Prospects for Post-Copernican Dogmatism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Prospects for Post-Copernican Dogmatism COLLAPSE V 1 2 Prospects for Post-Copernican 3 Dogmatism: The Antinomies of 4 Transcendental Naturalism 5 6 Iain Hamilton Grant 7 8 9 For it is not because there is thinking that there is being, but 10 rather because there is being that there is thinking. 11 1 Schelling 12 13 [T]he fundamental error of dogmatism [...][is to] search outside 14 the I in order to discover the ultimate ground of all that is in 15 and for the I. 16 2 Fichte 17 18 What is the dogmatism against which transcendental 19 philosophy launched its Copernican revolution? Since 20 Kant’s invention of the thing-in-itself, we are apt to think 21 3 dogmatism in terms of an access problem, and therefore 22 to conclude that any philosophy is dogmatic that, through 23 insufficient attention to its own conditioning, denies that 24 there is an access problem. Yet characterising dogmatism as 25 1. F.W.J. Schelling, Sämmtliche Werke, ed. K.F.A. Schelling, 14 vols (Stuttgart und 26 Augsburg: Cotta, 1856-61), vol. XIII, 161 n., trans. B. Matthews, The Grounding of 27 Positive Philosophy (New York: SUNY, 2007), 203 n. 28 2. J.G. Fichte (1971) J.G. Fichtes sämmtliche Werke (hereafter: W), ed. I.H. Fichte, 8 vols (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1971), vol. IV, 174, trs. D. Breazeale and G. Zöller, The 29 System of Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005), 165. 30 3. For an excellent recent account of the access problem, see Chapter One of Quentin 31 Meillassoux’s After Finitude (London: Continuum, 2008). 1 grant.indd 1 28/12/08 13:53:04 COLLAPSE V Grant – Post-Copernican Dogmatism 1 access-positivism does little to define it positively, providing Schelling’s claim above: it is a transcendental argument in 1 2 only a formal regression to inhibit speculative or rational that it stipulates what conditions the possibility of thinking 2 3 egress beyond reflection, as the Fichte citation above makes without reducing these conditions to any given or particular 3 4 sun-clear. Nevertheless, the Fichtean egress-prohibition has domain of objects. Hence Kant’s having noted, with regard 4 5 latterly been posited as a positive criterion of ‘philosophi- to Schelling’s System of Transcendental Idealism, that ‘tran- 5 6 cally effective’ transcendental arguments: scendental idealism is realism in an absolute sense’ (1993, 6 7 255). In accordance with this absolute realism, Schelling’s 7 The transcendental argument must not invalidly infer objective 8 thesis stems from his ontological naturalism:7 being is the 8 and or unrestricted conclusions from purely subjective and/or 9 necessary condition of thinking and not vice versa. 9 merely parochial premises.4 10 The point to note is that neither claim is inherently 10 11 Again, following Fichte, this criterion is expressly designed inconsistent, both are transcendental, and accordingly, that 11 12 to counter any claim to a ‘transcendental naturalism’, which transcendental positions are themselves open to counterpo- 12 13 comes close, as Bell claims, to an oxymoron.5 It follows sitions. Given this, in what follows, we shall argue that tran- 13 14 from the above criterion that the only valid transcenden- scendental philosophy is itself a dogmatism8 on the basis of 14 15 tal argument is one that demonstrates and asserts the the applicability of three criteria specified by transcendental 15 16 parochial subjectivism of its premises. What is striking is 16 17 17 that the double assertion of subjectivity and parochialism is what Kant sought by way of the ‘ether proofs’ in the Opus postumum, trans. by E. 18 asserted against the rest of being or nature. We must ask, Förster, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 62-99. Transcendental 18 19 philosophy is then defined as the ‘system of ideas, which are problematic (not 19 however, whether the Bell-Fichte subjective parochialism assertoric) in themselves […] but must nevertheless be thought as possible forces 20 thesis does in fact exhaustively define transcendentalism, affecting the rational subject’ (ibid., 250), necessitating a dynamica generalis (ibid., 224) 20 21 so that to reject the one is to dismiss the viability of the to ground both the system of objects and the system of ideas. 21 22 other, and thus to assert that there can be no other basis for 7. ‘Anything whose conditions simply cannot be given in nature, must be absolutely 22 impossible’ (Schelling, Werke III, 571). Although it could be argued that the ‘positive 23 transcendental philosophy. If this is so, transcendentalism’s philosophy’ of the Grounding is incompatible with the ‘negative philosophical’ theses 23 24 parochialism is as much the grounds for its rejection as for of the System of Transcendental Idealism, this would be to disguise the extent to which 24 Schelling’s naturalism is precisely the kind of ‘absolute realism’ with which Kant 25 its putative value. If not, we cannot conclude a transcen- identifies ‘transcendental idealism’. 25 26 6 26 dental naturalism to be oxymoronic. Consider for example 8. As indeed Fichte claims in the ‘Review of Anesidemus’: ‘the [Dogmatic] system holds 27 open the possibility that we might someday be able to go beyond the boundary of 27 the human mind, whereas the Critical system proves that such progress is absolutely 28 4. D. Bell, ‘Transcendental Arguments and Non-Naturalistic Anti-Realism’, in R. 28 impossible, and it shows that the thought of a thing possessing existence and specific Stern (ed.) Transcendental Arguments. Problems and Prospects (Oxford: Oxford University 29 properties in itself and apart from any faculty of representation is a piece of whimsy, 29 Press, 1999),189-210, at 192. 30 a pipe dream, a nonthought. And to this extent the Humean system is sceptical and 30 5. Ibid., 194. the Critical system is dogmatic – and indeed negatively so’ (W I, 16; Eng trans. by 31 D. Breazeale in Fichte: Early Philosophical Writings, Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 31 6. The prospect of a naturalistically grounded transcendental philosophy is precisely 1988, 70-71). 2 3 grant.indd 2-3 28/12/08 13:53:05 COLLAPSE V Grant – Post-Copernican Dogmatism 1 philosophers for the identification of dogmatism. These Since (3) can itself be construed as satisfying (2), it may 1 2 criteria are: be subsumed under it. Our point in its separate statement 2 3 is threefold. Firstly, to highlight the crucial role played 3 C.1 Logical: the susceptibility of dogmatic systems to 4 by ‘things’ not only in the determination of the nature 4 internally consistent but antinomic counter-systems.9 5 of dogmatism, as above, but also in the development of 5 6 C.2 Metaphysical: the attempt to provide a ground or cause transcendental philosophy’s ontology, for which the concept 6 7 of beings external to the I, or to satisfy the Principle of ‘thing-in-itself’ asserts only the most elementary determi- 7 8 Sufficient Reason;10 and nation of existents; but transcendental philosophy is itself 8 dogmatic when it concludes that therefore that they exist at 9 9 C.3 Ontological: the thesis that beings are things or all, and that this is how being is, as when, for instance, 10 10 objects.11 11 it asserts that ‘concepts of relation presuppose things 11 12 12 9. ‘[Reason, in] its dogmatic employment [...] lands us in dogmatic assertions to which are absolutely [schlechthin] given, and without these 13 which other assertions, equally specious, can always be opposed’ (Kant, Critique are impossible’.12 That is, the condition of possibility of 13 of Pure Reason, trans. N. Kemp Smith, London: Macmillan, 1958, B22-3; hereafter 14 14 CPR). ‘[I]n the dogmatic procedure of reason […] unavoidable contradictions of objects of intuition – even of their distinction – is simply 15 reason with itself have long since undermined the authority of every metaphysical ‘things absolutely given’. At this point, transcendental 15 system yet propounded’ (CPR: A10/B23-4). In ‘the dispute between the idealist and 16 16 the dogmatist […] reason gives us no principle of choice [… and n]either of these philosophy, whose ‘supreme concept […] is the division 17 two systems can directly refute its opposite’ (Fichte W I, 429-432; trans. by P. Heath into the possible and the impossible’, can avoid dogmatic 17 and J. Lachs, The Science of Knowledge, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982; 18 18 hereafter SK, 12-14). ontological commitment only at the cost of antithesis: 19 19 10. While metaphysics, ‘as science […] has to deal […] only with itself and the Thus the object of a concept to which no assignable intuition 20 20 problems which arise entirely from within itself, and which are imposed upon it by whatsoever corresponds is = nothing. That is, it is a concept 21 its own nature, not by the nature of things which are distinct from it’ (CPR: B23), 21 ‘dogmati[sm] claim[s] acquaintance with the constitution of the object fuller than that without an object (ens rationis), like noumena, which cannot be 22 22 of the counter-assertion’ (CPR: A388). See also Fichte W IV, 174; System of Ethics, trans. reckoned among the possibilities, although they must not for 23 and ed. by Daniel Breazeale and Günter Zöller (Cambridge: Cambridge University 23 Press, 2005), 165: ‘[T]he fundamental error of dogmatism [...][is to] search outside that reason be declared to be also impossible.13 24 the I in order to discover the ultimate ground of all that is in and for the I’. Wayne 24 25 Martin confirms this diagnosis in his Idealism and Objectivity: Understanding Fichte’s Jena 25 Project (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1997), 37: ‘dogmatists are not identified The ‘things absolutely given’ on which the objects of 26 simply as those who assert that things-in-themselves exist; rather they are those who intuition depend are neither possible nor impossible, and 26 27 assert that things in themselves constitute the ground of experience’.
Recommended publications
  • Schelling's Naturalism: Motion, Space, and the Volition of Thought
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Scholarship@Western Western University Scholarship@Western Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository 9-23-2015 12:00 AM Schelling's Naturalism: Motion, Space, and the Volition of Thought Ben Woodard The University of Western Ontario Supervisor Tilottama Rajan The University of Western Ontario Joint Supervisor Joan Steigerwald The University of Western Ontario Graduate Program in Theory and Criticism A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the equirr ements for the degree in Doctor of Philosophy © Ben Woodard 2015 Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/etd Part of the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Woodard, Ben, "Schelling's Naturalism: Motion, Space, and the Volition of Thought" (2015). Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository. 3314. https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/etd/3314 This Dissertation/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarship@Western. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository by an authorized administrator of Scholarship@Western. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Schelling's Naturalism: Motion, Space, and the Volition of Thought (Thesis Format: Monograph) by Benjamin Graham Woodard A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctorate of Philosophy in Theory and Criticism The School of Graduate and Postdoctoral Studies The University of Western Ontario London, Ontario, Canada © Ben Woodard 2015 Abstract: This dissertation examines F.W.J. von Schelling's Philosophy of Nature (or Naturphilosophie) as a form of early, and transcendentally expansive, naturalism that is, simultaneously, a naturalized transcendentalism.
    [Show full text]
  • Download (8Mb)
    A Thesis Submitted for the Degree of PhD at the University of Warwick Permanent WRAP URL: http://wrap.warwick.ac.uk/110900 Copyright and reuse: This thesis is made available online and is protected by original copyright. Please scroll down to view the document itself. Please refer to the repository record for this item for information to help you to cite it. Our policy information is available from the repository home page. For more information, please contact the WRAP Team at: [email protected] warwick.ac.uk/lib-publications THE BRITISH LIBRARY BRITISH THESIS SERVICE COPYRIGHT Reproduction of this thesis, other than as permitted under the United Kingdom Copyright Designs and Patents Act 1988, or under specific agreement with the copyright holder, is prohibited. This copy has been supplied on the understanding that it is copyright material and that no quotation from the thesis may be published without proper acknowledgement. REPRODUCTION QUALITY NOTICE Th e quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the original thesis. Whilst every effort has been made to ensure the highest quality of reproduction, some pages which contain small or poor printing may not reproduce well. Previously copyrighted material (journal articles, published texts etc.) is not reproduced. THIS THESIS HAS BEEN REPRODUCED EXACTLY AS RECEIVED FLATLINE CONSTRUCTS: GOTHIC MATERIALISM AND CYBERNETIC THEORY-FICTION Mark Fisher Presented for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of Warwick July 1999 Numerous Originals in Colour Abstract FLATLINE CONSTRUCTS: GOTHIC MATERIALISM AND CYBERNETIC THEORY- FICTION Cyberpunk fiction has been called “the supreme literary expression, if not of postmodernism then of late capitalism itself.” (Jameson) This thesis aims to analyse and question this claim by rethinking cyberpunk Action, postmodernism and late capitalism in terms of three - interlocking - themes: cybernetics, the Gothic and fiction.
    [Show full text]
  • Masses, Turbo-Capitalism and Power in Jean Baudrillard's Social
    International Journal of Theology, Philosophy and Science No. 3, Year 2/2018 MASSES, TURBO-CAPITALISM AND POWER IN JEAN BAUDRILLARD’S SOCIAL AND POLITICAL ONTOTHEOLOGY PhD. Prof. Spiros MAKRIS Assistant Professor in Political Theory University of Macedonia, Thessaloniki, GREECE Email: [email protected] ABSTRACT If postmodern Jean Baudrillard (1929-2007) could be defined as a theorist of power - to the extent that for some this is a contradiction by definition, although something very similar takes place in the case of Michel Foucault, he could be defined as a theorist of meta-power in the globalized era of turbo-capitalism. In his late texts (2005), which were published in 2010, the eminent French philosopher builds a provocative theory about power by using the classic concepts of domination and hegemony within the contemporary social, economic, political and ideological context of neoliberal globalization. In these papers, he analyzes in-depth the meta- power of hegemony in comparison with the power of domination. Actually, by signifying the critical passage of postwar capitalism from the phase of production to the phase of consumption, as Zygmunt Bauman does in his relevant work, Baudrillard formulates a meta-power theory as the equivalent of what he defines as turbo-capitalism. What is at stake is no longer the conventional issues of state sovereignty, Marx-inspired concept of alienation and Critical Theory-like negative dialectics but the crucial questions of hegemony, hostage and evilness. In short, Jean Baudrillard builds a new ontological and by extension disciplinary and theoretical field concerning global power, where the ‘Empire of Good’, or turbo-capitalism in his own terminology, is reborn in a totally catastrophic way (see simulation in the sense of a capitalist hypocrisy) either as an ‘Axis of Evil’ or as the ‘problem of terror’ (see simulacrum in the sense of a Lacanian stage of image within which turbo-capitalism represses, through a Freudian process of repelling, its unfamiliar self/i.e.
    [Show full text]
  • Language After Philosophy of Nature: Schelling’S Geology of Divine Names
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by University of Liverpool Repository LANGUAGE AFTER PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE: SCHELLING’S GEOLOGY OF DIVINE NAMES DANIEL WHISTLER Each mineral is a real philological problem.1 Future commentary on Dante belongs to the natural sciences… No one has yet approached Dante with a geologist’s hammer, in order to ascertain the crystalline structure of his rock, in order to study the particles of other minerals in it, to study its smoky colour, its garish patterning, to judge it as a mineral crystal which has been subjected to the most varied series of accidents.2 What happens to language after the post-linguistic turn? In what does a speculative approach to religion consist? Such are the two questions around which this essay is structured. It is not my purpose to give a comprehensive answer to either question; rather, I am concerned with one very specific approach that could be taken, and this is the approach of F.W.J. Schelling. Schelling has never been so relevant, and this is in no small part thanks to Iain Hamilton Grant’s Philosophies of Nature after Schelling. Grant’s work–part of the recent resurgence in speculative philosophies—has been instrumental in presenting Schelling’s Naturphilosophie as a viable pursuit for philosophy in the wake of Deleuze. This chapter is intended as a “regional application” of Grant’s presentation of Schelling onto philosophy of language and religion. It is important to stress straight-off that, while language and the numinous may well be two of the deconstructionist’s favourite tools for undermining theoretical discourse, this chapter has no such aim.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical Fundamentalism: on Taking
    1 THE NEW LITERALISM: READING AFTER GRANT’S SCHELLING Daniel Whistler (University of Liverpool) Abstract In the wake of post-hermeneutic refusals of interpretation in recent continental philosophy, this essay returns to Schelling as a means of understanding what such a renewed reading practice of philosophical fundamentalism might look like. I argue that recent impetus for a Schellingian conception of literalism can be found in Grant’s attack on the metaphorising tendencies of previous Schelling scholarship, and the ground for such literalism is to be located in the concept of tautegory that Schelling proposes in the Lectures on the Philosophy of Mythology. Schelling is a philosopher of form, and the form of the word remains as inviolable as any other natural form. 2 1. The post-hermeneutic era in continental philosophy is grounded in a refusal to accept the vocation of the philosopher as interpreter, passing on old texts while uncovering new meanings.1 Many philosophers in the continental tradition now see themselves embarking on a constructive, speculative voyage into the new.2 In this essay, I contend that this post-hermeneutic age is to be defined by a renewed literalism. It is a Schellingian age in which one must read tautegorically. This is an argument that ultimately concerns difference and repetition – specifically, the various modalities of difference and repetition at play in critical re- readings of philosophy. At the centre of this essay is an interrogation of the hermeneutic contention that “we understand in a different way, if we understand at all”3, and the prejudice this exposes, widespread in philosophy, for the disposability and mutability of form.
    [Show full text]
  • The Speculative Turn Continental Materialism and Realism
    The Speculative Turn Continental Materialism and Realism Edited by Levi Bryant, Nick Srnicek and Graham Harman Open Access Statement – Please Read This book is Open Access. This work is not simply an electronic book; it is the open access version of a work that exists in a number of forms, the traditional printed form being one of them. Copyright Notice This work is ‘Open Access’, published under a creative commons license which means that you are free to copy, distribute, display, and perform the work as long as you clearly attribute the work to the authors, that you do not use this work for any commercial gain in any form and that you in no way alter, transform or build on the work outside of its use in normal aca- demic scholarship without express permission of the author and the publisher of this volume. Furthermore, for any reuse or distribution, you must make clear to others the license terms of this work. For more information see the details of the creative commons licence at this website: http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/2.5/ This means that you can: • read and store this document free of charge • distribute it for personal use free of charge • print sections of the work for personal use • read or perform parts of the work in a context where no financial transactions take place However, you cannot: • gain financially from the work in anyway • sell the work or seek monies in relation to the distribution of the work • use the work in any commercial activity of any kind • profit a third party indirectly via use or distribution
    [Show full text]
  • Symbolic Violence As Subtle Virulence: the Philosophy of Terrorism
    Beever Symbolic Violence as Subtle Virulence: The Philosophy of Terrorism Jonathan Beever Synopsis Jean Baudrillard’s semiotic analysis of violence leads us to understand the form of violence as three-fold: aggressive, historical, and semiotically virulent. Violence of the third form is the violence endemic to terrorism. If violence has been typically understood as of the first two types, terrorism should be understood as the virulence of simulacra. The conflation of these types of violence explains the failure of militaristic responses to terrorism. This paper will explore Baudrillard’s conception of symbolic violence as the virulence of signs and help us come to terms with the semiotic foundation of terrorism. Biography Jonathan Beever is a doctoral candidate in the Department of Philosophy at Purdue University. Jonathan works primarily in environmental and bio- ethics but also has interests in contemporary continental philosophy, political philosophy, and semiotics. He is the co-founder of the Purdue Lectures in Ethics, Policy, and Science . Essay The analysis of terrorism by contemporary French philosopher and cultural theorist Jean Baudrillard presents terrorism as the violence of empty representation - from symbolic representation to simulation. While well-known, 1 few scholars have focused on his analysis as not merely cultural but more specifically and interestingly semiotic . This focus gives us a way to better understand Baudrillard’s analysis and its implications post 9/11. In this presentation, I employ a semiotic framework to explore the contemporary problem of terrorism, outline three levels of violence, and distinguish these from terrorism. The goal of this analysis is to re-envision a not only political but also symbolic response to terror.
    [Show full text]
  • On an Ungrounded Earth: Towards a New Geophilosophy
    ON AN UNGROUNDED EARTH: TOWARDS A NEW GEOPHILOSOPHY ON AN UNGROUNDED EARTH TOWARDS A NEW GEOPHILOSOPHY Ben Woodard punctum books ✶ brooklyn, ny ON AN UNGROUNDED EARTH: TOWARDS A NEW GEOPHILOSOPHY © Ben Woodard, 2013. http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0 This work is Open Access, which means that you are free to copy, distribute, display, and perform the work as long as you clearly attribute the work to the authors, that you do not use this work for commercial gain in any form whatsoever, and that you in no way alter, transform, or build upon the work outside of its normal use in academic scholarship without express permission of the author and the publisher of this volume. For any reuse or distribution, you must make clear to others the license terms of this work. First published in 2013 by punctum books Brooklyn, New York http://punctumbooks.com ISBN-13: 978-0615785387 ISBN-10: 0615785387 Cover Image: computer fractalization of detail from Ernst Haeckel (1834-1919), Kunstform der Natur (1904), plate 70: organisms classified as Ophiodea. Facing-page drawing by Heather Masciandaro. Before you start to read this book, take this moment to think about making a donation to punctum books, an independent non-profit press, @ http://punctumbooks.com/about/ If you’re reading the e-book, you can click on the image below to go directly to our donations site. Any amount, no matter the size, is appreciated and will help us to keep our ship of fools afloat. Contributions from dedicated readers will also help us to keep our commons open and to cultivate new work that can’t find a welcoming port elsewhere.
    [Show full text]
  • The Reawakening of the Barbarian Principle
    CHAPTER ONE The Reawakening of the Barbarian Principle Jason M. Wirth φύσις κρύπτεσθαι φιλεῖ —Heraclitus (DK frag. 123)1 In what follows, I would like to speak both to our motivation for this collection of essays and then to the character of the essays themselves. I In his provocative essay in Signs on Husserl and the problem of non-philosophy and non-phenomenology, “The Philosopher and His Shadow,” Merleau-Ponty takes up the question of what eludes philosophy but which cannot nonetheless be dismissed from philosophy. “What resists phenomenology within us—natural being, the ‘barbarian’ source Schelling spoke of—cannot remain outside phenomenology and should have its place within it. The philosopher must bear his shadow, which is not simply the factual absence of future light” (S2, 178).2 In the working notes to the Visible and the Invisible, Merleau-Ponty proposes a “psychoanalysis of Nature” that takes up the question of the “ever new” and “always the same” in Nature, that is, “the barbarian principle” (VI2, 267), that which haunts the face of Nature. 3 © 2013 State University of New York Press, Albany 4 Jason M. Wirth Let us be clear: To take up the project of a psychoanalysis of Nature is to enter into an analytic relationship with the ψυχή of Nature, but that in turn assumes that Nature is both whole (Nature as such is thinkable) and animated. In a sense, it asks that we reengage the anima mundi of the Ancients, Nature as a living creature, animated by its ψυχή or anima. Otherwise, what is there to psychoanalyze? At the same time, the sensibilities that have largely governed Western (and increasingly global) thinking for the past four centuries would find such a project absurd.
    [Show full text]
  • The Root of Heidegger's Concern for the Earth At
    Cosmos and History: The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy, vol. 17, no. 1, 2021 NEGATIVITY AND THE IDEOLOGY OF EXISTENCE: THINKING FUTURES THROUGH EXTINCTION Virgilio Rivas ABSTRACT: In her Deleuzian forays into the paradox of immanent life, Claire Colebrook (2014) takes issue with a theory of vitalism that interprets life as an organic, self-sustaining whole. Colebrook proposes a variation of the Deleuzian theory based on a concept of life involving instead a complicated orientation toward life potentials that are, in fact, non-self-maintaining to the extent that they approach the eternal, the beyond-human, beyond the anthropocentrism of organized natures and bodies. Meanwhile, the idea of an extainment set that I.H. Grant (2013) advanced in his annotation of Schelling’s Naturphilosophie echoes a similar Deleuzian inflection as to the counter-intuitive challenge to a life-sustaining world, the notion of inexistent nature. Nature’s extainment is impervious to reason and the time-systems that modern rationality has forged to supersede nature’s deep unprethinkable past. This oblique correspondence between a particular strand of Deleuzianism and the extaining principle intrinsic to Schelling’s philosophy reveals a shared critique of Hegel’s approach towards the notion of 'externality' that has characterized the mono-vitalism of critical theory today. At stake in this criticism of vitalism is the future of thinking a world other than its potentials to sustain a human-rationalized system, an ordered system of economic telos that Schelling warned about in the early 18th century in light of the tendencies of Kant’s Copernican turn. The essay concludes with Andrew Culp’s main formulation in Dark Deleuze, concerning the death of the World, which systematically recapitulates this paper's discussions concerning a) ‘the organism has no future but a mindless futurality’ (following Colebrook’s Deleuzianism) and b) the notion of 'inexistent nature' (sketched out by Grant).
    [Show full text]
  • The Root of Heidegger's Concern for the Earth At
    Cosmos and History: The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy, vol. 9, no. 2, 2013 “PHYSICS OF THE IDEA” AN INTERVIEW WITH IAIN HAMILTON GRANT (2013) Leon Niemoczynski and Iain Hamilton Grant ABSTRACT: This is an interview with the philosopher Iain Hamilton Grant, author of Idealism: The history of a philosophy (Acumen, 2011) and Philosophies of Nature After Schelling (Continuum, 2008). KEYWORDS: Speculative Philosophy; Realism; German Idealism; Schelling; Peirce; Hegel; Whitehead; Ray Brassier; Nature 1. Hi Iain, and thanks for agreeing to do this interview. Tell us, how did you get started in philosophy? What made you become a philosopher? Two things got me started: art and material. Before I discovered that limitations of talent and technique made this improbable, I was attempting to be a performance artist, a sculptor and a musician and had therefore enrolled on a BA Fine Art at Reading University. During this time, I was working on a series of figures, in various media (copperplate, charcoal, silk-screen and acrylics), derived from headlamp-glare on the rain-soaked windscreen that absorbed my attention on a ten hour night-time bus journey from London to Edinburgh. The figure formed by light and rain on a moving screen reconstructed these physical elements as if constructing a four dimensional account of the dynamics of Kandinsky’s and Malevich’s most abstract compositions. This was the first move toward philosophy: abstraction and actuality are identical. The second had more to do with the material, and stemmed from working in metal. The physical hardness of metal is an alterable state, so that in www.cosmosandhistory.org 32 LEON NIEMOCZYNSKI AND IAIN HAMILTON GRANT 33 welding, it becomes liquid or can be drawn through with an electrical arc with less resistance than paper exerts on charcoal, was my Platonic moment, such that matter, the “darkest of all things”, revealed its capacity to become at the expense of its apparent solidity, its secure three-dimensional massiveness.
    [Show full text]
  • Gilles Deleuze and the Genesis of Real Experience
    Gilles Deleuze and the Genesis of Real Experience Mitchell Harper This thesis is submitted to the School of Humanities and Languages at the University of New South Wales in fulfilment of the requirements of a PhD in Philosophy School of Humanities and Languages Faculty of Arts and Social Sciences June 2018 Thesis/Dissertation Sheet Surname/Family Name : Harper Given Name/s : Mitchell Eden Abbreviation for degree as give in the University calendar : PhD Faculty : Arts and Social Sciences School : Humanities and Languages Thesis Title : Gilles Deleuze and the Genesis of Real Experience Abstract 350 words maximum: (PLEASE TYPE) This thesis investigates Deleuze’s genetic account of real experience in Difference and Repetition (hereafter DR) as a systematic form of metaphysics. While there is broad agreement on the aims of DR as a thesis in metaphysics, there is significant disparity in accounts of how this is accomplished. The overall goal of this thesis is to examine and clarify the processes involved in Deleuze’s metaphysical account of genesis in DR (the three syntheses of time and space, differentiation, individuation, differenciation, and dramatisation), how these processes involve a metaphysics of difference (intensive quantity), how they form a system (the relationship between the virtual, the actual, and the intensive), and how this has been understood in the secondary scholarship. Chapter 1 examines Deleuze’s reading of Kantian critique for two reasons. Firstly, it outlines Kant’s account of the conditioning of possible experience in order to provide a framework from which to understand how Deleuze radically transforms transcendental philosophy. Secondly, it critically examines Deleuze’s reading of Kant’s genetic account of real experience in order to outline its philosophical limitations.
    [Show full text]