A Contextualist History of Cartesian Philosophy: Roger Ariew’S Descartes and the First Cartesians

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Contextualist History of Cartesian Philosophy: Roger Ariew’S Descartes and the First Cartesians A Contextualist History of Cartesian Philosophy: Roger Ariew’s Descartes and the First Cartesians Domenico Collacciani Sorbonne Université–République des Saviors (USR3608) 1. Introduction The title Descartes and the First Cartesians only partly reflects the scope of the research presented in Roger Ariew’s latest book. To be sure, this study does offer a new and extensive account of the work of the first Cartesians and thus a new perspective on the historical phenomenon that was seventeenth century Cartesianism. Yet it does so on the basis of a vast survey of the Scholastic context from which the new philosophy emerged. The investigation of Cartesianism is thus given shape by the inquiry into Scholasticism (somewhat vague at first, the term is subsequently presented in all its nuances). From this point of view, Descartes and the First Cartesians takes up and completes the research Ariew presented in his 1999 Descartes and the Last Scholastics.Atfirst sight, then, the field surveyed is the tran- sition from one way of doing philosophy, one that is reaching its end, to the new philosophy just beginning. The guiding question seems to be whether and how Descartes’s philosophy succeeded in replacing Aristotle’s. Yet, as Ariew has demonstrated throughout his work, while there is indeed a transition taking place in the seventeenth century, it is in no way the case that one knowledge replaced another. The approach of Descartes and the First Cartesians thus consists in study- ing the transition from the viewpoint of an unchanging element, in defin- ing a trait that characterizes philosophy before and after Descartes. In considering the relationship of the new philosophy to Scholasticism, Ariew focuses on a specific context: the teaching of philosophy in the seventeenth century. He thus examines a sizable corpus of textbooks published before and after Descartes with the aim of measuring the effects of the encounter between Cartesian thought and a well-established traditional structure of Perspectives on Science 2018, vol. 26, no. 5 © 2018 by The Massachusetts Institute of Technology doi:10.1162/posc_a_00286 521 Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/posc_a_00286 by guest on 01 October 2021 522 Contextualist History of Cartesian Philosophy knowledge. At the center of his study is the well-known fact that Descartes initially conceived of his own textbook as an annotated edition of an earlier text (his choice had fallen on Eustache de Saint-Paul’s Summa quadripartita) and only later settled on publishing an autonomous work. The major strength of this method of research derives no doubt from the fact that the Cartesians were openly “rivaling” with the Scholastics (Ariew 2014, p. xvi). Historians of Cartesianism are well familiar with the polariza- tion of the debate. On the one hand, the Cartesians—Du Roure, Arnauld, Clerselier, and Rohault—explicitly and forcefully took up their master’s teachings (Azouvi 2002). On the other, the anti-Cartesians—Huygens, Oldenburg, Huet, and, starting the 1660s, the Jesuits—openly called out and criticized their adversaries’ sectarianism. Ariew turns this particular feature of the reception of Descartes into a principle for selecting his corpus. In fact, he remarks, there is no necessary and sufficient condition for calling an author “Cartesian.” Whether on the issue of doubt or of the cogito,ofthe divisibility of matter, and so on, there will always be an assuredly Cartesian author who will nonetheless reject one of these ideas central to Descartes’s philosophy. Yet the set of problems to be discussed in the book requires that the central category “Cartesian” leaves no room for doubt: “My rule of thumb is to think of ‘Cartesian’ as an actor’s category in the intellectual universe of the seventeenth century. The authors I cite as Cartesians published works with Descartes’ name prominently displayed in their titles or subtitles; they saw themselves as Cartesians and others saw them as such” (Ariew 2014, p. xvi).1 The first two chapters deal with Scholasticism before Descartes. The first describes Descartes’s position within the institutional setting, throw- ing light on the didactic practices of the religious orders that at the time enjoyed a de facto monopoly over education: the Oratorians, the Doctri- naires, and above all the Jesuits. In the second chapter, the author gives an account of the four part textbook prior to Descartes. The two last chapters show how a Cartesian textbook was constructed, first in the Prin- ciples of Philosophy, then in the work of the first Cartesians. 2. Chapter 1 The events relating to Descartes’s condemnation by the Roman Church have been the object of ample study in the critical literature. Contempo- raries noted that the attack on substantial forms mounted by mechanized 1. For a recent attempt at defining Cartesianism from a “non-essentialist” point of view via a study of these controversies, see Roux 2013. Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/posc_a_00286 by guest on 01 October 2021 Perspectives on Science 523 physics could imply a criticism of the dogma of the Eucharist.2 Nonethe- less, the sources are not entirely clear on this point: despite its significance, the 1663 censure by the Roman Church seems not to have been circulated in France. In keeping with its decidedly contextualist orientation, Ariew’s study thus turns primarily to Louis XIV’s 1671 condemnation whose effect on the spread of Cartesianism is indeed easily discernable. While the partisans of the new philosophy famously polemicized against any kind of philosophical sect, Ariew stresses that even before Descartes the field we call Scholastic philosophy was very heterogeneous. Around the middle of the century, Thomist Aristotelianism is still the doctrine of ref- erence; Scotism, meanwhile, seems to have established itself just as much, judging from the fact that, beside Thomism, it is attacked by the Cartesians as one of the main philosophical sects. Like “Cartesian,” however, the his- toriographical categories “Thomist” and “Scotist” are not invented by later historians; they are self-descriptions often explicitly used by the authors. It is thus possible to choose a paradigmatic text, draw certain general theses from it, and attribute these to one or the other of the categories. Ariew chooses the twenty-four Thomist (and anti-Scotist) theses articulated by the Dominican friar Antoine Goudin as a tool with which to “measure” the degree to which other authors are Thomists or Scotists. As for the institutions charged with teaching at mid-century, beside the colleges of the University of Paris, the market was dominated by the Oratorians and the Jesuits. Each of these schools was different and thus reacted differently to Descartes’ work. At the Sorbonne, instruction was based on the Scotist theses of Eustache de Saint-Paul’s Summa philosophiæ quadripartita, namely: the subject of metaphysics is the being shared by God and creatures; it is possible to have an idea of God even if it cannot be demonstrated a priori; there is a third distinction in addition to real and rational distinction, etc. The Oratorians’ teaching stands out in that it was being conducted in French and inspired by the Platonism of the order’s founder, Pierre de Bérulle. Matters are more complicated in the case of the Jesuits: even if the ratio studiorum demanded fidelity to Thomas, authors like Cériziers and Gautruche managed to have their Scotist lessons published. While the Society’s authorities in Rome and Spain were Thomist, those in Paris seem to have held less clear-cut positions. Descartes first came into contact with the Society of Jesus during his education in the collège at La Flèche, and the relationship with the order continued throughout his life. It can be divided into three periods: the first around the publication of the Discourse on the Method; the second dating to the 1640s and marked by the polemic with Bourdin; the third characterized 2. On the debate between Arnauld and Mesland, see Armogathe 1977. Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/posc_a_00286 by guest on 01 October 2021 524 Contextualist History of Cartesian Philosophy by the correspondence with Mesland. According to Ariew, the Jesuits—with the notable exception of Bourdin—were not hostile toward Descartes. After his death, however, they become more and more critical of Cartesian philosophy: the main difficulties they saw concerned its newness, its re- duction of physics to mathematics, and the explanation of the Eucharist. Descartes’s exchanges with the Oratorians were similarly rich. Ariew points to the meeting with Bérulle at Chandoux’s lecture and the cor- respondence with Gibieuf, whom Descartes asks for assistance in obtaining approbation for publishing the Meditations. In general, the Oratorian order was favorably disposed toward Descartes. Ariew cites the work of Nicolas Poisson, editor and commentator of some of Descartes’s posthumous works; Lamy and Fromentier, who taught Cartesian philosophy and were censored on that count; and, of course, Malebranche. Their adherence to Cartesianism, however, is never mere uncritical acceptance, as a look at de la Grange’s refutation of Descartes shows. By studying the history of Cartesianism via academic institutions, Ariew succeeds in combining several heterogeneous subjects within a stable per- spective. One remarkable result of this approach is that he is able to present the classic historiographical categories from a new angle. In 1978, Gouhier referred to a specifically French tendency within the reception of Descartes as “Augustinized Cartesianism,” which sought to correct Descartes’ system by grafting onto it theses backed up by the authority of Saint Augustine. In his study, Ariew demonstrates that this phenomenon is almost exclu- sively confined to Oratorian schools. Studying the pedagogical practices of the religious orders here leads to a remarkable result: the coherence of the themes of Augustinized Cartesianism reveals itself to be above all a doc- trinal coherence characteristic of a particular religious order.
Recommended publications
  • One Hundred Years of Thomism Aeterni Patris and Afterwards a Symposium
    One Hundred Years of Thomism Aeterni Patris and Afterwards A Symposium Edited By Victor B. Brezik, C.S.B, CENTER FOR THOMISTIC STUDIES University of St. Thomas Houston, Texas 77006 ~ NIHIL OBSTAT: ReverendJamesK. Contents Farge, C.S.B. Censor Deputatus INTRODUCTION . 1 IMPRIMATUR: LOOKING AT THE PAST . 5 Most Reverend John L. Morkovsky, S.T.D. A Remembrance Of Pope Leo XIII: The Encyclical Aeterni Patris, Leonard E. Boyle,O.P. 7 Bishop of Galveston-Houston Commentary, James A. Weisheipl, O.P. ..23 January 6, 1981 The Legacy Of Etienne Gilson, Armand A. Maurer,C.S.B . .28 The Legacy Of Jacques Maritain, Christian Philosopher, First Printing: April 1981 Donald A. Gallagher. .45 LOOKING AT THE PRESENT. .61 Copyright©1981 by The Center For Thomistic Studies Reflections On Christian Philosophy, All rights reserved. No part of this book may be used or Ralph McInerny . .63 reproduced in any manner whatsoever without written Thomism And Today's Crisis In Moral Values, Michael permission, except in the case of brief quotations embodied in Bertram Crowe . .74 critical articles and reviews. For information, write to The Transcendental Thomism, A Critical Assessment, Center For Thomistic Studies, 3812 Montrose Boulevard, Robert J. Henle, S.J. 90 Houston, Texas 77006. LOOKING AT THE FUTURE. .117 Library of Congress catalog card number: 80-70377 Can St. Thomas Speak To The Modem World?, Leo Sweeney, S.J. .119 The Future Of Thomistic Metaphysics, ISBN 0-9605456-0-3 Joseph Owens, C.Ss.R. .142 EPILOGUE. .163 The New Center And The Intellectualism Of St. Thomas, Printed in the United States of America Vernon J.
    [Show full text]
  • Bishop Robert Barron Recommended Books
    BISHOP ROBERT BARRON’S Recommended Books 5 FAVORITE BOOKS of ALL TIME SUMMA THEOLOGIAE Thomas Aquinas THE DIVINE COMEDY Dante Alighieri THE SEVEN STOREY MOUNTAIN Thomas Merton MOBY DICK Herman Melville MACBETH William Shakespeare FAVORITE Systematic Theology BOOKS CLASSICAL: • Summa Theologiae St. Thomas • On the Trinity (De trinitate) St. Augustine • On First Principles (De principiis) Origen • Against the Heresies (Adversus haereses) Irenaeus • On the Development of Christian Doctrine John Henry Newman MODERN/CONTEMPORARY: • The Spirit of Catholicism Karl Adam • Catholicism Henri de Lubac • Glory of the Lord, Theodrama, Theologic Hans Urs von Balthasar • Hearers of the Word Karl Rahner • Insight Bernard Lonergan • Introduction to Christianity Joseph Ratzinger • God Matters Herbert McCabe FAVORITE Moral Theology BOOKS CLASSICAL: • Secunda pars of the Summa theologiae Thomas Aquinas • City of God St. Augustine • Rule of St. Benedict • Philokalia Maximus the Confessor et alia MODERN/CONTEMPORARY: • The Sources of Christian Ethics Servais Pinckaers • Ethics Dietrich von Hilldebrand • The Four Cardinal Virtues and Faith, Hope, and Love Josef Pieper • The Cost of Discipleship Dietrich Bonhoeffer • Sanctify Them in the Truth: Holiness Exemplified Stanley Hauerwas FAVORITE Biblical Theology BOOKS CLASSICAL: • Sermons Origen • Sermons and Commentary on Genesis and Ennarationes on the Psalms Augustine • Commentary on John, Catena Aurea, Commentary on Job, Commentary on Romans Thomas Aquinas • Commentary on the Song of Songs Bernard of Clairvaux • Parochial and Plain Sermons John Henry Newman MODERN/CONTEMPORARY: • Jesus and the Victory of God and The Resurrection of the Son of God N.T. Wright • The Joy of Being Wrong James Alison • The Theology of the Old Testament Walter Brueggemann • The Theology of Paul the Apostle James D.G.
    [Show full text]
  • Alexander of Hales'stheology in His Authentic Texts (Commentary On
    chapter 13 Alexander of Hales’s Theology in His Authentic Texts (Commentary on the Sentences of Peter Lombard, Various Disputed Questions) Hubert Philipp Weber As the first teacher at the University of Paris to become a Franciscan friar, Alexander of Hales has an honoured place in the history of the order. The greater part of his theological work was already completed while he was a secular master. It is therefore more correct to call him an important theolo- gian who influenced Franciscan theology. However, it is not easy to distinguish what makes him a ‘Franciscan theologian’. I will begin by offering some his- torical remarks on his life and his authentic writings, most of which were discovered in the twentieth century. Then I will continue by giving an impres- sion of his thought with a few examples from his writings. The final sec- tion contains a very short outline of the Summa Universae Theologiae (also known as the Summa fratris Alexandri or Summa Halensis) connected with his name. 1 Historical Remarks: Alexander’s Life and Work We do not know very much about Alexander’s early life.1 His surname indicates his origin, Hales in Shropshire, England, where he was born around 1185. He stayed in contact with England all his life. In the first years of the thirteenth century he arrived at the University of Paris, where he studied and taught artes liberales. From about 1220 he lectured at the theological faculty. During the conflict between the university and the bishop of Paris in 1229/31 he went into exile.
    [Show full text]
  • |||GET||| Analytical Thomism 1St Edition
    ANALYTICAL THOMISM 1ST EDITION DOWNLOAD FREE Matthew S Pugh | 9781351958554 | | | | | Taking Aquinas Seriously Get A Copy. The Dominican order, to which Aquinas had belonged, defended his thought, and by a number of young teachers were among his strongest advocates. The extensive commentary on the Summa theologiae by Cardinal Cajetan remains unsurpassed for its detailed analysis. Through the influence of traditional Augustinian theologians, some theses of Aquinas were condemned in by the ecclesiastical authorities of Paris and Oxford the most important theological schools in the Middle Ages. Next Article. The rest of what you need we teach at VIU. In philosophy, Aquinas ' disputed questions and commentaries on Aristotle are perhaps his best-known Analytical Thomism 1st edition. Aristotle's De anima On the Soul divides the mind into three parts: sensationimagination and intellection. I also recommend that you read all of C. Consequently, God's causality is never in competition with the causality of creatures; rather, God even causes some things through the causality of creatures. It illuminates the Analytical Thomism 1st edition of Aquinas's work for contemporary problems by drawing on the resources of contemporary Anglo- Saxon analytical philosophy, the work of Frege, Wittgenstein, and Kripke proving particularly significant. See also: God. Mazdakism Mithraism Zoroastrianism Zurvanism. Lists with This Book. Get A Copy. The dominant theme was metaphysics Analytical Thomism 1st edition the study of being reality. But I am a knowing and moral being which is undeniable. The cover caught my attention. Repeated legislation of the General Chapters, beginning after the death of St. Aristotle categorized causality into four Analytical Thomism 1st edition in the Metaphysicswhich is an integral part of Thomism:.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphysical Systems
    Table of Contents Volume I - The Distant Past On ‘being’: Cartesianism - Passive Observation Introduction: Metaphysical system number three #1: The Error of Zeno Resolving the problem of Abstraction #2: The Error of Aristotle Resolving the problem of Cartesianism #3: The Error of Boethius Resolving the problem of Free Will #4: The Error of Copernicus Resolving the problem of Centricism $5: The Error of Leibniz Resolving the problem of Theodicy #6: The Error of Kant Resolving the problem of Universal Ethics Volume II - The Recent Past On ‘being’ being: Non-Cartesianism - Active Observation Preface to Volume II #7: The Error of Hegel Resolving the problem of non-Cartesianism $8: The Error of Einstein Resolving the problem of ‘i’ #9: The Error of Russell Resolving the problem of Non-Members #10: The Error of Heidegger Resolving the problem of The Void of a Void #11: The Error of Philosophy Resolving the problem of Either/Or #12: The Error of ‘being’ being Resolving the problem of Nihilism Volume III - The Future On ‘being’ being ‘Being’: Cartesianism ‘within’ Non-Cartesianism: Active Observation within Passive Observation Preface to Volume III #13: Metaphysical System 28 Introducing the problem of Metaphysical Systems 7 & 9 #14: Principle Three Introducing the problem of Principles One and Two #15: Ockham’s Razor Introducing the problem of Reductionism #16: Wrong Again Introducing the problem of Being Right #17: The Beginning Introducing the problem of The End #18: Why Now? Introducing the problem of History’s Vector Conclusion: The Peer
    [Show full text]
  • HNRS 2030 — Humanities Colloquium: Aristotle and Aquinas on Nature and Justice
    “It has been well said of Aristotle, ‘Solet Aristoteles quaerere pugnam’; ‘Aristotle has a habit of seeking a fight.’ He is seeking a fight not because he loves fight and enmity but because he loves peace and friendship; but true peace and friendship can only be found in the truth.” Leo Strauss1 “It will not be possible to conceal much longer from anybody the fact that St. Thomas Aquinas was one of the great liberators of the human intellect…. Thomas was a very great man who reconciled religion with reason, who expanded it towards experimental science, who insisted that the senses were the windows of the soul and that the reason had a divine right to feed upon facts, and that it was the business of the Faith to digest the strong meat of the toughest and most practical of pagan philosophies” G.K. Chesterton2 HONORS 2030: Humanities Colloquium Aristotle and Aquinas: On Nature and Justice Spring 2019 Through study of the writings of Aristotle and Aquinas, we will seek to understand what nature is and how it can be known, and then to consider the implications for understanding human nature and the question of how to live a good life, individually and in community with others. Attending to the influence of modern science as well as to the rise of modern society, we will ask what is living and true in the philosophy of Aristotle and Aquinas, respectively, and what has been superseded by modern discoveries. Instructor: James Stoner Stubbs 214 (tel: 578-2538); e-mail: [email protected] Office Hours: M, 2:00-3:00, W, 1:30–3:30, and by appointment Books available for purchase: • Anthony Rizzi, The Science Before Science (Institute for Advanced Physics/AuthorHouse) [ISbN 9781418465049] • Richard McKeon, ed., Basic Works of Aristotle (Modern Library) [ISbN 9780375757990] • Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics (tr, Robert Bartlett & Susan Collins) (Chicago) [ISbN 9780226026756] • Thomas Aquinas, Summa of the Summa [ed.
    [Show full text]
  • Theories and Images of Creation in Northern Europe in the Twelfth Century
    Art History ISSN 0141-6790 Vol. 22 No. 1 March 1999 pp. 3-55 In the Beginning: Theories and images of creation in Northern Europe in the twelfth century Conrad Rudolph 'Logic has made me hated by the world!' So Peter Abelard thought and wrote to his former lover, the brilliant Heloise, in probably his last letter to her before his death in 1142, after having been virtually driven from Paris by Bernard of Clairvaux, the austere Cistercian mystic and perhaps the most powerful ecclesiastical politician of Western Europe.1 Characteristically for Abelard in matters of self-conception, he was exaggerating. Logic had made him hated not by the world but by only a portion of it. While this was certainly an influential portion and one that had almost succeeded in destroying him, it could never do so entirely. In fact, logic had made Abelard 'the Socrates of the Gauls, the great Plato of the West, our Aristotle ... the prince of scholars'2- and this, this great fame and the almost unprecedented influence that accompanied it, was as much the problem as logic was. In a word, Abelard had been caught up in the politics of theology. The time was one of great theological inquiry, challenging, as it did, the very authority of divine revelation on the most fundamental level, and at a moment when both interest in secular learning and the number of students were dramatically increasing - all factors that can hardly be over-emphasized. But for certain elements within the Church, more still was at stake. And this was nothing less than a perceived assault on one of the basic underpinnings of the complex relationship between religion, theology, society and political power.
    [Show full text]
  • “It Has Been Well Said of Aristotle, 'Solet Aristoteles Quaerere Pugnam
    “It has been well said of Aristotle, ‘Solet Aristoteles quaerere pugnam’; ‘Aristotle has a habit of seeking a fight.’ He is seeking a fight not because he loves fight and enmity but because he loves peace and friendship; but true peace and friendship can only be found in the truth.” Leo Strauss1 “It will not be possible to conceal much longer from anybody the fact that St. Thomas Aquinas was one of the great liberators of the human intellect…. Thomas was a very great man who reconciled religion with reason, who expanded it towards experimental science, who insisted that the senses were the windows of the soul and that the reason had a divine right to feed upon facts, and that it was the business of the Faith to digest the strong meat of the toughest and most practical of pagan philosophies” G.K. Chesterton2 HONORS 3030: Humanities Colloquium Aristotle and Aquinas Spring 2013 Instructor: James Stoner Stubbs 240 (tel: 578-2538; e-mail: [email protected]) Office Hours: Mondays, 1:30-3:00 p.m., Wednesdays and Fridays, 9:00-10:00 a.m., and by appointment (call 578-2142) Course requirements: • Attendance at every class and participation in class discussion [15%] • Four 400-word essays on the reading, two on Aristotle, two on Aquinas [20%] • Two take-home exams, one each on Aristotle & Aquinas (Mar. 8 & Apr. 19) [30%] • Topic for final paper (due March 27) • Class presentation on final paper (during April) [5%] • Ten-page paper on modern-day Aristotelianism and/or Thomism, due Wednesday, May 8, 9:30 a.m.
    [Show full text]
  • Saint Bonaventure
    Saint Bonaventure and the Entrance of God Falque Into Theology Saint Bonaventure Saint Bonaventure by Emmanuel Falque and Saint Bonaventure and the Entrance of God Into Theology Into God of Entrance the and Bonaventure Saint translated from French by Brain Lapsa and Sarah Horton The Entrance of God Revised by William C. Hackett Into Theology Properly original, the new version of this essay intends both to nourish debate and differentiate points of view. In its new articulation, the book justifies work that has been carried out since. It justifies the sense of Franciscan rootedness that has never been denied and at the same time opens to the discovery of another reading of the Dominican Thomas Aquinas. The preface specially composed for this American edition, the opening debate with famous medievalist Etienne Gilson, and above all the afterword entitled “Saint Thomas Aquinas and the entrance of God into Philosophy” make it a radically new book. Emmanuel Falque, Professor and honorary dean of philosophy at the Institut Catholique de Paris (ICP), is a philosopher of religion whose research and writing focuses on patristic and medieval philosophy, phenomenology and philosophy of religion. A graduate of the University of Paris IV (Sorbonne), he received his license in Catholic theology summa cum laude from the Centre Sèvres, a university level Jesuit institution in Paris, in 1993, then returned to the Sorbonne to study with Jean-Luc Marion and earned a Ph.D. in philosophy summa cum laude in 1998 and the title of full Professor in 2006. He erved as the 2015 Tipton Visiting Professor in Catholic Studies at the University of California, Santa Barbara and held the Gadamer Visiting Professorship Chair in 2016 (Boston College).
    [Show full text]
  • Malebranche's Augustinianism and the Mind's Perfection
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations Spring 2010 Malebranche's Augustinianism and the Mind's Perfection Jason Skirry University of Pennsylvania, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations Part of the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Skirry, Jason, "Malebranche's Augustinianism and the Mind's Perfection" (2010). Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations. 179. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/179 This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/179 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Malebranche's Augustinianism and the Mind's Perfection Abstract This dissertation presents a unified interpretation of Malebranche’s philosophical system that is based on his Augustinian theory of the mind’s perfection, which consists in maximizing the mind’s ability to successfully access, comprehend, and follow God’s Order through practices that purify and cognitively enhance the mind’s attention. I argue that the mind’s perfection figures centrally in Malebranche’s philosophy and is the main hub that connects and reconciles the three fundamental principles of his system, namely, his occasionalism, divine illumination, and freedom. To demonstrate this, I first present, in chapter one, Malebranche’s philosophy within the historical and intellectual context of his membership in the French Oratory, arguing that the Oratory’s particular brand of Augustinianism, initiated by Cardinal Bérulle and propagated by Oratorians such as Andre Martin, is at the core of his philosophy and informs his theory of perfection. Next, in chapter two, I explicate Augustine’s own theory of perfection in order to provide an outline, and a basis of comparison, for Malebranche’s own theory of perfection.
    [Show full text]
  • MID-TWENTIETH CENTURY NEO-THOMIST APPROACHES to MODERN PSYCHOLOGY Dissertation Submitted to the College of Arts and Sciences Of
    MID-TWENTIETH CENTURY NEO-THOMIST APPROACHES TO MODERN PSYCHOLOGY Dissertation Submitted to The College of Arts and Sciences of the UNIVERSITY OF DAYTON In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for The Degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Theology By Matthew Glen Minix UNIVERSITY OF DAYTON Dayton, Ohio December 2016 MID-TWENTIETH CENTURY NEO-THOMIST APPROACHES TO MODERN PSYCHOLOGY Name: Minix, Matthew G. APPROVED BY: _____________________________________ Sandra A. Yocum, Ph.D. Dissertation Director _____________________________________ William L. Portier, Ph.D. Dissertation Reader. _____________________________________ Anthony Burke Smith, Ph.D. Dissertation Reader _____________________________________ John A. Inglis, Ph.D. Dissertation Reader _____________________________________ Jack J. Bauer, Ph.D. _____________________________________ Daniel Speed Thompson, Ph.D. Chair, Department of Religious Studies ii © Copyright by Matthew Glen Minix All rights reserved 2016 iii ABSTRACT MID-TWENTIETH CENTURY NEO-THOMIST APPROACHES TO MODERN PSYCHOLOGY Name: Minix, Matthew Glen University of Dayton Advisor: Dr. Sandra A. Yocum This dissertation considers a spectrum of five distinct approaches that mid-twentieth century neo-Thomist Catholic thinkers utilized when engaging with the tradition of modern scientific psychology: a critical approach, a reformulation approach, a synthetic approach, a particular [Jungian] approach, and a personalist approach. This work argues that mid-twentieth century neo-Thomists were essentially united in their concerns about the metaphysical principles of many modern psychologists as well as in their worries that these same modern psychologists had a tendency to overlook the transcendent dimension of human existence. This work shows that the first four neo-Thomist thinkers failed to bring the traditions of neo-Thomism and modern psychology together to the extent that they suggested purely theoretical ways of reconciling them.
    [Show full text]
  • Virtue Theory and the Present Evolution of Thorn Ism
    Virtue Theory and the Present Evolution of Thorn ism Romanus Cessario, O.P. Overthepastdecade,aquietrevolutionhasbeengatheringmomen­ tum in the fields of moral philosophy and Christian ethics. These disciplines are undergoing a decisive shift as duty, obligation, and decision yield their central role in the understanding of the moral life lo the long-neglected concepts of virtue, character, and action. 1 In the En­ glish-speaking world, Alasdair Macintyre remains the chief spokesman for the effort. It may interest some to learn that several years before he published After Virtue in 1981, the Faculty of the Dominican House of Studies in Washington, D. C., had decided to reinstate instruction in speculative moral theology, especially treating the matter of virtue theory. In the late 1960s, that is, shortly after the conciliar directive Optatam totius, No. 16, urged that the development of moral theology "should be nourished more thoroughly by scriptural teaching," such instruction had been dropped from the curriculum and replaced by courses such as the "Biblical Foundations of Morality." In some respects, we can credit British scholarship within the analytical tradition as providing the impetus toward a contemporary study of the virtues.2 Peter Geach, for instance, renders a complete account of classical virtue theory in his small book, The Virtues (Cam­ bridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977).3 In this work, the author 1. In The Moral Virtues and Theological Ethics (Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press, 1991), I provide an overview of the nature of the moral virtues, their relation to the intellectual virtues, the centrality of prudence in the moral life, and the structures of the acquisition and development of virtues.
    [Show full text]