The Specter of Fascism: Defining the “F-Word”

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Specter of Fascism: Defining the “F-Word” Trevor Erlacher Te Specter of Fascism: Defning the “F-Word” In one sense—a moral sense—there could hardly be more agreement today on the subject of fascism as a general, interwar European political phenomenon.1 Liberals, conservatives, and socialists all concur on the immorality of fascism. Of all its conventional varieties, German National Socialism in particular has come to epitomize our notion of malevolence, serving as a guidepost to righteous certitude in an otherwise postmodern world of doubt, ambiguity, and fruitless debate. American theologian Reinhold Niebuhr, for example, used Nazism as the cornerstone of his infuential postwar doctrine of Christian Realism. Nazism has also provided a common point of reference for the most hackneyed arguments against ethical relativism. traces Indeed, Nazism’s present-day status as evil par excellence has led to an unfortunate proliferation of the so-called reductio ad Hitlerum in daily conversation, political rhetoric, and Internet forums.2 All of the other putative varieties of 1 Fascism, that is, with a little ‘f,’ to distinguish it from its Italian namesake. 2 This phenomenon is summed up in Godwin’s Law, formulated by American attorney Mike Godwin, partly in jest, to state that as a given “online discussion grows longer, the probability of a comparison involving Hitler or the Nazis approaches 1.” The result, Godwin argues, is a trivialization of the Holocaust. See Andrew McFarlane, (2010-07-14). “Is it ever OK to call someone a Nazi?”. BBC News Magazine. http://www.bbc.co.uk/ news/10618638. Retrieved 2011-05-01. 244 Trevor Erlacher fascism—including the original, Italian Fascism (which we typically regard, despite its chronological priority and extreme brutality, as an entirely more benign, even humorous, junior partner)3—derive the better part of their historical guilt from association with the apogee (or nadir) of fascism in the Tird Reich. Yet, this moral certitude does not extend to the academic debate about what fascism, as a political genus, is. It also remains unclear whether we can legitimately categorize National Socialism under “fascism.” Only Italian Fascism, due to its name, is invariably designated as fascist, and even in this case scholars have argued that Nazism actually represented the more “fascistic” of the two.4 Te following discussion is typical insofar as it considers only the cases of Italian Fascism and Nazism. Other potential fascisms—the Hungarian Arrow Cross, the Romanian Iron Guard, the Croatian Ustasha, Peronist Argentina, Showa Japan, and the Organization of Ukrainian Nationalists, to name just a few—inspire far less agreement about classifcation and rarely enter treatises on fascism’s defnition until afer it has been established on the basis of the Italian and, usually, the German exemplars. A clear and concise defnition of fascism is needed, but a real consensus on what that might entail has yet to emerge. Is fascism an ideology, a collection of movements and regimes, or both? Is it lefwing, rightwing, or “radical centrist”? Is fascism confned to the interwar period? Is a resurgence of it still possible, and if so, how do we know it when we see it? Tis paper presents a brief critical survey of some of the most prominent attempts to solve these defnitional conundrums.5 Approaches to defning generic fascism can be divided into four categories, all of which are problematic for diferent reasons and motivated by diferent concerns. Te frst is the Marxist approach, which takes fascism to be a symptom of late capitalism’s desperate struggle against the working class. Te second will be referred to as the ideological approach, which intellectual historians starting with Ernst 3 R. J. B. Bosworth, Mussolini (Londen: Hodder Education, 2005), 35. 4 This position is implied by Paxton’s five-stage program of fascist development, since Nazi Germany alone reached the fifth stage and “experienced full radicalization,” whereas Italian Fascism habitually lapsed into mere “military dictatorship.” Robert Paxton, The Anatomy of Fascism (New York: Vintage, 2005), 23, 150. 5 More specifically, it will evaluate the arguments of Stanley G. Payne, Robert O. Paxton, George L. Mosse, Roger Griffin, Ernst Nolte, Zeev Sternhell, Gilbert Allardyce, Roger Eatwell, Geoff Eley, and Martin Kitchen. 245 The UNC-Chapel Hill Journal of History Nolte have typically favored. Te third is the functionalist (or structuralist) approach, which attempts to understand fascism “in time” as the sum total of its deeds in specifc contexts rather than its ideas and rhetoric. Te fourth, or nominalist, approach argues for a rejection of the other three as logically fawed, philosophically unjustifable, and detrimental to the study of history. Te latter position represents the most rational, modest, and easily defensible of the four, although its acceptance entails a renunciation of the purported heuristic, didactic, and political advantages of an umbrella concept to incorporate all ostensible instances of “fascism.” Te Bestiary: A Typology of Typologies I. Te Marxist Approach Self-identifed Marxists of diferent stripes made the frst attempts to understand fascism analytically as a generic breed of politics shortly afer its appearance in the early 1920s. Nevertheless, prior to Hitler’s rise to power, many of them remained skeptical about the potential for fascism to take root anywhere other than Italy. Writing in 1928, Italian Communist Palmiro Togliatti expressed his belief that Fascism could not be exported to other countries, because of the degree to which the economic and class relations peculiar to Italy determined its existence: “A movement of the ‘fascist’ type, like the one in Italy, would have the greatest difculty in conquering power elsewhere.”6 Antonio Gramsci proposed a similar, Sonderweg-like explanation of Italy’s descent into fascism, arguing that the Risorgimento was a “missed revolution” that had burdened the country with a tortured social and political development thereafer.7 In his 1944 pamphlet, Fascism: What It Is and How to Fight It, Leon Trotsky argued that fascism was a reactionary mass movement of the petty bourgeoisie under the aegis of the capitalist class—their true enemies—against a bewildered and disorganized proletariat. Trotsky did not, however, regard fascism as an inevitable outcome of the crisis of capitalism. Instead, he argued for its latency in any capitalist society, holding the Communist Party’s incompetence, complacency, and cowardice responsible for fascism’s rise to power in Italy 6 Palmiro Togliatti, “On the Question of Fascism,” in Aristotle A. Kallis, ed., The Fascism Reader (New York: Routledge, 2003), 109. 7 Antonio Gramsci, Selections from Prison (New York: Weidenfled and Nicolson, 1971). 246 Trevor Erlacher and Germany.8 More sophisticated Marxist interpretations of fascism have appeared since, though the list-making method of defnition has retained its appeal. Martin Kitchen, for example, has posited ten distinguishing marks of fascism, each with a decidedly economistic favor.9 On the basis of these criteria, Kitchen efectively limits fascism to Germany and Italy, while insisting that many other places came close to ftting his defnition, and that refusing to recognize fascism as a possibility in the postwar context “would make it impossible to analyze fascist dangers in the present day.”10 Writing in the 1970s, Kitchen warned of the likelihood, given the economic problems at the time, of a resurgent “neo-fascism” in capitalist countries. Te tactical value of the term “fascism” as a general concept for use in Cold War-era socialist politics thus constituted Kitchen’s principal justifcation for the adoption of his ten-point defnition. More recently, one of the most nuanced, nonpartisan, and self-critical statements of the problem from a Marxist perspective has been that of Geof Eley, who nevertheless retreats to the trite position that fascism was nothing other than the “counterrevolutionary” outgrowth of the interwar “crisis of capitalism” 8 Leon Trotsky, Fascism: What It Is and How to Fight It (New York: Pathfinder, 1996). 9 They are as follows: 1) Fascism “is a phenomenon of developed industrial states”; 2) “fascist movements are triggered off by a severe socioeconomic crisis”; 3) “fascism is a response to a large and organized working class”; 4) it “recruits its mass following from a politicized, threatened, and frightened petite bourgeoisie”; 5) “fascist regimes are characterized by an alliance between the fascist party leadership and the traditional elites of industry, banking, the bureaucracy, and the military”; 6) fascism was intended to “stabilize, strengthen and, to a certain degree, transform capitalist property relationships and to ensure the social and economic domination of the capitalist class”; 7) “fascism is a terror regime which dispenses with all of the trappings of parliamentary democracy”; 8) “fascist movements use ideology deliberately to manipulate and divert the frustrations and anxieties of the mass following away from their objective source”; 9) “fascist regimes pursue aggressive expansionist foreign political aims”; and 10) fascism displays a “greater degree of intensity” in more developed societies. Martin Kitchen, Fascism (London and Basingstoke: Macmillan, 1976), 83-91. 10 Ibid. 247 The UNC-Chapel Hill Journal of History in countries with potent workers’ movements.11 Insofar as capitalism is still with us, therefore, fascistic movements and regimes could still appear wherever the prevailing economic order is challenged.12
Recommended publications
  • SOCS 648: EUROPE SINCE the FRENCH REVOLUTION Summer, 2014 Nathanael Greene [email protected] 860-685-2376
    GRADUATE LIBERAL STUDIES PROGRAM SOCS 648: EUROPE SINCE THE FRENCH REVOLUTION Summer, 2014 Nathanael Greene [email protected] 860-685-2376 BOOKS AVAILABLE AT THE BOOKSTORE: John Merriman A History of Modern Europe: VOL. II, From the French Revolution to the Present Eric Hobsbawm, The Age of Revolution Sheila Fitzpatrick, The Russian Revolution Robert Paxton, The Anatomy of Fascism Ian Kershaw, Hitler, 1936-1945 JUNE 30: INTRODUCTION AND THE FRENCH REVOLUTION, NAPOLEON, RESTORATION John Merriman, A History of Modern Europe, Volume II, From the French Revolution to the Present, chapters 13-15 OR, E. J. Hobsbawm, The Age of Revolution, chapters 1, 3, 4, 6, 12 and 13 and 4 • Documents: [on Moodle in your portfolio] • The Marseillaise • Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen • Robespierre’s Last Speech JULY 2: INDUSTRIALIZATION John Merriman, A History of Modern Europe, Volume II, From the French Revolution to the Present, chapters 16 and 20, OR, instead of Merriman’s chapter 16, E. J. Hobsbawm, The Age of Revolution, chapter 2 • Documents: • Taine, “Notes on England” • Ure, “The Philosophy of Manufacturers” • Dickens, Dombey And Son • “The 1834 Poor Law Report” GLSP SOCS 648 Summer, 2014 Page 2 • Coulson, “Child Labor in the Factories” • Chadwick, “The Sanitary Condition of the Laboring Population” • Wilson, “Chartism in Halifax” • Smiles, “Self Help” • Macaulay, “The 1832 Reform Bill” • Cobden, “Repeal of the Corn Laws” JULY 7: REVOLUTION, MASS POLITICS, NATIONAL UNIFICATION John Merriman, A History of Modern Europe, Volume
    [Show full text]
  • Communism That a Few Years Ago Was Unthinkable
    Norbert Frei and Dominik Rigoll, eds., Der Antikommunismus in seiner Epoche. Weltanschauung und Politik in Deutschland, Europa und den USA. Göttingen: Wallstein Verlag, 2017. 267 pages. ISBN 978-3-8353-3007-8 In the last few years, we have observed a growth of historiographic research on anti- communism that a few years ago was unthinkable. Arising from research into transnation- al anticommunist networks, the collection of essays here reviewed documents the results of a symposium held at the Jena Center 20th Century History and the Imre Kertész Kol- leg, which took place in November 2014.1 The fourteen papers, some written in German and some in English, are structured into three parts. They examine the genesis, the impact and the meaning of anticommunism as an ideological worldview in Germany, Europe and the United States. In the preface to the collection, one of its editors, Norbert Frei, says that the focus of the work is to explore how anticommunism became the common political denominator of certain institutions, individuals and political parties. What made anticommunism a popular lens with which to view so many political, social and cultural issues in the twentieth century? What linked and what distinguished the anti-Bolshevism that followed Russia’s 1917 revolution from Cold War anticommunism (p. 8)? The opening paper by Anselm Doering-Manteuffel is separate from the three parts of the book that follow it. The author discusses the stabilizing effect anticommunist mobi- lization had on its adherents, which stemmed from their fear of economic and political revolution. Doering-Manteuffel seeks to integrate the philosophy of anticommunism into the history of ideas.
    [Show full text]
  • Martin Heidegger on Humanism 8
    Alon Segev Thinking and Killing Alon Segev Thinking and Killing Philosophical Discourse in the Shadow of the Third Reich ISBN 978-1-61451-128-1 e-ISBN 978-1-61451-101-4 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data A CIP catalog record for this book has been applied for at the Library of Congress. Bibliografische Information der Deutschen Nationalbibliothek The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutschen Nationalbibliografie; detailed bibliographic data are available in the internet http://dnb.dnb.de. © 2013 Walter de Gruyter, Inc., Boston/Berlin Typesetting: Frank Benno Junghanns, Berlin Printing: Hubert & Co. GmbH & Co. KG, Göttingen ♾ Printed on acid-free paper Printed in Germany www.degruyter.com Foreword The motivation for writing this book began with my, one might say, naïve belief that critical thinking could have avoided the rise of the Third Reich and the Shoah in World War II. The main culprits were put on trial in Nuremberg, and then came the Eichmann trial in Jerusalem and the Auschwitz trials in Germany. Later on, the compliancy of Heidegger, Gadamer, and others with the Nazi regime was exposed by prominent scholars.1 Thus, the personal and public reputations of Heidegger, Jünger, Schmitt, Gadamer and others were destroyed and then partly rehabilitated. Their teaching, which was essential in consolidating and promulgating the Nazi world-view and in creating and designing the atmosphere of support for the Nazi movement, has, however, mostly remained untouched and continues to be uncritically studied and referred to. As Alain Finkielkraut writes: As Jankélévitch has rightly noted, the extermination of the Jews “was doctrinally founded, philosophically explained, methodically prepared by the most pedantic doctri- narians ever to have existed.” The Nazis were not, in effect, brutes, but theorists.
    [Show full text]
  • The Radical Roots of the Alt-Right
    Gale Primary Sources Start at the source. The Radical Roots of the Alt-Right Josh Vandiver Ball State University Various source media, Political Extremism and Radicalism in the Twentieth Century EMPOWER™ RESEARCH The radical political movement known as the Alt-Right Revolution, and Evolian Traditionalism – for an is, without question, a twenty-first century American audience. phenomenon.1 As the hipster-esque ‘alt’ prefix 3. A refined and intensified gender politics, a suggests, the movement aspires to offer a youthful form of ‘ultra-masculinism.’ alternative to conservatism or the Establishment Right, a clean break and a fresh start for the new century and .2 the Millennial and ‘Z’ generations While the first has long been a feature of American political life (albeit a highly marginal one), and the second has been paralleled elsewhere on the Unlike earlier radical right movements, the Alt-Right transnational right, together the three make for an operates natively within the political medium of late unusual fusion. modernity – cyberspace – because it emerged within that medium and has been continuously shaped by its ongoing development. This operational innovation will Seminal Alt-Right figures, such as Andrew Anglin,4 continue to have far-reaching and unpredictable Richard Spencer,5 and Greg Johnson,6 have been active effects, but researchers should take care to precisely for less than a decade. While none has continuously delineate the Alt-Right’s broader uniqueness. designated the movement as ‘Alt-Right’ (including Investigating the Alt-Right’s incipient ideology – the Spencer, who coined the term), each has consistently ferment of political discourses, images, and ideas with returned to it as demarcating the ideological territory which it seeks to define itself – one finds numerous they share.
    [Show full text]
  • Populism and Fascism
    Populism and Fascism An evaluation of their similarities and differences MA Thesis in Philosophy University of Amsterdam Graduate School of Humanities Titus Vreeke Student number: 10171169 Supervisor: Dr. Robin Celikates Date: 04-08-2017 1 Table of Contents Introduction ............................................................................................................................................... 3 1. Ideology ............................................................................................................................................. 8 1.1 Introduction ....................................................................................................................................... 8 1.2 Populism and fascism as ideologies ........................................................................................................ 9 1.3 The Dichotomies of Populism and Fascism ........................................................................................... 13 1.4 Culture and Nationalism in Populism and Fascism ............................................................................... 19 1.5 The Form of the State and its Role in Security ...................................................................................... 22 1.6 Conclusion ............................................................................................................................................. 25 2. Practice ...............................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • A Historiography of Fascism
    History in the Making Volume 6 Article 5 2013 A Historiography of Fascism Glenn-Iain Steinback CSUSB Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.lib.csusb.edu/history-in-the-making Part of the Political History Commons Recommended Citation Steinback, Glenn-Iain (2013) "A Historiography of Fascism," History in the Making: Vol. 6 , Article 5. Available at: https://scholarworks.lib.csusb.edu/history-in-the-making/vol6/iss1/5 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the History at CSUSB ScholarWorks. It has been accepted for inclusion in History in the Making by an authorized editor of CSUSB ScholarWorks. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Articles History Department’s 2013 Faculty Choice Award A Historiography of Fascism By Glenn-Iain Steinback Abstract: A long-standing historical debate revolves around the definition, fundamental nature and historical constraints of the concept of fascism. A wide array of scholarly questions about the political and ideological nature of fascism, the minimum or necessary traits of a fascist movement, arguments over the classification of semi-fascist groups and the concept of generic fascism characterize this debate. The result is a substantial body of scholarly research replete with competing theories for the evolution and origin of fascism as a concept, of individual fascist movements and even over the geographic and temporal application of the term itself within history. This paper is a historiography of fascist studies that illuminates the development of the scholarly narrative and understanding of fascism. Beginning with the historically contemporary Marxist perceptive of fascism, this paper examines competing and complimentary understandings of the phenomenon across the twentieth century, including various theories for the evolution of fascism in Europe, the relationship to and placement of fascism in the broader political spectrum, and the debate over fascism as a form of political religion.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction After Totalitarianism – Stalinism and Nazism Compared
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-89796-9 - Beyond Totalitarianism: Stalinism and Nazism Compared Michael Geyer and Sheila Fitzpatrick Excerpt More information 1 Introduction After Totalitarianism – Stalinism and Nazism Compared Michael Geyer with assistance from Sheila Fitzpatrick The idea of comparing Nazi Germany with the Soviet Union under Stalin is not a novel one. Notwithstanding some impressive efforts of late, however, the endeavor has achieved only limited success.1 Where comparisons have been made, the two histories seem to pass each other like trains in the night. That is, while there is some sense that they cross paths and, hence, share a time and place – if, indeed, it is not argued that they mimic each other in a deleterious war2 – little else seems to fit. And this is quite apart from those approaches which, on principle, deny any similarity because they consider Nazism and Stalinism to be at opposite ends of the political spectrum. Yet, despite the very real difficulties inherent in comparing the two regimes and an irreducible political resistance against such comparison, attempts to establish their commonalities have never ceased – not least as a result of the inclination to place both regimes in opposition to Western, “liberal” traditions. More often than not, comparison of Stalinism and Nazism worked by way of implicating a third party – the United States.3 Whatever the differences between them, they appeared small in comparison with the chasm that separated them from liberal-constitutional states and free societies. Since a three-way comparison 1 Alan Bullock, Hitler and Stalin: Parallel Lives (London: HarperCollins, 1991); Ian Kershaw and Moshe Lewin, eds., Stalinism and Nazism: Dictatorships in Comparison (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977); Henry Rousso, ed., Stalinisme et nazisme: Histoire et memoire´ comparees´ (Paris: Editions´ Complexe, 1999); English translation by Lucy Golvan et al., Stalinism and Nazism (Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 2004); Richard J.
    [Show full text]
  • (January 2002), No. 6 Julian Jackson, France: the Dark Years
    H-France Review Volume 2 (2002) Page 19 H-France Review Vol. 2 (January 2002), No. 6 Julian Jackson, France: The Dark Years, 1940-1944. Oxford New York: Oxford University Press, 2001. xix+660pp. Notes, maps, abbreviation tables and index. $35.00 ISBN 0-19-820706-9. Review by Robert Zaretsky, University of Houston. Nearly thirty years ago in Vichy France: Old Guard and New Order, 1940-1944, Robert Paxton revealed a regime driven by jumbled and frequently opposing ideological visions. There were fleeting, ragged projects advocated by corporatists and regionalists, traditionalists and technocrats, anti-Semites and personalists, Maurrasians and pacifists, syndicalists and fascists jostling one another for a space under the umbrella of the so-called Révolution nationale. Paxton made the damning case that Vichy’s leaders-- ranging from Pétain and Laval through Darlan and Flandin--actively pursued a policy of collaboration with Nazi Germany--an ambition as deluded as it was immoral. In addition to subverting the image of France so carefully burnished for more than 30 years by Vichy apologists, Paxton also undermined the claims that these four “dark years” represented a rupture or parenthesis in French history. Instead, he showed the continuities--administrative, ideological, political and social--that made Vichy a bridge between the late Third Republic and the postwar regimes. Since then, a vast amount of original work on Vichy has been done on both sides of the Atlantic. This research has now been brilliantly synthesized by Julian Jackson in France: The Dark Years, 1940-1944. This huge, exhilarating work reveals the undiminished strength of Paxton’s interpretation.
    [Show full text]
  • Jürgen Habermas and the Third Reich Max Schiller Claremont Mckenna College
    Claremont Colleges Scholarship @ Claremont CMC Senior Theses CMC Student Scholarship 2012 Jürgen Habermas and the Third Reich Max Schiller Claremont McKenna College Recommended Citation Schiller, Max, "Jürgen Habermas and the Third Reich" (2012). CMC Senior Theses. Paper 358. http://scholarship.claremont.edu/cmc_theses/358 This Open Access Senior Thesis is brought to you by Scholarship@Claremont. It has been accepted for inclusion in this collection by an authorized administrator. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Introduction The formation and subsequent actions of the Nazi government left a devastating and indelible impact on Europe and the world. In the midst of general technological and social progress that has occurred in Europe since the Enlightenment, the Nazis represent one of the greatest social regressions that has occurred in the modern world. Despite the development of a generally more humanitarian and socially progressive conditions in the western world over the past several hundred years, the Nazis instigated one of the most diabolic and genocidal programs known to man. And they did so using modern technologies in an expression of what historian Jeffrey Herf calls “reactionary modernism.” The idea, according to Herf is that, “Before and after the Nazi seizure of power, an important current within conservative and subsequently Nazi ideology was a reconciliation between the antimodernist, romantic, and irrantionalist ideas present in German nationalism and the most obvious manifestation of means ...modern technology.” 1 Nazi crimes were so extreme and barbaric precisely because they incorporated modern technologies into a process that violated modern ethical standards. Nazi crimes in the context of contemporary notions of ethics are almost inconceivable.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 3 the ISSUE of the HOLOCAUST AS a UNIQUE
    Chapter 3 THE ISSUE OF THE HOLOCAUST AS A UNIQUE EVENT by Alan Rosenberg and Evelyn Silverman The question of the "uniqueness" of the Holocaust If the Holocaust was a truly unique event, then it has itself become a unique question. When we approach lies beyond our comprehension. If it was not the Holocaust, we are at once confronted with a truly unique, then there is no unique lesson to be dilemma: if the Holocaust is the truly unique and learned from it. Viewed solely from the unprecedented historical event that it is often held to perspective of its uniqueness, the Holocaust must be, then it must exceed the possibility of human be considered either incomprehensible or trivial. comprehension, for it lies beyond the reach of our A contexualist analysis, on the other hand, finds customary historical and sociological means of inquiry that it was neither "extra historical" nor just and understanding. But if it is not a historically unique another atrocity. It is possible to view the event, if it is simply one more incident in the long Holocaust as unprecedented in many respects history of man's inhumanity to man, there is no special and as an event of critical and transformational point in trying to understand it, no unique lesson to importance in the history of our world. Using be learned. Yehuda Bauer states the problem from a this method, we can determine the ways in which somewhat different perspective: the uniqueness question both helps and hinders our quest for understanding of the Holocaust. If what happened to the Jews was unique, then it took place outside of history, it becomes a mysterious event, an upside-down miracle, so to speak, an event of religious significance in the sense that it is not man-made as that term is normally under­ stood.
    [Show full text]
  • Reading List for Comprehensive Examination in Political Theory
    READING LIST FOR COMPREHENSIVE EXAMINATION IN POLITICAL THEORY Department of Political Science Columbia University Requirements Majors should prepare for questions based on reading from the entire reading list. Minors should prepare for questions based on reading from the core list and any one of the satellite lists. CORE LIST Plato, The Republic Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics Books I, II, V, VIII, X; Politics Polybius, Rise of the Roman Empire, Book I paragraphs 1-10 (“Introduction”) and Book VI Cicero, The Republic Augustine, City of God, Books I, VIII (ch.s 4-11), XII, XIV, XIX, XXII (ch.s 23-24, 29-30) Aquinas, Summa Theologica, Questions 42, 66, 90-92, 94-97, 105 Niccolò Machiavelli, The Prince; Discourses (as selected in Selected Political Writings, ed. David Wootton) Jean Bodin, On Sovereignty (ed. Julian Franklin) Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan (as selected in Norton Critical Edition, ed. David Johnston) James Harrington, Oceana (Cambridge U. Press, ed. J.G.A. Pocock), pp. 63-70 (from Introduction), pp. 161-87; 413-19 John Locke, Second Treatise of Government; “A Letter Concerning Toleration” David Hume, “Of the Original Contract,” “The Independence of Parliament,” “That Politics May Be Reduced to A Science,” “Of the First Principle of Government,” “Of Parties in General” 1 Montesquieu, Spirit of the Laws (as selected in Selected Political Writings, ed. Melvin Richter) Adam Smith, The Theory of Moral Sentiments, Part I ("On the propriety of action"); Part II, Section II ("Of justice and beneficence"); Part IV ("On the effect of utility on the sentiment of approbation") Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Discourse on the Origins of Inequality; On The Social Contract Adam Smith, The Wealth of Nations (as selected in World’s Classics Edition, ed.
    [Show full text]
  • Modernity, Modernism, and Fascism. a "Mazeway Resynthesis"
    0RGHUQLW\PRGHUQLVPDQGIDVFLVP$PD]HZD\UHV\QWKHVLV 5RJHU*ULIILQ Modernism/modernity, Volume 15, Number 1, January 2008, pp. 9-24 (Article) 3XEOLVKHGE\-RKQV+RSNLQV8QLYHUVLW\3UHVV DOI: 10.1353/mod.2008.0011 For additional information about this article http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/mod/summary/v015/15.1griffin.html Access provided by Universitätsbibliothek Bern (1 Mar 2015 12:52 GMT) GRIFFIN / modernity, modernism, and fascism 9 Modernity, modernism, and fascism. A “mazeway resynthesis”1 Roger Griffin MODERNISM / modernity VOLUME FIFTEEN, NUMBER Fascism and modernism: finding the “big picture” ONE, PP 9–24. Researchers combing through back numbers of this journal © 2008 THE JOHNS HOPKINS in search of authoritative guidance to the relationship between UNIVERSITY PRESS modernity, modernism, and fascism could be forgiven for occa- sionally losing their bearings. In one of the earliest issues they will alight upon Emilio Gentile’s article tracing the paternity of early Fascism to the campaign for a “modernist national- ism” which was launched in the 1900s by Italian avant-garde artists and intellectuals fanatical about providing the catalyst to a national program of radical modernization.2 They will also come across the eloquent case made by Peter Fritzsche for the thesis that there was a distinctive “Nazi modern,” that the Third Roger Griffin is Reich embodied an extreme, uncompromising form of politi- Professor in Modern History at Oxford cal modernism, a ruthless bid to realize an alternative vision of Brookes University modernity whatever the human cost.3 But closer to the present (UK), and author of they will encounter Lutz Koepnik’s sustained argument that over 70 publications on the aesthetics of fascism reflected its aspiration “to subsume generic fascism, notably everything under the logic of a modern culture industry, hop- The Nature of Fascism ing to crush the emancipatory substance of modern life through (Pinter, 1991).
    [Show full text]