Analysis Uc of Scientism? Incapacities;" and SP: "Survey of Pragmatism," 11? in Coj/Ected of Charles Sanders Peirce, Ed

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Analysis Uc of Scientism? Incapacities; THE GREAT CONVERSATION A Historical Introduction to Philosophy Fourth Edition 2Iit",,_ 4'0" Norman Melchert ~JItjc I1}0'&; .'l0s Virginia Commonwealth University ~ &ctEt1"'C'/lq.t % y flii?e l?lJ Cb..o ~·69 lI.8. rt;OIq '8.) "~ALiSISII New York Oxford OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS For Richard, Clark, and Emmy Ray Oxford University Press Oxford New York Auckland Bangkok Buenos Aires Cape Town Chenna! Dar es Salaam Delhi Hong Kong Istanbul Karachi Kolkata Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Mumbai Nairobi Sao Paulo Shanghai Taipei Tokyo Toronto Cop)Tighl © 2002, 1999, 1995, 1991 by Oxford University Press, Inc. A Word to Instructors ix A Weird to Stu.;lents xi Published by Oxford University Press, IK Acknowledgments xv 198 Madison Avenue, New York. New York 10016 ",,",w.oup.com Chapter 1 Oxford is a registered trademark of Ox1:ord University Press Before Philosophy: Myth reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, in Hesiod and Homer 1 retrieval system, or transmitted, itl any form or by any means, Hesiod: War among the Gods ekctronic, mechanical, photocopying. recording. or otherwise, without the prior permission of Oxford University Press. Homer: Heroes, Gods, and Ex. Cove" The .\,haol ifA,lle", by Raphael, fresco, 1510-11, Papal Apartments, . the Vatican, Rome. Scala I Art Resource. Raphael represents philosophers and Chapter 2 scientists from various periods and places as though they were aU involved in Philosophy before Socrate: one great conversation. Thales: The One as Water 11 Tex:t and photo credits appear on page C·1. which constitutes a continuation of Anaximander: 'The One as the the ,"'pyright page. Xenophanes: The Gods as Ficti ISlIN·a 9780·19.·\17510.3 ISBN· 10, 0-19·517510·7 Profile: Pythagoras 16 Heraclitus: Oneness in the LOB' Parmenides: Only the One 24 Printing number: 9 8 7 6 5 4 ,) 2 1 Zeno: The Paradoxes of Comn Atomism: The One and Printed in the United States of America on acid~free paper the Many Reconciled 30 The Key: An AmbigUity 30 , . \ ~ The Pragmatists: Thought and ActIO'" ,uld We be naturalists? Are Notes Chapter Twenty-Two 1, References to the works of Charles Sanders Peirce lrohlem solving? are as follows: he quest for certainty? FB: "The Fixation of Belief;" HMIC: "How to cisms of empiricism? Of Make Our Ideas Clear;" WPI: "What !owledge? tism Is;" SCFI: "Some Consequences of Analysis uc of scientism? Incapacities;" and SP: "Survey of Pragmatism," 11? in CoJ/ected of Charles Sanders Peirce, ed. Logical Atomism and the Logical Positivists md chairs events with Charles and Paul Weiss, vol. 5 meaning, or arc there (Cambridge, MA: Harvard College, 1934). 2. Note added by Peirce in 1903 to "The Fixation due? How does of Belief,!' in Hartshorne and Weiss, Collected the valuable is not 232. len to like? 3. Epigraph (translated from the German) to W. V. O. between ends-in-view and Quine's Word and Object (New York: John Wiley les Dewey think that means and Sons, 1960). ,ted? 4. References to the works of John Dewey are as s rise to the peculiarly mod­ UCR, how does pragmatism FAE: "From Absolutism to Experimentalism," and roblem? And what role does NRP. "The Necd tor a Recovery of Philosophy," 1C resolution? in Dewey: On Nature, and Freedom. ed. Richard Bernstein (Indianapolis: Babbs-Merrill, NE OF TH£ MAJOR interests in twentieth­ merely fictions or illusions. Kant holds that we do 1960). century philosophy is language. At first not understand how words such as "substance" erThought !DP: "The Influence of Darwinism on Philosophy, O glance, this may seem puzzling, but a sec­ or "cause" or "I" actually work. Nietzsche thinks h urge fallibilism, giving up in lohn Dewey: The Middle Works (! 899-1924), ond look suggests that it is not so surprising. Our nearly all of traditional philosophy is a house of . Imagine that our culture 4, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale, IL: scientific theories, our religiOUS and philosophical cards built from misleading words. Peirce says his t would be the rcsult? Do Southern minois University Press, 1977). views, and our commonsense understandings are pragmatism is nothing but a doctrine of meaning ~O: The QEestJor Certainty: A Study cfthe Relation cf ;)c mostly good or aU expressed in language. Whenever we try to and explores the geography of the land of Knowledge and Action (1929; New York: G. P. communicate with someone about a matter of any Only in our century, however, does attention to Putnam's Sons, Capricorn Books, 1960). importance, it is language that carries the freight. language hecome a major preoccupation of philos­ we human ar!" with­ HWf: How We Think (Boston: D. C. Heath and Co., What if there were something mis]eadino about the ophers, both on the European continent and in the )f the natural world ex 1933). , - not thinking souls (Plato, EN: and Nature (New York: W. W. Nor­ language in which we think? What if it set traps Anglo-American world. The interest in language f oerceptions (Humc), nou­ ton and Co., 1929). for us, catapulted us into errors without our even has been so dominant that some speak of "the Iin­ World Spirit on its TV: cf Valuation (Chicago: University of Chi­ realizing it? Perhaps we ought not to trust it at aIL turn" in philosophy. Why should we cago Press, 1939). Actually, this suspicion is a sort of subtext run­ In this chapter and the next we examine two philosophical through modern philosophy. Descartes notes phases ofthis interest in language. These two phases we naturally say that we "see" men passing are often called ana!Ytic philosophy and ordinary ]an­ by, but the truth is we see only colors and shapes; ouaoc philosophy. Both are complex movements in­ we "judge" that these are men. So our language volving many thlnkers, and one could get a taste misleads us. Hobbes tells us that words are the of these styles of doing philosophy in a number of money of fools who think they can buy truth with ways. I have chosen to focus on one remarkable them, but that the wise are not deceived. One thinker, LudWig Wittgenstein, whom many would of the four books of Locke's Essays is titled "Of cite as one ofthe greatest philosophers of the twen­ Words." Berkeley claims we have misunderstood tieth century. He has had, and continues to have, a how general tenus work. Hume thinks that lan­ pervasive influence on philosophical thought. Sur­ guage deludes us into identifying as ideas what are nri.inalv he can stand as an emblem for both ofthese 605 Ludwig \Vittgensh'in: Traclotus LOflico-Philos(lphiCUS 607 606 Chapter Twenty-Two Analysis! Logical Atomism and the Logical Positivists the conviction tbat natural such as or- York" to be meaningful, there must be something field, from n""r,tinns In Wittgenstein's of mind and his English, does not in fact possess this sort that they name: Although definite can show us severe critique of his own earlier analytic thought, The language we normally speak is look like names, they actually have the which assertions are inconsistent with each other, we can see how attention to language in its ordi­ of vagueness, ambiguity, and confusion. [t ications. If we can get clear about lhe lOgiC and so on. Being formal in this sense, it sets out nary ernployment tends to supplant the earlier at­ is by no means what Russell calls "a logically we will clear up our confusion. a kind of logical skeleton that can be fleshed out in tradion to constructing an ideal language. Witt· perfect language." The second idea is the suspicion to Russell, to say, "The any number of ways, while preserving the logical genstein is also interesting because he is not that these tawdry features of our naturallanguae:es mountain does not exist," is equivalent to saying, relations precisely. interested in language -- or even just in tend to lead US astray, particularly when we "There exists no tiring that has both of these prop­ The pro''Pect opened up by the new logic is tional philosophical problems; his passionate con­ about philosophkal matters, which are always at erties: being and being a mountain." In that of a language more precise and clear than the cern from first to last is, How shall we lil'c? But first some conceptual distance from everyday talk "of the language formal logic, this is expressed as language we normally speak---a purified, ideal lan­ we need a little background, shoes and ships and wax, of cabbages and follows: -(3x)(Gx &.Mx). In this formula, it is auaae, in which there is no ambiguity, no vague­ kings." tal clear that the "G" (for golden) and the "M" ness, no dependence on emphasiS, intonation, or So the dazzling idea of applying the new logic mountain) are in the predicate position. There are, the many other features of our language that may to traditional philosophical problems takes root in in fact, no names in it at all--not even the occur­ mislead us and that are inessential for representing the imagination of many philosophers. PerhaDs. if rences of the letter "x." which function as vari­ Language and Its Logic the truth. Bertrand Russell expresses the appeal of We could formulate these problems in terms ables ranging over everything. In effect, the for­ such a language in this way: crystalline purity ofthese formal logical structures, mula invites you to consider each and every To understand analytic philosophy, In a logically perfect language the words in a prop­ they could finally-after all these centuries --be and assures you with respect to it;.
Recommended publications
  • A Companion to Analytic Philosophy
    A Companion to Analytic Philosophy Blackwell Companions to Philosophy This outstanding student reference series offers a comprehensive and authoritative survey of philosophy as a whole. Written by today’s leading philosophers, each volume provides lucid and engaging coverage of the key figures, terms, topics, and problems of the field. Taken together, the volumes provide the ideal basis for course use, represent- ing an unparalleled work of reference for students and specialists alike. Already published in the series 15. A Companion to Bioethics Edited by Helga Kuhse and Peter Singer 1. The Blackwell Companion to Philosophy Edited by Nicholas Bunnin and Eric 16. A Companion to the Philosophers Tsui-James Edited by Robert L. Arrington 2. A Companion to Ethics Edited by Peter Singer 17. A Companion to Business Ethics Edited by Robert E. Frederick 3. A Companion to Aesthetics Edited by David Cooper 18. A Companion to the Philosophy of 4. A Companion to Epistemology Science Edited by Jonathan Dancy and Ernest Sosa Edited by W. H. Newton-Smith 5. A Companion to Contemporary Political 19. A Companion to Environmental Philosophy Philosophy Edited by Robert E. Goodin and Philip Pettit Edited by Dale Jamieson 6. A Companion to Philosophy of Mind 20. A Companion to Analytic Philosophy Edited by Samuel Guttenplan Edited by A. P. Martinich and David Sosa 7. A Companion to Metaphysics Edited by Jaegwon Kim and Ernest Sosa Forthcoming 8. A Companion to Philosophy of Law and A Companion to Genethics Legal Theory Edited by John Harris and Justine Burley Edited by Dennis Patterson 9. A Companion to Philosophy of Religion A Companion to African-American Edited by Philip L.
    [Show full text]
  • " CONTENTS of VOLUME XXXVIII—1964 >•
    " CONTENTS OF VOLUME XXXVIII—1964 >• it ARTICLES: pAGE Anderson, James F., Was St. Thomas a Philosopher? 435 Boh, Ivan, An Examination of Some Proofs in Burleigh's Propo- sitional Logic 44 Brady, Jules M., St. Augustine's Theory of Seminal Reasons.. 141 Burns, J. Patout, Action in Suarez 453 Burrell, David B., Kant and Philosophical Knowledge 189 Chroust, Anton-Hermann, Some Reflections on the Origin of the Term " Philosopher " 423 Collins, James, The Work of Rudolf Allers 28 Fairbanks, Matthew J., C. S. Peirce and Logical Atomism 178 Grisez, Germain G., Sketch of a Future Metaphysics 310 O'Brien, Andrew J., Duns Scotus' Teaching on the Distinction between Essence and Existence 61 McWilliams, James A., The Concept as Villain 445 Pax, Clyde V., Philosophical Reflection: Gabriel Marcel 159 Smith, John E., The Relation of Thought and Being: Some Lessons from Hegel's Encyclopedia 22 Stokes, Walter E., Whitehead's Challenge to Theistic Realism. ... 1 Tallon, Andrew, Personal Immortality in Averroes' Tahafut Al- Tahafut 341 REVIEW ARTICLE : O'Neil, Charles J., Another Notable Study of Aristotle's Meta­ physics 509 ill iv Contents of Volume XXXVIII DEPARTMENTS : PAGE Book Brevities 551 Books Received 133, 274, 415, 557 Chronicles: The Husserl Archives and the Edition of Husserl's Works 473 International Congresses of Philosophy in Mexico City.. 278 Progress Report: Philosophy in the NCE 214 The Secretary's Chronicle 80, 218, 358, 483 BOOK REVIEWS: Anderson, James P., Natural Theology: The Metaphysics of God 265 Austin, J. L., Philosophical Papers 125 Capek, Milec, The Philosophical Impact of Contemporary Physics 248 Caturelli, Alberto, La fdosofiu en Argentina actual 403 Crocker, Lester G., Nature and Cidture: Ethical Thought in the French Englightement 539 Dufrenne, Mikel, Language and Philosophy, transl.
    [Show full text]
  • Generalized Molecular Formulas in Logical Atomism
    Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy An Argument for Completely General Facts: Volume 9, Number 7 Generalized Molecular Formulas in Logical Editor in Chief Atomism Audrey Yap, University of Victoria Landon D. C. Elkind Editorial Board Annalisa Coliva, UC Irvine In his 1918 logical atomism lectures, Russell argued that there are Vera Flocke, Indiana University, Bloomington no molecular facts. But he posed a problem for anyone wanting Henry Jackman, York University to avoid molecular facts: we need truth-makers for generaliza- Frederique Janssen-Lauret, University of Manchester tions of molecular formulas, but such truth-makers seem to be Kevin C. Klement, University of Massachusetts both unavoidable and to have an abominably molecular charac- Consuelo Preti, The College of New Jersey ter. Call this the problem of generalized molecular formulas. I clarify Marcus Rossberg, University of Connecticut the problem here by distinguishing two kinds of generalized Anthony Skelton, Western University molecular formula: incompletely generalized molecular formulas Mark Textor, King’s College London and completely generalized molecular formulas. I next argue that, if empty worlds are logically possible, then the model-theoretic Editors for Special Issues and truth-functional considerations that are usually given ad- Sandra Lapointe, McMaster University dress the problem posed by the first kind of formula, but not the Alexander Klein, McMaster University problem posed by the second kind. I then show that Russell’s Review Editors commitments in 1918 provide an answer to the problem of com- Sean Morris, Metropolitan State University of Denver pletely generalized molecular formulas: some truth-makers will Sanford Shieh, Wesleyan University be non-atomic facts that have no constituents.
    [Show full text]
  • The Problem: the Theory of Ideas in Ancient Atomism and Gilles Deleuze
    Duquesne University Duquesne Scholarship Collection Electronic Theses and Dissertations 2013 The rP oblem: The Theory of Ideas in Ancient Atomism and Gilles Deleuze Ryan J. Johnson Follow this and additional works at: https://dsc.duq.edu/etd Recommended Citation Johnson, R. (2013). The rP oblem: The Theory of Ideas in Ancient Atomism and Gilles Deleuze (Doctoral dissertation, Duquesne University). Retrieved from https://dsc.duq.edu/etd/706 This Immediate Access is brought to you for free and open access by Duquesne Scholarship Collection. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Duquesne Scholarship Collection. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE PROBLEM: THE THEORY OF IDEAS IN ANCIENT ATOMISM AND GILLES DELEUZE A Dissertation Submitted to the McAnulty College & Graduate School of Liberal Arts Duquesne University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy By Ryan J. Johnson May 2014 Copyright by Ryan J. Johnson 2014 ii THE PROBLEM: THE THEORY OF IDEAS IN ANCIENT ATOMISM AND GILLES DELEUZE By Ryan J. Johnson Approved December 6, 2013 _______________________________ ______________________________ Daniel Selcer, Ph.D Kelly Arenson, Ph.D Associate Professor of Philosophy Assistant Professor of Philosophy (Committee Chair) (Committee Member) ______________________________ John Protevi, Ph.D Professor of Philosophy (Committee Member) ______________________________ ______________________________ James Swindal, Ph.D. Ronald Polansky, Ph.D. Dean, McAnulty College & Graduate Chair, Department of Philosophy School of Liberal Arts Professor of Philosophy Professor of Philosophy iii ABSTRACT THE PROBLEM: THE THEORY OF IDEAS IN ANCIENT ATOMISM AND GILLES DELEUZE By Ryan J. Johnson May 2014 Dissertation supervised by Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • 1. the Logical Atomism of Bertrand Russell Robert L
    Contemporary Civilization (Ideas and Institutions Section XXII: Philosophical Meaning of Western Man) 1958 1. The Logical Atomism of Bertrand Russell Robert L. Bloom Gettysburg College Basil L. Crapster Gettysburg College Harold L. Dunkelberger Gettysburg College See next page for additional authors Follow this and additional works at: https://cupola.gettysburg.edu/contemporary_sec22 Part of the History of Philosophy Commons Share feedback about the accessibility of this item. Bloom, Robert L. et al. "1. The Logical Atomism of Bertrand Russell. Pt. XXII: Philosophical Meaning." Ideas and Institutions of Western Man (Gettysburg College, 1958), 6-14. This is the publisher's version of the work. This publication appears in Gettysburg College's institutional repository by permission of the copyright owner for personal use, not for redistribution. Cupola permanent link: https://cupola.gettysburg.edu/ contemporary_sec22/2 This open access book chapter is brought to you by The uC pola: Scholarship at Gettysburg College. It has been accepted for inclusion by an authorized administrator of The uC pola. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 1. The Logical Atomism of Bertrand Russell Abstract As can easily be seen, the impact of these three schools of contemporary philosophy — the linguistic, the logical analytical, and the logical empiricist — has been largely negative, critical, and destructive, especially with regard to theological beliefs, metaphysical systems, and value judgment. Thus the particular growing edges of contemporary philosophy have contributed their full share to the shaking of the foundations of Western Civilization. But, during the last few decades they have presented less of a united front than before. The differences which have appeared have come largely from a rethinking of the status and role of value, and these differences have found expression in a large number of philosophers both in England and the United States.
    [Show full text]
  • Logical Atomism in Russell and Wittgenstein
    OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 04/15/11, SPi c h a p t e r 1 0 logical atomism in russell and wittgenstein i a n p r o o p s I n t r o d u c t i o n Russell and Wittgenstein develop diff erent, though closely related, versions of a posi- tion that has come to be known as ‘logical atomism’. Wittgenstein’s version is presented in the Tractatus , and discussed in the various pre-Tractatus manuscripts. Russell’s is pre- sented most fully in a set of eight lectures given in Gordon Square, London in early 1918. Th ese lectures, which are familiar to us today under the title ‘Th e Philosophy of Logical Atomism’ (Russell 1918/1956 : 175–281 , hereaft er ‘PLA’), were originally serialized in the Monist during the years 1918 and 1919. In them Russell attempts to synthesize his own ideas with those of Wittgenstein’s 1913 Notes on Logic . Although PLA is oft en treated as the defi nitive presentation of Russell’s logical atomism, we should not forget that Russell had already arrived at many elements of this doctrine before he encountered Wittgenstein. Th is earlier, pure Russellian, brand of logical atomism is fi rst set out in Russell’s 1911 article ‘Analytical Realism’ 1 —a text in which the phrase ‘logical atomism’ appears for the fi rst time. (See Monk 1996 , 200 .) It is further developed in certain chap- ters of the Problems of Philosophy of 1912. 2 Analytical realism, Russell explains, is a form of atomism because it maintains—in contrast to the British Hegelianism of Bradley, McTaggart, Joachim, and others,3 fi rst, 1 Th is work was composed in the summer of 1911, and so before Russell’s fi rst encounter with Wittgenstein.
    [Show full text]
  • Redalyc.LANGUAGE AS PICTURE in PLATO's CRATYLUS AND
    Tópicos, Revista de Filosofía ISSN: 0188-6649 [email protected] Universidad Panamericana México Mualem, Shlomy LANGUAGE AS PICTURE IN PLATO’S CRATYLUS AND WITTGENSTEIN’S TRACTATUS Tópicos, Revista de Filosofía, núm. 33, 2007, pp. 9-35 Universidad Panamericana Distrito Federal, México Available in: http://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=323028509001 How to cite Complete issue Scientific Information System More information about this article Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America, the Caribbean, Spain and Portugal Journal's homepage in redalyc.org Non-profit academic project, developed under the open access initiative i “shlomy” — 2008/10/6 — 21:25 — page 9 — #9 i i i LANGUAGE AS PICTURE IN PLATO’S CRATYLUS AND WITTGENSTEIN’S TRACTATUS Shlomy Mualem Bar Ilan University [email protected] Abstract The aim of the following article is to compare Plato and Wittgenstein’s doctrines of language as a picture, focusing on the Cratylus and the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Despite the fact that the Cratylus deals with the correct- ness of names while the Tractatus attends to the nature and structure of propo- sitions, the study demonstrates, focusing on Cratylus 421c-427e and Tractatus 4.01-4.12, that the language-as-picture doctrines in these texts closely resemble each other in terms of their basic properties and structures. The comparison comprises four aspects: (1) the structure of elements and their form; (2) the cor- respondence between language and reality; (3) the possibility of falsehood; and (4) the method of verification. Key words: philosophy of language, Picture Theory, Wittgenstein, Plato, analyti- cal philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • PHI 515-Wittgenstein
    Philosophy 515 Prof. Clare Batty Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logicus-Philosophicus 1. Historical Background 1872: Bertrand Russell born in Ravenscroft, Wales. 1889: Ludwig Wittgenstein born in Vienna, Austria. 1908: Wittgenstein begins studies in aeronautical engineering at Manchester University. Study philosophy of mathematics leads him to the work of Frege. 1911-1913: Wittgenstein studies with Russell at Cambridge. 1914: Russell delivers Our Knowledge of the External World as lectures at Harvard. 1914-1918: Wittgenstein spends World War I in the Austrian army. He writes the notes for Tractatus Logicus-Philosophicus while serving. 1918: Russell publishes The Philosophy of Logical Atomism. 1921: Wittgenstein’s Tractatus Logicus-Philosophicus published in German. 1922: Wittgentstein’s Tractatus translated into English. 1929: Wittgenstein returns to Cambridge after exposure to discussions of the Vienna Circle. (Books: Ludwig Wittgenstein and the Vienna Circle, The Blue and Brown Books, Philosophical Grammar) 1930-1940s: Wittgenstein delivers lectures at Cambridge. 1951: Wittgenstein dies. Last words: "Tell them I've had a wonderful life". 1970: Russell dies. 2. Facts 1 The world is everything that is the case. 1.1 The world is the totality of facts, not of things. What is Wittgenstein saying here? Well, he is not denying that there are things (as we shall be reminded of subsequently). Rather, what he is saying is that the totality of facts is something over and above the totality of things, and that a complete characterization of the world can be given in terms of the totality of facts. Facts? Facts are what make statements/sentences true or false. Consider the sentence ‘Socrates is wise’, and suppose that it is true.
    [Show full text]
  • Middle Wittgenstein" : from Logical Atomism to Practical Holism*
    er7, 812Are DAVID STERN THE "MIDDLE WITTGENSTEIN" : FROM LOGICAL ATOMISM TO PRACTICAL HOLISM* 1 . THE "MIDDLE WITTGENSTEIN" Wittgenstein arranged the Tractatus in its final form during the summer of 1918 ; Part I of the Philosophical Investigations was put into the form in which we now have it during the mid 1940s . The Tractatus was published in 1922; the Philosophical Investigations in 1953, two years after Wittgenstein's death . Because the two books were widely studied and interpreted at a time when the rest of his writing was unavailable, it became common practice to speak of the author of the first book as "Early Wittgenstein", and the author of the second as the "Late Wittgenstein" . As it gradually became clear that his writing during the intervening years was not only voluminous, but also could not simply be understood as a rejection of one view and the adoption of another, it was natural to speak of the author of this further body of writing, or at least those parts of it which could not be regarded as "Early", or "Late", as "Middle Wittgenstein" . While it is certainly convenient to use this talk of an early, middle and late Wittgenstein as conversational shorthand for lengthier and more cautious ways of discussing the development of his philosophy, it also has its dangers. One of the main assumptions which commonly accompanies this periodisation is the belief that we'can neatly divide the development of Wittgenstein's thought into several sharply demarcated phases. While there is some truth to this, it is only a half-truth, and for this reason it is particularly dangerous .
    [Show full text]
  • Russell's Relations, Wittgenstein's Objects, and the Theory of Types
    teorema Vol. XXXI/2, 2012, pp. 21-35 ISSN: 0210-1602 [BIBLID 0210-1602 (2012) 31:2; pp. 21-35] Russell’s Relations, Wittgenstein’s Objects, and the Theory of Types Giorgio Lando RESUMEN Discutimos aquí una semejanza –sobre la que no se ha hecho hincapié hasta ahora– entre la teoría de relaciones y predicados de The Philosophy of Logical Ato- mism [TPLA] de Russell y la teoría de los objetos y los nombres en el Tractatus Logi- co-Philosophicus [TLP] de Wittgenstein. Se detectan puntos de semejanza en tres niveles: en el de la ontología, en el de la sintaxis y en el de la semántica. Esta analogía explica las similitudes prima facie entre la presentación informal de la teoría de los ti- pos en TPLA y las secciones del TLP dedicadas al mismo tema. Eventualmente, ex- traemos algunas consecuencias que conciernen a ambos lados de la analogía: por lo que a Russell concierne, la pertienencia contextual de este sorprendente fragmento de la metafísica y la semántica tractariana es cuestionada en base a distintos fundamen- tos. Por lo que respecta a Wittgenstein, los intérpretes que no identifican los objetos tractarianos con particulares están en una posición mejor para dotar de sentido la ana- logía aquí descubierta. PALABRAS CLAVE: relaciones, teoría de tipos, Russell, Wittgenstein, Tractatus, ato- mismo lógico, principio del contexto. ABSTRACT We discuss a previously unnoticed resemblance between the theory of relations and predicates in The Philosophy of Logical Atomism [TPLA] by Russell and the theory of objects and names in the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus [TLP] by Wittgenstein.
    [Show full text]
  • Russellms Logical Atomism 1914P1918: Epistemological
    Russell’sLogical Atomism 1914–1918: Epistemological Ontology and Logical Form Nino B. Cocchiarella May 23, 2017 Abstract Logical analysis, according to Bertrand Russell, leads to and ends with logical atomism, an ontology of atomic facts that is epistemologi- cally founded on sense-data, which Russell claimed are mind-independent physical objects. We …rst explain how Russell’s 1914–1918 epistemolog- ical version of logical atomism is to be understood, and then, because constructing logical forms is a fundamental part of the process of logical analysis, we brie‡y look at what has happened to Russell’s type theory in this ontology. We then turn to the problem of explaining whether or not the logical forms of Russell’s new logic can explain both the forms of atomic facts and yet also the sentences of natural language, especially those about beliefs. The main problem is to explain the logical forms for belief and desire sentences and how those forms do not correspond to the logical forms of the facts of logical atomism. According to Bertrand Russell all “philosophy is logic,”by which he meant that “every philosophical problem, when it is subjected to the necessary analysis and puri…cation, is found either to be not really philosophical, or else to be, in the sense in which we are using the word, logical” (OKEW, 42). By necessary analysis Russell meant logical analysis, i.e., formally breaking up a complex whole into its separate parts or constituents, and then explaining the way the parts are held together in terms of a logical form (OKEW, 52).
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction
    Notes Introduction 1 . Bataille talks of an ‘abyss’ ( 1986 , p. 80); Ryle ( 1971b , p. 182) and Dummett ( 1993 , p. xi) talks of a ‘gulf’. 2 . See Reynolds & Chase, 2011 , pp. 254–255. 3 . A recent survey of the field is given in Floyd, 2009 ; see also Beaney, 1998 ; Preston, 2005 . 4 . See esp. Sluga, 1998 ; Stroll, 2000 ; Glock, 2008 ; Monk, 1996a . See also Hylton, 1990 ; Hacker, 2007 ; Glendinning, 2006 ; Preston, 2007 ; Floyd, 2009 , p. 173. 5 . See e.g. Stroll, 2000 ; Glock, 2008 . See also Reynolds and Chase, 2010 ; Reynolds et al., 2010 . 6 . An early variant of this view is proposed by Urmson (1992 ), who divides the history of philosophical analysis into four types: (i) ‘classical’ analysis (Russell), (ii) ideal-language analysis (early Wittgenstein, Vienna Circle, Quine, Goodman), (iii) ‘therapeutic positivist’ (p. 299) analysis (later Wittgenstein, Ryle, Wisdom, Waismann), and (iv) ‘ordinary language’ analysis (Austin). Weitz ( 1966 ) similarly comments that ‘it has become established practice in anthologies and histories of twentieth century philosophy to divide its analytic parts into (a) Realism, (b) Logical Analysis or Logical Atomism, (c) Logical Positivism, and (d) Linguistic, Ordinary Language, or Conceptual Analysis’ (p. 1). Russell ( 1959 , p. 216) talked of three waves in British philosophy 1914–1959, Wittgenstein’s Tractatus , Logical Positivism, and the later Wittgenstein. More recently, Hacker ( 1996 , pp. 4–5; 2007 ) proposed a similar understanding of analytic philosophy as a series of phases in the history of philosophy, rather than defining it as either a set of necessary and sufficient conditions or as a family resem- blance concept. Whereas Urmson emphasises the ‘decisive break’ (1960 , p.
    [Show full text]