fidel Structures for Some Extensions of mbC...... 242 6.3 Non-deterministic Matrices ...... 251 6.4 Swap Structures for mbC ...... 253 6.5 Swap Structures for Some Extensions of mbC ...... 260 6.6 Axiom (cl) and Uncharacterizability by Finite Nmatrices ...... 272 Contents xxiii

6.7 Some Remarks on Fidel Structures and Swap Structures ...... 279 6.8 The Possible-Translations Semantics ...... 280 6.8.1 Possible-Translations Semantics for Some LFIs...... 280 6.8.2 A 3-Valued Possible-Translations Semantics for Cila . . . 282 6.8.3 Some Remarks on Possible-Translations Semantics . . . . 288 References ...... 290 7 First-Order LFIs ...... 293 7.1 The Logic QmbC ...... 294 7.2 Basic Properties of QmbC ...... 296 7.3 Tarskian Paraconsistent Structures ...... 302 7.4 Soundness Theorem for QmbC ...... 308 7.5 Completeness Theorem for QmbC...... 310 7.5.1 Henkin Theories ...... 311 7.5.2 Canonical Interpretations...... 312 7.6 Compactness and Lowenhëim-Skolem Theorems for QmbC .... 316 7.7 QmbC with Equality ...... 318 7.8 First-Order Characterization of Other Quantified LFIs ...... 322 7.9 First-Order LFI1 and the Logic of Quasi-truth ...... 324 7.9.1 Semantics of Partial Structures...... 324 7.9.2 The Logic QLFI1 ...... 332 7.10 First-Order P1 and Partial Structures ...... 335 References ...... 343 8 Paraconsistent Set Theory ...... 345 8.1 Antinomic Sets and Paraconsistency...... 346 8.2 LFIs Predicating on Consistency ...... 349 8.3 Some Extensions of ZFmbC...... 354 8.4 Inconsistent Sets and Proper Classes ...... 360 8.5 On Models ...... 363 References ...... 365 9 Paraconsistency and Philosophy of Science: Foundations and Perspectives ...... 369 9.1 An Epistemological Understanding of Paraconsistency, and Its Significance for Science ...... 369 9.2 Consistency and Contradiction in Scientific Theories ...... 371 9.2.1 The Heritage of Kant ...... 371 9.2.2 Some Historical Examples ...... 373 9.2.3 The Beginning of Quantum Theory and Paraconsistency ...... 374 9.2.4 Mercury’s Orbit and a Non-existent Planet ...... 374 9.2.5 Contradictions in Phlogiston, the Imponderable ...... 376 9.2.6 The Special Theory of Relativity ...... 377 9.2.7 Mathematics, and the Meaning of Objects that Mean Nothing...... 379 xxiv Contents

9.3 Quasi-truth and the Reconciliation of Science and Rationality ...... 382 9.4 An Evidence-Based Approach to Paraconsistency ...... 384 9.5 Summing Up...... 385 References ...... 387

Index ...... 391

Index of Logic Systems ...... 397